Results for 'Criterion of Logicality'

988 found
Order:
  1.  54
    Carnap's criterion of logicality.Denis Bonnay - 2009 - In Pierre Wagner (ed.), Carnap's Logical Syntax of Language. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 147-165.
    Providing a principled characterization of the distinction between logical and non-logical expressions is a longstanding issue in the philosophy of logic. In the Logical Syntax of Language, Carnap proposes a syntactic solution to this problem, which aims at grounding the claim that logic and mathematics are analytic. Roughly speaking, his idea is that logic and mathematics correspond to the largest part of science for which it is possible to completely specify by "syntactic" means which sentences are valid and which are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2.  36
    A criterion of fullness of many-valued systems of propositional logic.Jerzy Słupecki - 1972 - Studia Logica 30 (1):153-157.
  3. Theological Statements and the Question of an Empiricist Criterion of Cognitive Significance.Michael Tooley - 1975 - In Malcolm L. Diamond & Jr Litzenburg (eds.), Theology and Verification. Bobbs-Merrill. pp. 481–524.
    This paper is divided into four sections. -/- The first section contains an informal characterization of what may, for the purposes of this discussion, be referred to as the standard interpretation of theological statements. -/- Then, in the second section, I mention two challenges to the commonsense view that theological statements have cognitive content: the quote “falsifiability challenge” and the “ translatability challenge”. -/- Both of these challenges involve an appeal to an empiricist criterion of cognitive content, but I (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  99
    The Undergeneration of Permutation Invariance as a Criterion for Logicality.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (1):81-97.
    Permutation invariance is often presented as the correct criterion for logicality. The basic idea is that one can demarcate the realm of logic by isolating specific entities—logical notions or constants—and that permutation invariance would provide a philosophically motivated and technically sophisticated criterion for what counts as a logical notion. The thesis of permutation invariance as a criterion for logicality has received considerable attention in the literature in recent decades, and much of the debate is developed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  5
    Basic Problems in Methodology and Linguistics: Part Three of the Proceedings of the Fifth International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, London, Ontario, Canada-1975.Robert E. Butts, Jaakko Hintikka & Methodology Philosophy of Science International Congress of Logic - 1977 - Springer.
    The Fifth International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science was held at the University of Western Ontario, London, Canada, 27 August to 2 September 1975. The Congress was held under the auspices of the International Union of History and Philosophy of Science, Division of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, and was sponsored by the National Research Council of Canada and the University of Western Ontario. As those associated closely with the work of the Division over the years (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. The causal criterion of reality and the necessity of laws of nature.Max Kistler - 2002 - Metaphysica 3 (1):57-86.
    I propose an argument for the thesis that laws of nature are necessary in the sense of holding in all worlds sharing the properties of the actual world, on the basis of a principle I propose to call the Causal Criterion of Reality . The CCR says: for an entity to be real it is necessary and sufficient that it is capable to make a difference to causal interactions. The crucial idea here is that the capacity to interact causally (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  7.  39
    A criterion of identity for intensional entities.C. Anthony Anderson - 2001 - In C. Anthony Anderson & Michael Zelëny (eds.), Logic, meaning, and computation: essays in memory of Alonzo Church. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 305--395.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Marfa-Luisa Rivero.Antecedents of Contemporary Logical & Linguistic Analyses in Scholastic Logic - 1973 - Foundations of Language 10:55.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  16
    Logical Necessity Based on Carnap's Criterion of Adequacy.Nino Cocchiarella - 2002 - Korean Journal of Logic 5 (2):1-21.
    A semantics for logical necessity, based on Carnap's criterion of adequacy, is given with respect to the ontology of logical atomism. A calculus for sentential (propositional) modal logic is described and shown to be complete with respect to this semantics. The semantics is then modified in terms of a restricted notion of 'all possible worlds' in the interpretation of necessity and shown to yield a completeness theorem for the modal logic S5. Such a restricted notion introduces material content into (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  8
    Philosophy of Logic.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1970 - Englewood Cliffs, NJ, USA: Prentice-Hall.
