Results for 'Geometry in nature'

998 found
Order:
  1.  89
    Natural Geometry in Descartes and Kepler.Gary Hatfield - 2015 - Res Philosophica 92 (1):117-148.
    According to Kepler and Descartes, the geometry of the triangle formed by the two eyes when focused on a single point affords perception of the distance to that point. Kepler characterized the processes involved as associative learning. Descartes described the processes as a “ natural geometry.” Many interpreters have Descartes holding that perceivers calculate the distance to the focal point using angle-side-angle, calculations that are reduced to unnoticed mental habits in adult vision. This article offers a purely psychophysiological (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2. “In Nature as in Geometry”: Du Châtelet and the Post-Newtonian Debate on the Physical Significance of Mathematical Objects.Aaron Wells - 2023 - In Wolfgang Lefèvre (ed.), Between Leibniz, Newton, and Kant: Philosophy and Science in the Eighteenth Century. Springer Verlag. pp. 69-98.
    Du Châtelet holds that mathematical representations play an explanatory role in natural science. Moreover, she writes that things proceed in nature as they do in geometry. How should we square these assertions with Du Châtelet’s idealism about mathematical objects, on which they are ‘fictions’ dependent on acts of abstraction? The question is especially pressing because some of her important interlocutors (Wolff, Maupertuis, and Voltaire) denied that mathematics informs us about the properties of material things. After situating Du Châtelet (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Natural Philosophy, Deduction, and Geometry in the Hobbes-Boyle Debate.Marcus P. Adams - 2017 - Hobbes Studies 30 (1):83-107.
    This paper examines Hobbes’s criticisms of Robert Boyle’s air-pump experiments in light of Hobbes’s account in _De Corpore_ and _De Homine_ of the relationship of natural philosophy to geometry. I argue that Hobbes’s criticisms rely upon his understanding of what counts as “true physics.” Instead of seeing Hobbes as defending natural philosophy as “a causal enterprise … [that] as such, secured total and irrevocable assent,” 1 I argue that, in his disagreement with Boyle, Hobbes relied upon his understanding of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. The Marriage of Metaphysics and Geometry in Kant's Prolegomena (Forthcoming in Cambridge Critical Guide to Kant’s Prolegomena).James Messina - 2021 - In Peter Thiekle (ed.), Cambridge Critical Guide to Kant’s Prolegomena. Cambridge.
    Kant was engaged in a lifelong struggle to achieve what he calls in the 1756 Physical Monadology (PM) a “marriage” of metaphysics and geometry (1:475). On one hand, this involved showing that metaphysics and geometry are complementary, despite the seemingly irreconcilable conflicts between these disciplines and between their respective advocates, the Leibnizian-Wolffians and the Newtonians. On the other hand, this involved defining the terms of their union, which meant among other things, articulating their respective roles in grounding Newtonian (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Dmitri Nikulin: Matter, Imagination and Geometry, Ontology, Natural Philosophy and Mathematics in Plotinus, Proclus and Descartes.J. J. Cleary - 2003 - Early Science and Medicine 8 (3):267-268.
  6. Fractal geometry is not the geometry of nature.Orly R. Shenker - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (6):967-981.
    In recent years the magnificent world of fractals has been revealed. Some of the fractal images resemble natural forms so closely that Benoit Mandelbrot's hypothesis, that the fractal geometry is the geometry of natural objects, has been accepted by scientists and non-scientists alike. The present paper critically examines Mandelbrot's hypothesis. It first analyzes the concept of a fractal. The analysis reveals that fractals are endless geometrical processes, and not geometrical forms. A comparison between fractals and irrational numbers shows (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7.  46
    On Natural Geometry and Seeing Distance Directly in Descartes.Gary Hatfield - 2015 - In Vincenzo De Risi (ed.), Mathematizing Space: The Objects of Geometry from Antiquity to the Early Modern Age. Birkhäuser. pp. 157-91.
    As the word “optics” was understood from antiquity into and beyond the early modern period, it did not mean simply the physics and geometry of light, but meant the “theory of vision” and included what we should now call physiological and psychological aspects. From antiquity, these aspects were subject to geometrical analysis. Accordingly, the geometry of visual experience has long been an object of investigation. This chapter examines accounts of size and distance perception in antiquity (Euclid and Ptolemy) (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8. Matter and geometry in a unified theory.Leopold Halpern - 1994 - Foundations of Physics 24 (12):1697-1703.
