123 found
Order:
Disambiguations
James G. Lennox [95]James Lennox [22]J. Lennox [4]John Lennox [2]
James Gordon Lennox [1]Jg Lennox [1]John C. Lennox [1]
See also
  1.  15
    Aristotle's philosophy of biology: studies in the origins of life science.James G. Lennox - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    In addition to being one of the world's most influential philosophers, Aristotle can also be credited with the creation of both the science of biology and the philosophy of biology. He was the first thinker to treat the investigations of the living world as a distinct inquiry with its own special concepts and principles. This book focuses on a seminal event in the history of biology - Aristotle's delineation of a special branch of theoretical knowledge devoted to the systematic investigation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  2. Darwin was a teleologist.James G. Lennox - 1993 - Biology and Philosophy 8 (4):409-421.
    It is often claimed that one of Darwin''s chief accomplishments was to provide biology with a non-teleological explanation of adaptation. A number of Darwin''s closest associates, however, and Darwin himself, did not see it that way. In order to assess whether Darwin''s version of evolutionary theory does or does not employ teleological explanation, two of his botanical studies are examined. The result of this examination is that Darwin sees selection explanations of adaptations as teleological explanations. The confusion in the nineteenth (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  3.  75
    Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology.Allan Gotthelf & James G. Lennox (eds.) - 1987 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle's biological works - constituting over 25% of his surviving corpus and for centuries largely unstudied by philosophically oriented scholars - have been the subject of an increasing amount of attention of late. This collection brings together some of the best work that has been done in this area, with the aim of exhibiting the contribution that close study of these treatises can make to the understanding of Aristotle's philosophy. The book is divided into four parts, each with an introduction (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  4. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science.James G. Lennox - 2001 - Journal of the History of Biology 36 (1):223-224.
  5.  20
    Self-Motion: From Aristotle to Newton.Mary Louise Gill & James G. Lennox (eds.) - 2017 - Princeton University Press.
    The concept of self-motion is not only fundamental in Aristotle's argument for the Prime Mover and in ancient and medieval theories of nature, but it is also central to many theories of human agency and moral responsibility. In this collection of mostly new essays, scholars of classical, Hellenistic, medieval, and early modern philosophy and science explore the question of whether or not there are such things as self-movers, and if so, what their self-motion consists in. They trace the development of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  6. Aristotle on the Unity of the Nutritive and Reproductive Functions.Cameron F. Coates & James G. Lennox - 2020 - Phronesis 65 (4):414-466.
    In De Anima 2.4, Aristotle claims that nutritive soul encompasses two distinct biological functions: nutrition and reproduction. We challenge a pervasive interpretation which posits ‘nutrients’ as the correlative object of the nutritive capacity. Instead, the shared object of nutrition and reproduction is that which is nourished and reproduced: the ensouled body, qua ensouled. Both functions aim at preserving this object, and thus at preserving the form, life, and being of the individual organism. In each case, we show how Aristotle’s detailed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7.  12
    Aristotle on Inquiry: Erotetic Frameworks and Domain Specific Norms.James G. Lennox - 2020 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle is a rarity in the history of philosophy and science - he is a towering figure in the history of both disciplines. Moreover, he devoted a great deal of philosophical attention to the nature of scientific knowledge. How then do his philosophical reflections on scientific knowledge impact his actual scientific inquiries? In this book James Lennox sets out to answer this question. He argues that Aristotle has a richly normative view of scientific inquiry, and that those norms are of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  8.  33
    Introduction to the Philosophy of Science.Merrilee H. Salmon, John Earman, Clark Glymour & James G. Lennox (eds.) - 1992 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    A reprint of the Prentice-Hall edition of 1992. Prepared by nine distinguished philosophers and historians of science, this thoughtful reader represents a cooperative effort to provide an introduction to the philosophy of science focused on cultivating an understanding of both the workings of science and its historical and social context. Selections range from discussions of topics in general methodology to a sampling of foundational problems in various physical, biological, behavioral, and social sciences. Each chapter contains a list of suggested readings (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  9.  84
    Natural selection and the struggle for existence.James G. Lennox & Bradley E. Wilson - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (1):65-80.
