23 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Jeffry L. Ramsey [21]Jeffry Ramsey [2]
  1.  69
    Molecular shape, reduction, explanation and approximate concepts.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1997 - Synthese 111 (3):233-251.
  2.  77
    Construction by reduction.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (1):1-20.
    Scientists employ a variety of procedures to eliminate degrees of freedom from computationally and/or analytically intractable equations. In the process, they often construct new models and discover new concepts, laws and functional relations. I argue these procedures embody a central notion of reduction, namely, the containment of one structure within another. However, their inclusion in the philosophical concept of reduction necessitates a reevaluation of many standard assumptions about the ontological, epistemological and functional features of a reduction. On the basis of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  3.  90
    Mechanisms and their explanatory challenges in organic chemistry.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2008 - Philosophy of Science 75 (5):970-982.
    Chemists take mechanisms to be an important way of explaining chemical change. I examine the usefulness of the mechanism approach in the recent philosophical literature in explicating the explanatory use of mechanisms by organic chemists. I argue that chemists consider a mechanism to be explanatory because it accounts for the “dynamic process of bringing about” (Tabery 2004 , 10) chemical change. For chemists, mechanisms are causal explanations based on interventions that show “how some possibilities depend on others” (Woodward 2003 , (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  4.  25
    Towards an Expanded Epistemology for Approximations.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1992 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992:154 - 164.
    By stressing the act rather than the relation of approximation, I argue that the magnitude of the error introduced should not be used as the sole criterion for judging the worth of the approximation. Magnitude is a necessary but not sufficient condition for such a judgement. Controllability, the absence of cancelling errors, and the approximation's justification are also important criteria to consider when praising or blaming an approximation. Boltzmann's discussion of the types of approximations used in the kinetic theory of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  5.  56
    Calibrating and constructing models of protein folding.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2007 - Synthese 155 (3):307-320.
    Prediction is more than testing established theory by examining whether the prediction matches the data. To show this, I examine the practices of a community of scientists, known as threaders, who are attempting to predict the final, folded structure of a protein from its primary structure, i.e., its amino acid sequence. These scientists employ a careful and deliberate methodology of prediction. A key feature of the methodology is calibration. They calibrate in order to construct better models. The construction leads to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  6.  28
    Between the fundamental and the phenomenological: The challenge of 'semi-empirical' methods.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):627-653.
    Philosophers disagree how abstract, theoretical principles can be applied to instances. This paper generates a puzzle for law theorists, causal theorists and inductivists alike. Intractability can force scientists to use a "semi-empirical" method, in which some of an equation's theoretically-determinable parameters are replaced with values taken directly from the data. This is not a purely deductive or inductive process, nor does it involve causes and capacities in any simple way (Humphreys 1995). I argue the predictive successes of such methods require (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7.  37
    Realism, Essentialism, and Intrinsic Properties.Jeffry L. Ramsey & Rosenfeld Bhushan - 2000 - In Nalini Bhushan & Stuart Rosenfeld (eds.), Of Minds and Molecules: New Philosophical Perspectives on Chemistry. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 117.
  8.  36
    Of parameters and principles: Producing theory in twentieth century physics and chemistry.Jeffry Ramsey - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 31 (4):549-567.
  9.  10
    Of Parameters and Principles: Producing Theory in Twentieth Century Physics and Chemistry.Jeffry Ramsey - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 31 (4):549-567.
  10.  17
    Beyond Numerical and Causal Accuracy: Expanding the Set of Justificational Criteria.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:485 - 499.
    I argue that numerical and causal accuracy arguments can be successful only if: (1) the theories in use are known to be true, (2) computational difficulties do not exist, and (3) the experimental data are stable and resolved. When any one or more of these assumptions are not satisfied, additional justificational considerations must be invoked. I illustrate the need for range of validity and intelligibility claims with examples drawn from chemical kinetics. My arguments suggest that the realist and anti-realist accounts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  32
    When reduction leads to construction: Design considerations in scientific methodology.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1993 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 (3):241 – 253.