    1 Meaning and Truth Objection to propositions Propositions as information Diffuseness of empirical meaning Propositions dismissed Truth and semantic ascent Tokens and eternal sentences 2 Grammar Grammar by recursion Categories Immanence and transcendence Grammarian's goal reexamined Logical grammar Redundant devices Names and functors Lexicon, particle, and name Criterion of lexicon Time, events, adverbs Attitudes and modality 3 Truth Truth and satisfaction Satisfaction by sequences Tarski's definition of truth Paradox in the object language Resolution in set theory 4 Logical Truth (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  11.  7
    Review: Jerzy Slupecki, A Criterion of Fullness of Many-Valued Systems of Propositional Logic. [REVIEW]Jan Kalicki - 1946 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):128-128.
  12.  19
    Luis moniz Pereira.Philosophical Incidence Of Logic - 2002 - In Dov M. Gabbay (ed.), Handbook of the Logic of Argument and Inference: The Turn Towards the Practical. Elsevier.
  13. Understanding the object.Property Structure in Terms of Negation: An Introduction to Hegelian Logic & Metaphysics in the Perception Chapter - 2019 - In Robert Brandom (ed.), A Spirit of Trust: A Reading of Hegel’s _phenomenology_. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Carnap's Forgotten Criterion of Empirical Significance.James Justus - 2014 - Mind 123 (490):415-436.
    The waning popularity of logical empiricism and the supposed discovery of insurmountable technical difficulties led most philosophers to abandon the project to formulate a formal criterion of empirical significance. Such a criterion would delineate claims that observation can confirm or disconfirm from those it cannot. Although early criteria were clearly inadequate, criticisms made of later, more sophisticated criteria were often indefensible or easily answered. Most importantly, Carnap’s last criterion was seriously misinterpreted and an amended version of it (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15.  6
    A Criterion of Necessity.Christopher Blake - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (4):291-292.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint.Gila Sher - 1991 - MIT Press.
    The Bounds of Logic presents a new philosophical theory of the scope and nature of logic based on critical analysis of the principles underlying modern Tarskian logic and inspired by mathematical and linguistic development. Extracting central philosophical ideas from Tarski’s early work in semantics, Sher questions whether these are fully realized by the standard first-order system. The answer lays the foundation for a new, broader conception of logic. By generally characterizing logical terms, Sher establishes a fundamental result in semantics. Her (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  17. Philosophy of Science, History of Science a Selection of Contributed Papers of the 7th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Salzburg, 1983.C. Pühringer, Paul Weingartner & Methodology and Philosophy of Science International Congress of Logic - 1984 - A. Hain.
  18.  10
    The Criterion of Reality.W. H. Sheldon - 1948 - Review of Metaphysics 1 (3):3 - 37.
    Effort is then well-nigh indescribable. Not wholly so, else it would be meaningless. Description is a matter of degree: who can fully describe red or wet? To be sure, description comes down in the end to the pointing to certain given qualities or relations or events which are just there. All connotation rests on denotation, though it may be something more. But the unique positive thing about effort is its originality; to which indeed we can point, since every one experiences (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Polyhedral Completeness of Intermediate Logics: The Nerve Criterion.Sam Adam-day, Nick Bezhanishvili, David Gabelaia & Vincenzo Marra - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):342-382.
    We investigate a recently devised polyhedral semantics for intermediate logics, in which formulas are interpreted in n-dimensional polyhedra. An intermediate logic is polyhedrally complete if it is complete with respect to some class of polyhedra. The first main result of this paper is a necessary and sufficient condition for the polyhedral completeness of a logic. This condition, which we call the Nerve Criterion, is expressed in terms of Alexandrov’s notion of the nerve of a poset. It affords a purely (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  49
    The logic behind Quine's criterion of ontological commitment.Jeroen Smid - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 28 (3):789-804.
    European Journal of Philosophy, EarlyView.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Types of negation in logical reconstructions of meinong Andrew Kenneth Jorgensen university of Leeds.in Logical Reconstructions Of Meinong - 2004 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 67 (1):21-36.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. The Modal and Epistemic Arguments against the Invariance Criterion for Logical Terms.Gil Sagi - 2015 - Journal of Philosophy 112 (3):159-167.
    The essay discusses a recurrent criticism of the isomorphism-invariance criterion for logical terms, according to which the criterion pertains only to the extension of logical terms, and neglects the meaning, or the way the extension is fixed. A term, so claim the critics, can be invariant under isomorphisms and yet involve a contingent or a posteriori component in its meaning, thus compromising the necessity or apriority of logical truth and logical consequence. This essay shows that the arguments underlying (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  23. The Interpretation of Two Systems of Modal Logic.A. N. Prior & Institute of Applied Logic - 1954 - Institute of Applied Logic.