    The prediction of general relativity on the gravitational collapse of matter ending in a point is viewed as an absurdity of the kind to be expected in any consistent physical theory due to ultimate conflicts of the axioms of geometry with the properties of physical objects. The necessity to introduce a probability interpretation for the solution of partial differential equations in space time for quantum theory points to similar roots. It is pointed out that quantum theory in the very (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  62
    Matter Creation by Geometry in an Integrable Weyl-Dirac Theory.Mark Israelit - 1999 - Foundations of Physics 29 (8):1303-1322.
    An integrable version of the Weyl-Dirac geometry is presented. This framework is a natural generalization of the Riemannian geometry, the latter being the basis of the classical general relativity theory. The integrable Weyl-Dirac theory is both coordinate covariant and gauge covariant (in the Weyl sense), and the field equations and conservation laws are derived from an action integral. In this framework matter creation by geometry is considered. It is found that a spatially confined, spherically symmetric formation made (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Alphonso Lingis.I. Consciousness Naturalized in A. Body - 1971 - Analecta Husserliana 1:75.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Frege on the Foundation of Geometry in Intuition.Jeremy Shipley - 2015 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 3 (6).
    I investigate the role of geometric intuition in Frege’s early mathematical works and the significance of his view of the role of intuition in geometry to properly understanding the aims of his logicist project. I critically evaluate the interpretations of Mark Wilson, Jamie Tappenden, and Michael Dummett. The final analysis that I provide clarifies the relationship of Frege’s restricted logicist project to dominant trends in German mathematical research, in particular to Weierstrassian arithmetization and to the Riemannian conceptual/geometrical tradition at (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  70
    Hobbes on Hypotheses in Natural Philosophy.Frank Horstmann - 2001 - The Monist 84 (4):487-501.
    Thomas Hobbes adheres to a conception of philosophy as causal knowledge that bears the mark of the Aristotelian tradition, as Cees Leijenhorst has elaborated in another issue of The Monist. Referring to Aristotle, Hobbes states explicitly in two mathematical studies of the 1660’s: “To know is to know by causes.” But according to Hobbes, we encounter obstacles when we search for causes in the field of natural philosophy. Consequently, his well-known definition of philosophy consists of two parts. The earliest version, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  2
    Chapter seventeen.Monster Nature’S. & In Seneca’S. - 2008 - In I. Sluiter & Ralph Mark Rosen (eds.), Kakos: Badness and Anti-Value in Classical Antiquity. Brill. pp. 451.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Copyright© The Monist: An International Quarterly Journal of General Philosophical Inquiry, Open Court Publishing Company, Chicago, Illinois. Reprinted by permission.Disvalues In Nature - 1992 - The Monist 75 (2):250-278.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  11
    Symmetrical Geometry of Flowers in Art and Nature “The Triumphal Entry of Jesus into Jerusalem”.Cristian Ungureanu - 2016 - Human and Social Studies 5 (2):90-99.
    The aim of our study is to highlight the obvious similarities that exist between the organizational structures of the biological world, particularly in terms of the number and distribution of the petals on flower and the geometric configurations used by the great masters of European painting, both in the East but also in the West, in order to elaborate the compositional framework of paintings and icons. Taking into consideration the symbolic connotations concerning the field of biology, we chose as a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  4
    Advances in Geometry and Lie Algebras from Supergravity.Pietro Giuseppe Frè - 2018 - Cham: Imprint: Springer.
    This book aims to provide an overview of several topics in advanced Differential Geometry and Lie Group Theory, all of them stemming from mathematical problems in supersymmetric physical theories. It presents a mathematical illustration of the main development in geometry and symmetry theory that occurred under the fertilizing influence of supersymmetry/supergravity. The contents are mainly of mathematical nature, but each topic is introduced by historical information and enriched with motivations from high energy physics, which help the reader (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Geometry, biophysics, and neuroscience: On the quantum nature of life and consciousness in the confluence of the thoughts of Erwin Schrodinger and Hermann Weyl.Manuel Bejar Gallego - 2009 - Pensamiento 65 (246):959-986.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  21
    Grasping the spirit in nature: Anschauung in Ørsted’s epistemology of science and beauty.Kristine Hays Lynning & Anja Skaar Jacobsen - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):45-57.