  10. Health as an objective value.James G. Lennox - 1995 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 20 (5):499-511.
    Variants on two approaches to the concept of health have dominated the philosophy of medicine, here referred to as ‘reductionist’ and ‘relativis’. These two approaches share the basic assumption that the concept of health cannot be both based on an empirical biological foundation and be evaluative, and thus adopt either the view that it is ‘objective’ or evaluative. It is here argued that there are a subset of value concepts that are formed in recognition of certain fundamental facts about living (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  11.  17
    Introduction.James G. Lennox & Mary Louise Gill - 2017 - In Mary Louise Gill & James G. Lennox (eds.), Self-Motion: From Aristotle to Newton. Princeton University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  72
    Aristotle on genera, species, and?the more and the less?James G. Lennox - 1980 - Journal of the History of Biology 13 (2):321-346.
  13. Aristotelian Problems.James G. Lennox - 1994 - Ancient Philosophy 14 (S1):53-77.
  14. Aristotle on the Emergence of Material Complexity: Meteorology IV and Aristotle’s Biology.James G. Lennox - 2014 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4 (2):272-305.
    In this article I defend an account of Meteorology IV as providing a material-level causal account of the emergence of uniform materials with a wide range of dispositional properties not found at the level of the four elements—the emergence of material complexity. I then demonstrate that this causal account is used in the Generation of Animals and Parts of Animals as part of the explanation of the generation of the uniform parts (tissues) and of their role in providing nonuniform parts (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15.  43
    History and philosophy of science: A phylogenetic approach.James G. Lennox - unknown
    Kuhn closed the Introduction to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions with what was clearly intended as a rhetorical question: How could history of science fail to be a source of phenomena to which theories about knowledge may legitimately be asked to apply? (Kuhn 1970, 9) This paper argues that there is a more fruitful way of conceiving the relationship between a historical and philosophical study of science, which is dubbed the 'phylogenetic' approach. I sketch an example of this approach, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  16.  84
    The darwin/gray correspondence 1857–1869: An intelligent discussion about chance and design.James G. Lennox - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (4):456-479.
    This essay outlines one aspect of a larger collaboration with John Beatty and Alan Love.2 The project’s focus is philosophical, but for reasons that will become clear momentarily, the method of approach is historical. All three of us share the conviction that philosophical issues concerning the foundations of the sciences are often illuminated by investigating their history. It is my hope that this paper both provides support for that thesis, and illustrates it. The focal philosophical issue can be stated in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  17. Between data and demonstration: The Analytics and the Historia Animalium.James G. Lennox - 1991 - In Alan C. Bowen (ed.), Science and Philosophy in Classical Greece. Garland. pp. 2--61.
  18. Aristotle on Norms of Inquiry.James G. Lennox - 2011 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (1):23-46.
    Where does Aristotle stand in the debate between rationalism and empiricism? The locus classicus on this question, Posterior Analytics II. 19, seems clearly empiricist. Yet many commentators have resisted this conclusion. Here, I review their arguments and conclude that they rest in part on expectations for this text that go unfulfilled. I argue that this is because his views about norms of empirical inquiry are in the rich methodological passages in his scientific treatises. In support of this claim, I explore (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  19.  11
    Concepts and Their Role in Knowledge: Reflections on Objectivist Epistemology.Allan Gotthelf & James G. Lennox (eds.) - 2013 - Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
    The philosopher and novelist Ayn Rand is a cultural phenomenon. Her books have sold more than twenty-eight million copies, and countless individuals speak of her writings as having significantly influenced their lives. Despite her popularity, Rand’s philosophy of Objectivism has received little serious attention from academic philosophers. _Concepts and Their Role in Knowledge_ offers scholarly analysis of key elements of Ayn Rand’s radically new approach to epistemology. The four essays, by contributors intimately familiar with this area of her work, discuss (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20. Plato's Unnatural Teleology.James Lennox - 1985 - In Dominic J. O'Meara (ed.), Platonic Investigations. Catholic University of Amer Press. pp. 195-218.
  21.  76
    Darwin’s Methodological Evolution.James G. Lennox - 2005 - Journal of the History of Biology 38 (1):85-99.