    Abstract Philosophers have paid little attention to the kind of reduction involved in transforming an analytically intractable equation into solvable form. I argue that this practice is important because it involves the design of a basic level theory for use in a specific domain. The design process can lead to the construction of a new theory. As a result of my analysis, theory design emerges as an important category of analysis for scientific methodology. Similarities between design in technology and science (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  84
    On Not Defining Sustainability.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2015 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 28 (6):1075-1087.
    Definitions of sustainability—and criticisms of the definitions—abound. I argue that there are problems with the definitional approach itself and not just with any specific definition. Wittgenstein. Macmillan Publishing Company, New York, 1958) argued that definitions are not sufficient to determine meaning or to legislate correct usage of words. For both singular terms and general concepts, meaning is meaning-as-use, proceeding via examples that instruct within an already existing normative structure. Once we are clear on the ways in which use presupposes a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  54
    Defining Sustainability.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2014 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 27 (6):1049-1054.
    Heather M. Farley and Zachary A. Smith, Sustainability: If It’s Everything, Is It Nothing? xiv + 176 pp., index. New York: Routledge, 2014. $39.95 Leslie Paul Thiele, Sustainability. viii + 234 p., bibl., index. New York: Polity Press, 2013. $22.95 The authors of both of these books offer new definitions of sustainability. They do so in order to battle “faux interpretations” or “hypocritical” or “unsupported endorsements” of sustainability. While I think many people, including I expect many readers of this journal, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  27
    Ideal Reaction Types and the Reactions of Real Alloys.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1994 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994:149 - 159.
    Research on the oxidation of alloys supports the claim that natural scientists can and do use ideal type concepts when confronted with analytical or computational intractability. In opposition to those who collapse ideal types into 'standard' theoretical concepts, I argue ideal types possess a unique structure, function and axiology. In phenomenologically complex situations, scientists use these features to articulate experiment with theory generally and in particular to discover new boundary conditions. This conceptual articulation is achieved using models rather than objective (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  25
    On refusing to be an epistemologically black box: Instruments in chemical kinetics during the 1920s and '30s.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 23 (2):283-304.
  16.  11
    Beyond Numerical and Causal Accuracy: Expanding the Set of Justificational Criteria.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (1):485-499.
    Until recently, realists and anti-realists alike have assumed that any approximations which appear in explanations and confirmations in the mathematically oriented physical and biological sciences are “mere distractions” (Laymon 1989, p. 353). When approximation techniques must be used, they are typically justified by appeals to their numerical accuracy. However, recent interest in computational complexity in the sciences has revealed that numerical accuracy is not always the only criterion which should be invoked to justify the use of approximations. Cartwright (1983), Franklin (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  46
    Hume and Same‐Sex Marriage.Jeffry L. Ramsey & Olivia O'Connor - 2017 - Journal of Social Philosophy 48 (2):180-196.
  18.  44
    Hegel's philosophy of nature.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2001 - Foundations of Chemistry 3 (3):263-268.
  19.  10
    Recent Work in the History and Philosophy of Chemistry.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 1998 - Perspectives on Science 6 (4):409-427.
  20.  34
    Straining to explain strain and synthesis.Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2004 - Foundations of Chemistry 6 (1):81-91.
  21.  49
    Joachim Schummer, realismus und chemie: Philosophische untersuchungen der wissenschaft Von den stoffen. [REVIEW]Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2000 - Foundations of Chemistry 2 (1):79-84.
  22.  40
    P.j.T. Morris and O.t. Benfey (eds.): Robert Burns Woodward: Architect and artist in the world of molecules (history of modern chemical sciences series). [REVIEW]Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2003 - Foundations of Chemistry 5 (2):175-178.
  23.  27
    U. Klein (ed.): Tools and modes of representation in the laboratory sciences. [REVIEW]Jeffry L. Ramsey - 2003 - Foundations of Chemistry 5 (1):93-97.