    The intersection between art, poetry, philosophy and science was the leitmotif which guided the lives and careers of romantic natural philosophers including that of the Danish natural philosopher, H. C. Ørsted. A simple model of Ørsted’s career would be one in which it was framed by two periods of philosophical speculation: the youth’s curious and idealistic interest in new attractive thoughts and the experienced man’s mature reflections at the end of his life. We suggest that a closer look at the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  24
    The Geometry of Otto Selz’s Natural Space.Klaus Robering - 2019 - Erkenntnis 86 (2):325-354.
    Following ideas elaborated by Hering in his celebrated analysis of color, the psychologist and gestalt theorist Otto Selz developed in the 1930s a theory of “natural space”, i.e., space as it is conceived by us. Selz’s thesis is that the geometric laws of natural space describe how the points of this space are related to each other by directions which are ordered in the same way as the points on a sphere. At the end of one of his articles, Selz (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  40
    The synthetic nature of geometry, and the role of construction in intuition.Anja Jauernig - 2013 - In Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht: Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant Kongresses 2010 in Pisa, Volume V. Berlin/New York: pp. 89-100.
    Most commentators agree that (part of what) Kant means by characterizing the propositions of geometry as synthetic is that they are not true merely in virtue of logic or meaning, and that this characterization has something to do with his views about the construction of geometrical concepts in intuition. Many commentators regard construction in intuition as an essential part of geometrical proofs on Kant’s view. On this reading, the propositions of geometry are synthetic because the geometrical theorems cannot (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. The geometry of visual space and the nature of visual experience.Farid Masrour - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (7):1813-1832.
    Some recently popular accounts of perception account for the phenomenal character of perceptual experience in terms of the qualities of objects. My concern in this paper is with naturalistic versions of such a phenomenal externalist view. Focusing on visual spatial perception, I argue that naturalistic phenomenal externalism conflicts with a number of scientific facts about the geometrical characteristics of visual spatial experience.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  22.  51
    Conventionalism In Reid’s ‘geometry Of Visibles’.Edward Slowik - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (3):467-489.
    The subject of this investigation is the role of conventions in the formulation of Thomas Reid’s theory of the geometry of vision, which he calls the ‘geometry of visibles’. In particular, we will examine the work of N. Daniels and R. Angell who have alleged that, respectively, Reid’s ‘geometry of visibles’ and the geometry of the visual field are non-Euclidean. As will be demonstrated, however, the construction of any geometry of vision is subject to a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  15
    Moral geometry, natural alignments and utopian urban form.Jean-Paul Baldacchino - 2018 - Thesis Eleven 148 (1):52-76.
    The city has featured as a central image in utopian thought. In planning the foundation of the new and ideal city there is a close interconnection between ideas about urban form and the vision of the moral good. The spatial structure of the ideal city in these visions is a framing device that embodies and articulates not only political philosophy but is itself an articulation of moral and cosmological systems. This paper analyses three different utopian moments in three different historical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  5
    Explanations in Hobbes's Optics and Natural Philosophy.Marcus P. Adams - 2021 - In A Companion to Hobbes. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 75–90.
    This chapter discusses Thomas Hobbes's statements about the structure of philosophy and suggests that a focus on these reflections has led some scholars to understand Hobbes as an armchair speculative philosopher, both in his own natural‐philosophy endeavors and his well‐known criticisms of Robert Boyle and other experimental philosophers. Beyond Hobbes's statements about natural philosophy, it argues that a more complete understanding of his natural philosophy must also consider his practice of explaining in natural philosophy and optics. Hobbes divides all human (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Natural number and natural geometry.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2011 - In Stanislas Dehaene & Elizabeth Brannon (eds.), Space, Time and Number in the Brain. Oxford University Press. pp. 287--317.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  26.  2
    New Trends in Geometry, and its Role in the Natural and Life Sciences.Claudio Bartocci, Luciano Boi & Corrado Sinigaglia (eds.) - 2011 - World Scientific.