    A necessary condition for having a revolution named after you is that you are an innovator in your field. I argue that if Charles Darwin meets this condition, it is as a philosopher and methodologist. In 1991, I made the case for Darwin's innovative use of "thought experiment" in the "Origin." Here I place this innovative practice in the context of Darwin's methodological commitments, trace its origins back into Darwin's notebooks, and pursue Darwin's suggestion that it owes its inspiration to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  22. Aristotle on Chance.James G. Lennox - 1984 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 66 (1):52-60.
  23. Bios and Explanatory Unity in Aristotle's Biology.James Lennox - 2010 - In David Charles (ed.), Definition in Greek Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24.  37
    “As if we were investigating snubness”: Aristotle on the prospects for a single science of nature,'.J. Lennox - 2008 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 35:149-186.
  25.  7
    Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox (ed.) - 2002 - Clarendon Press.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help in understanding (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26.  81
    Aristotle's biology.James Lennox - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Aristotle is properly recognized as the originator of the scientific study of life. This is true despite the fact that many earlier Greek natural philosophers occasionally speculated on the origins of living things and much of the Hippocratic medical corpus, which was written before or during Aristotle's lifetime, displays a serious interest in human anatomy, physiology and pathology. Even Plato has Timaeus devote a considerable part of his speech to the human body and its functions (and malfunctions). Nevertheless, before Aristotle, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27.  49
    Darwinism.James Lennox - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Darwinism designates a distinctive form of evolutionary explanation for the history and diversity of life on earth. Its original formulation is provided in the first edition of On the Origin of Species in 1859. This entry first formulates ‘Darwin's Darwinism’ in terms of five philosophically distinctive themes: (i) probability and chance, (ii) the nature, power and scope of selection, (iii) adaptation and teleology, (iv) nominalism vs. essentialism about species and (v) the tempo and mode of evolutionary change. Both Darwin and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  28. Teleology, chance, and Aristotle's theory of spontaneous generation.James G. Lennox - 1982 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (3):219-238.
  29. An Aristotelian Philosophy of Biology: Form, Function and Development.James G. Lennox - 2017 - Acta Philosophica 26 (1):33-52.
    In metaphysics and philosophy of science, a significant movement is making inroads, under the banner of ‘neo-Aristotelianism’. This movement has so far been focused primarily on the physical sciences; but given that Aristotle the natural scientist was above all a biologist, it is worth asking what a neo-Aristotelian philosophy of biology would look like? In this paper, I begin a discussion on precisely that question. One interesting result is that the fact that biology is now permeated by evolutionary ways of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (213):607-609.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help in understanding (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  31.  40
    Aristotle's De Motu Animalium: Text with Translation, Commentary and Interpretive Essays.James G. Lennox - 1980 - Philosophy of Science 47 (1):156-159.
  32.  17
    Concepts, Theories, and Rationality in the Biological Sciences.Gereon Wolters & James G. Lennox (eds.) - 1995 - Pittsburgh P.A./Konstanz, Germany: University of Pittsburgh Press/Universitätsverlag Konstanz.
    Leading biologists and philosophers of biology discuss the basic theories and concepts of biology and their connections with ethics, economics, and psychology, providing a remarkably unified report on the “state of the art” in the philosophy of biology.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  78
    Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf.James G. Lennox & Robert Bolton (eds.) - 2010 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This volume of essays explores major connected themes in Aristotle's metaphysics, philosophy of nature, and ethics, especially themes related to essence, definition, teleology, activity, potentiality, and the highest good. The volume is united by the belief that all aspects of Aristotle's work need to be studied together if any one of the areas of thought is to be fully understood. Many of the papers were contributions to a conference at the University of Pittsburgh entitled 'Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle', (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34. La fonction biologique: phylogénie d'un concept.J. Lennox - 2010 - In Jean Gayon & Armand de Ricqlès (eds.), Les Fonctions: Des Organismes aux Artefacts. Presses Universitaires de France. pp. 17--42.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  23
    Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox (ed.) - 2002 - Clarendon Press.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help in understanding (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  18
    Getting a Science Going: Aristotle on Entry Level Kinds'.James G. Lennox - 2005 - In Gereon Wolters & Martin Carrier (eds.), Homo Sapiens Und Homo Faber. De Gruyter. pp. 87.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37. Philosophy of biology.James G. Lennox - 1992 - In Merrilee H. Salmon (ed.), Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Hackett. pp. 269--309.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  38.  10
    Robert Boyle's Defense of Teleological Inference in Experimental Science.James Lennox - 1983 - Isis 74:38-52.