    This volume focuses on the interactions between mathematics, physics, biology and neuroscience by exploring new geometrical and topological modeling in these fields. Among the highlights are the central roles played by multilevel and scale-change approaches in these disciplines. The integration of mathematics with physics, molecular and cell biology, and the neurosciences, will constitute the new frontier and challenge for 21st century science, where breakthroughs are more likely to span across traditional disciplines.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  41
    The Synthetic Nature of Geometry, and the Role of Construction in Intuition.Anja Jauerning - 2013 - In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Boston: de Gruyter. pp. 89-100.
  28. Affine geometry, visual sensation, and preference for symmetry of things in a thing.Birgitta Dresp-Langley - 2016 - Symmetry 127 (8).
    Evolution and geometry generate complexity in similar ways. Evolution drives natural selection while geometry may capture the logic of this selection and express it visually, in terms of specific generic properties representing some kind of advantage. Geometry is ideally suited for expressing the logic of evolutionary selection for symmetry, which is found in the shape curves of vein systems and other natural objects such as leaves, cell membranes, or tunnel systems built by ants. The topology and (...) of symmetry is controlled by numerical parameters, which act in analogy with a biological organism’s DNA. The introductory part of this paper reviews findings from experiments illustrating the critical role of two-dimensional (2D) design parameters, affine geometry and shape symmetry for visual or tactile shape sensation and perception-based decision making in populations of experts and non-experts. It will be shown that 2D fractal symmetry, referred to herein as the “symmetry of things in a thing”, results from principles very similar to those of affine projection. Results from experiments on aesthetic and visual preference judgments in response to 2D fractal trees with varying degrees of asymmetry are presented. In a first experiment (psychophysical scaling procedure), non-expert observers had to rate (on a scale from 0 to 10) the perceived beauty of a random series of 2D fractal trees with varying degrees of fractal symmetry. In a second experiment (two-alternative forced choice procedure), they had to express their preference for one of two shapes from the series. The shape pairs were presented successively in random order. Results show that the smallest possible fractal deviation from “symmetry of things in a thing” significantly reduces the perceived attractiveness of such shapes. The potential of future studies where different levels of complexity of fractal patterns are weighed against different degrees of symmetry is pointed out in the conclusion. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  96
    Geometry and the Science of Morality in Hobbes.Stephen Finn - 2001 - Social Philosophy Today 17:57-66.
    In the central chapters of Leviathan, Hobbes offers a demonstration of the "true doctrine of the laws of nature," which is identified with the "science of virtue andvice" and the "true moral philosophy." In his deduction of the laws of nature, Hobbes attempts to mimic the science of geometry, which he says is the "only science God had hitherto bestowed on mankind. "In this paper, I discuss some of the problems associated with Hobbes's application of the method (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  24
    ""Platonic Dualism, LP GERSON This paper analyzes the nature of Platonic dualism, the view that there are immaterial entities called" souls" and that every man is identical with one such entity. Two distinct arguments for dualism are discovered in the early and middle dialogues, metaphysical/epistemological and eth.Aaron Ben-Zeev Making Mental Properties More Natural - 1986 - The Monist 69 (3).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  9
    Sacred geometry: your personal guide.Bernice Cockram - 2020 - New York, NY: Wellfleet Press.
    With In Focus Sacred Geometry, learn the fascinating history behind this ancient tradition as well as how to decipher the geometrical symbols, formulas, and patterns based on mathematical patterns. People have searched for the meaning behind mathematical patterns for thousands of years. At its core, sacred geometry seeks to find the universal patterns that are found and applied to the objects surrounding us, such as the designs found in temples, churches, mosques, monuments, art, architecture, and nature. Learn (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  17
    Geometry and analysis in Euler’s integral calculus.Giovanni Ferraro, Maria Rosaria Enea & Giovanni Capobianco - 2017 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 71 (1):1-38.
    Euler developed a program which aimed to transform analysis into an autonomous discipline and reorganize the whole of mathematics around it. The implementation of this program presented many difficulties, and the result was not entirely satisfactory. Many of these difficulties concerned the integral calculus. In this paper, we deal with some topics relevant to understand Euler’s conception of analysis and how he developed and implemented his program. In particular, we examine Euler’s contribution to the construction of differential equations and his (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Geometric conventionalism and carnap's principle of tolerance: We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a conventionalism that allows us complete freedom to select whatever language we wish—an interpretation that generalizes the conventionalism promoted by Poincaré and Hilbert which allows us complete freedom to select whatever axiom system we wish for geometry. We argue that such an interpretation saddles Carnap with a theory of meaning that has unhappy consequences, a theory we believe he did not hold. We suggest that the principle of linguistic tolerance in.David De Vidi & Graham Solomon - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (5):773-783.
    We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a conventionalism that allows (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Geometry and Experimental Method in Locke, Newton and Kant.Mary Domski - 2003 - Dissertation, Indiana University
    Historians of modern philosophy have been paying increasing attention to contemporaneous scientific developments. Isaac Newton's Principia is of course crucial to any discussion of the influence of scientific advances on the philosophical currents of the modern period, and two philosophers who have been linked especially closely to Newton are John Locke and Immanuel Kant. My dissertation aims to shed new light on the ties each shared with Newtonian science by treating Newton, Locke, and Kant simultaneously. I adopt Newton's philosophy of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  39
    Geometry and Mechanics in the Preface to Newton’s Principia.Niccolò Guicciardini - 2004 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 25 (2):119-159.
    The first edition of Newton’s Principia opens with a “Praefatio ad Lectorem.” The first lines of this Preface have received scant attention from historians, even though they contain the very first words addressed to the reader of one of the greatest classics of science. Instead, it is the second half of the Preface that historians have often referred to in connection with their treatments of Newton’s scientific methodology. Roughly in the middle of the Preface, Newton defines the purpose of philosophy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  39
    Hume on Geometry and Infinite Divisibility in the Treatise.H. Mark Pressman - 1997 - Hume Studies 23 (2):227-244.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume XXIII, Number 2, November 1997, pp. 227-244 Hume on Geometry and Infinite Divisibility in the Treatise H. MARK PRESSMAN Scholars have recognized that in the Treatise "Hume seeks to find a foundation for geometry in sense-experience."1 In this essay, I examine to what extent Hume succeeds in his attempt to ground geometry visually. I argue that the geometry Hume describes in the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  44
    Geometry, Time and Force in the Diagrams of Descartes, Galileo, Torricelli and Newton.Emily R. Grosholz - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:237 - 248.
    Cartesian method both organizes and impoverishes the domains to which Descartes applies it. It adjusts geometry so that it can be better integrated with algebra, and yet deflects a full-scale investigation of curves. It provides a comprehensive conceptual framework for physics, and yet interferes with the exploitation of its dynamical and temporal aspects. Most significantly, it bars a fuller unification of mathematics and physics, despite Descartes' claims to quantify nature. The work of his contemporaries Galileo and Torricelli, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Music, Geometry, and the Listener: Space in The History of Western Philosophy and Western Classical Music.M. Buck - unknown
    This thesis is directed towards a philosophy of music by attention to conceptions and perceptions of space. I focus on melody and harmony, and do not emphasise rhythm, which, as far as I can tell, concerns time rather than space. I seek a metaphysical account of Western Classical music in the diatonic tradition. More specifically, my interest is in wordless, untitled music, often called 'absolute' music. My aim is to elucidate a spatial approach to the world combined with a curiosity (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  52
    Geometry and the Gods: Theurgy_ in Proclus’s _Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements.Robert Goulding - 2022 - Perspectives on Science 30 (3):358-406.
    The gods that guard the poles have been assigned the function of assembling the separate and unifying the manifold members of the whole, while those appointed to the axes keep the circuits in everlasting revolution around and around. And if I may add my own conceit, the centers and poles of all the spheres symbolize the wry-necked gods by imitating the mysterious union and synthesis which they effect; the axes represent the connectors of all the cosmic orders … and the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  88
    Optics in Hobbes’s Natural Philosophy.Franco Giudice - 2016 - Hobbes Studies 29 (1):86-102.
    _ Source: _Volume 29, Issue 1, pp 86 - 102 The aim of this paper is to give an overview of the place that Hobbes assigns to optics in the context of his classification of sciences and disciplinary boundaries. To do this, I will begin with an account of Hobbes’s conception of philosophy or science, and particularly his distinction between true and hypothetical knowledge. I will also show that in his demarcation between mathematics or geometry and natural philosophy Hobbes (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  15
    Andrzej Grzegorczyk. Axiomatizability of geometry without points. Synthese, vol. 12 nos. 2–3 , pp. 228–233; also in The concept and role of the model in mathematics and natural and social sciences, Synthese Library, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht 1961, pp. 104–111. [REVIEW]Wolfram Schwabhäuser - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (1):201-201.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Modular diploma in complementary medicine, the letchworth centre for homoeopathy and complementary medicine.Are Natural Therapies Safe - forthcoming - Mind.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  51
    Diagrammatic representation in geometry.Dennis Potter - 2006 - Dialectica 60 (4):369–382.