  39.  21
    Robert Boyle's Defense of Teleological Inference in Experimental Science.James G. Lennox - 1983 - Isis 74 (1):38-52.
  40. The Comparative Study of Animal Development: William Harvey's Aristotelianism.”.James G. Lennox - 2006 - In Justin E. H. Smith (ed.), The Problem of Animal Generation in Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 21--46.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  20
    De caelo 2.2 and Its Debt to De incessu animalium.James G. Lennox - 2009 - In A. C. Bowen & C. Wildberg (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle’s de Caelo. Brill. pp. 1--187.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  19
    From the Method of Division to the Theory of Transformations: Thompson After Aristotle, and Aristotle After Thompson.Laura Nuño de la Rosa & James G. Lennox - forthcoming - Biological Theory:1-16.
    Aristotle’s influence on D’Arcy Thompson was praised by Thompson himself and has been recognized by others in various respects, including the aesthetic and normative dimensions of biology, and the multicausal explanation of living forms. This article focuses on the relatedness of organic forms, one of the core problems addressed by both Aristotle’s History of Animals (HA), and the renowned chapter of Thompson’s On Growth and Form (G&F), “On the Theory of Transformations, or the Comparison of Related Forms.” We contend that, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  28
    Most Natural Among the Functions of Living Things.James G. Lennox - 2020 - In Giouli Korobili & Roberto Lo Presti (eds.), Nutrition and Nutritive Soul in Aristotle and Aristotelianism. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 1-20.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Episteme, demonstration, and explanation: A fresh look at Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics.Gregory Salmieri, David Bronstein, David Charles & James G. Lennox - 2014 - Metascience 23 (1):1-35.
  45. 'As if we were investigating snubness': Aristotle on the Prospects for a Single Science of Nature.James G. Lennox - 2008 - In Brad Inwood (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxxv: Winter 2008. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  50
    The complexity of Aristotle's study of animals.James G. Lennox - 2012 - In Christopher Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oup Usa. pp. 287.
    Aristotle is the first person in the history of science to see the study of nature as an articulated complex of interrelated, yet somewhat autonomous, investigations. Understanding why goes to the heart of what is philosophically distinctive about him. Why does Aristotle present the investigation of “the common cause of animal motion” as distinct and independent from a study of the causes of the different forms of animal locomotion, the announced project of De incessu animalium? This article examines the puzzling (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Demarcating ancient science. A discussion of GER Lloyd, Science, Folklore and Ideology.James G. Lennox - 1985 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3:307-324.
  48.  64
    Putting Philosophy of Science to the Test: The Case of Aristotle's Biology.James G. Lennox - 1994 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994:239 - 247.
    During the Middle Ages and Rennaissance, it was commonly believed that Aristotle's biological studies reflected his theory of demonstrative science quite well. By contrast, most commentators in the twentieth century have taken it that this is not the case. This is largely the result of preconceptions about what a natural science modelled after the proposals of Aristotle's Posterior Analytics would look like. I argue that these modern preconceptions are incorrect, and that, while the Analytics leaves a variety of issues unanswered (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  84
    The Place of Mankind in Aristotle’s Zoology.James G. Lennox - 1999 - Philosophical Topics 27 (1):1-16.
    Historians of psychology often treat Aristotle’s De Anima as the first scientific treatment of their subject; and historians of biology do likewise with his zoological treatises. How are the investigations recorded in works such as the Parts of Animals and History of Animals connected to those in the De Anima? More specifically, given Aristotle’s views about man’s special and distinctive cognitive capacities, what does he think about man as an object of a distinctively zoological investigation? In the following pages, this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  9
    Form, Essence, and Explanation in Aristotle's Biology.James G. Lennox - 2009 - In Georgios Anagnostopoulos (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 348–367.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Essence and Explanation in Theory and Practice Form, Function, and Biological Essentialism The Priority of Being to Generation Conclusion Notes Bibliography.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 123