    In this paper I offer a theory about the nature of diagrammatic representation in geometry. On my view, diagrammatic representaiton differs from pictorial representation in that neither the resemblance between the diagram and its object nor the experience of such a resemblance plays an essential role. Instead, the diagrammatic representation is arises from the role the components of the diagram play in a diagramatic practice that allows us to draws inferences based on them about the ojbects they represent.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  17
    Diagrammatic Representation in Geometry.Dennis Potter - 2006 - Dialectica 60 (4):369-382.
    In this paper I offer a theory about the nature of diagrammatic representation in geometry. On my view, diagrammatic representaiton differs from pictorial representation in that neither the resemblance between the diagram and its object nor the experience of such a resemblance plays an essential role. Instead, the diagrammatic representation is arises from the role the components of the diagram play in a diagramatic practice that allows us to draws inferences based on them about the ojbects they represent.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  22
    Kant and the Synthetic Nature of Geometry.Colwyn Williamson - 1968 - Dialogue 6 (4):497-515.
    The purpose of this paper is to explore the significance of Kant's claim that geometry is synthetic. I begin by outlining certain criticisms of the Kantian position, criticisms selected with an eye to their popularity, rather than their importance in the abstract. I am no expert on the textual exegesis of Kant, and serious Kantian scholars would not, perhaps, be much troubled by the criticisms I propose to discuss: indeed, they might properly maintain that some of these problems were, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  40
    Differential Sheaves and Connections: A Natural Approach to Physical Geometry.Anastasios Mallios & Elias Zafiris - 2015 - World Scientific.
    This unique book provides a self-contained conceptual and technical introduction to the theory of differential sheaves. This serves both the newcomer and the experienced researcher in undertaking a background-independent, natural and relational approach to "physical geometry". In this manner, this book is situated at the crossroads between the foundations of mathematical analysis with a view toward differential geometry and the foundations of theoretical physics with a view toward quantum mechanics and quantum gravity. The unifying thread is provided by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  61
    Helmholtz's naturalized conception of geometry and his spatial theory of signs.David Jalal Hyder - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):286.
    I analyze the two main theses of Helmholtz's "The Applicability of the Axioms to the Physical World," in which he argued that the axioms of Euclidean geometry are not, as his neo-Kantian opponents had argued, binding on any experience of the external world. This required two argumentative steps: 1) a new account of the structure of our representations which was consistent both with the experience of our (for him) Euclidean world and with experience of a non-Euclidean one, and 2) (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  41
    Natural Philosophy, Abstraction, and Mathematics among Materialists: Thomas Hobbes and Margaret Cavendish on Light.Marcus P. Adams - 2022 - Philosophies 7 (2):44.
    The nature of light is a focus of Thomas Hobbes’s natural philosophical project. Hobbes’s explanation of the light of lucid bodies differs across his works, from dilation and contraction in Elements of Law to simple circular motions in De corpore. However, Hobbes consistently explains perceived light by positing that bodily resistance generates the phantasm of light. In Letters I.XIX–XX of Philosophical Letters, fellow materialist Margaret Cavendish attacks the Hobbesian understanding of both lux and lumen by claiming that Hobbes has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. The Role of Material and Efficient Causes in Aristotle's Natural Teleology Margaret Scharle.Natural Teleology - 2008 - In John Mouracade (ed.), Aristotle on life. Kelowna, BC: Academic Print. &. pp. 41--3.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  76
    Nature’s drawing: problems and resolutions in the mathematization of motion.Ofer Gal & Raz Chen-Morris - 2012 - Synthese 185 (3):429-466.
    The mathematical nature of modern science is an outcome of a contingent historical process, whose most critical stages occurred in the seventeenth century. ‘The mathematization of nature’ (Koyré 1957 , From the closed world to the infinite universe , 5) is commonly hailed as the great achievement of the ‘scientific revolution’, but for the agents affecting this development it was not a clear insight into the structure of the universe or into the proper way of studying it. Rather, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 998