  24.  62
    Beyond the Formalist Criterion of Cognitive Significance: Philipp Frank’s Later Antimetaphysics.Thomas Uebel - 2011 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (1):47-72.
    This article considers the development of Philipp Frank’s opposition to metaphysics in the light of the contention that there also was a long-standing pragmatic strand to the theorizing about science in the Vienna Circle. It is argued that the later Frank did not only distinguish metaphysical statements from those deemed simply cognitively meaningless by a substantive criterion but that in order to identify the latter he also sought to employ a practical rather than a formal criterion with which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25. An Empiricist Criterion of Meaning.Yann Benétreau-Dupin - 2011 - South African Journal of Philosophy 30 (2):95-108.
    The meaning of scientific propositions is not always expressible in terms of observable phenomena. Such propositions involve generalizations, and also terms that are theoretical constructs. I study here how to assess the meaning of scientific propositions, that is, the specific import of theoretical terms. Empiricists have expressed a concern that scientific propositions, and theoretical terms, should always be, to some degree, related to observable consequences. We can see that the former empiricist criterion of meaning only implies for theoretical terms (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Carnap and the invariance of logical truth.Steve Awodey - 2017 - Synthese 194 (1):67-78.
    The failed criterion of logical truth proposed by Carnap in the Logical Syntax of Language was based on the determinateness of all logical and mathematical statements. It is related to a conception which is independent of the specifics of the system of the Syntax, hints of which occur elsewhere in Carnap’s writings, and those of others. What is essential is the idea that the logical terms are invariant under reinterpretation of the empirical terms, and are therefore semantically determinate. A (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science Iii Proceedings of the Third International Congress for Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Amsterdam 1967; Edited by B. Van Rootselaar and J.F. Staal.Methodology and Philosophy of Science International Congress for Logic, B. van Rootselaar & J. F. Staal - 1968 - North-Holland Pub. Co.
  28.  55
    The Metaphysics of Logical Consequence.Alexandra Zinke - 2018 - Frankfurt a.M.: Klostermann.
    The book discusses the central notion of logic: the concept of logical consequence. It shows that the classical definition of consequence as truth preservation in all models must be restricted to all admissible models. The challenge for the philosophy of logic is therefore to supplement the definition with a criterion for admissible models. -/- The problem of logical constants, so prominent in the current debate, constitutes but a special case of this much more general demarcation problem. The book explores (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  32
    Wittgenstein on "Imaginability" as a Criterion for Logical Possibility.Jasmin Trächtler - 2020 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 9.
    Throughout his whole work, Wittgenstein seizes on a distinction between logical and physical possibility, and impossibility. Despite this continuity and although, Wittgenstein brings in this distinction in various contexts and from different vantage points, he often solely brushes over it without elaborating in detail. In the so-called Big Typescript, however, he dedicates himself not only to the distinction between logical and physical possibility but also to the distinction between logical possibility and impossibility in particular investigations. In the course of these (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  16
    Simplicity as a Criterion of Induction.R. Harré - 1959 - Philosophy 34 (130):229 - 234.
    There is now a well-established distinction recognized in the ways simplicity considerations enter into science. Laws of nature may be graded either with regard to their simplicity of form or with regard to the fewness of the concepts employed to express them. I shall distinguish these as formal simplicity and conceptual simplicity respectively. Dr. J. O. Wisdom suggests that it should be fewness of non-instantial concepts that serves as the guide for making judgements of relative simplicity; a “non-instantial” concept being (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning.Carl G. Hempel - 1950 - 11 Rev. Intern. De Philos 41 (11):41-63.
    The fundamental tenet of modern empiricism is the view that all non-analytic knowledge is based on experience. Let us call this thesis the principle of empiricism. [1] Contemporary logical empiricism has added [2] to it the maxim that a sentence makes a cognitively meaningful assertion, and thus can be said to be either true or false, only if it is either (1) analytic or self-contradictory or (2) capable, at least in principle, of experiential test. According to this so-called empiricist (...) of cognitive meaning, or of cognitive significance, many of the formulations of traditional metaphysics and large parts of epistemology are devoid of cognitive significance--however rich some of them may be in non-cognitive import by virtue of their emotive appeal or the moral inspiration they offer. Similarly certain doctrines which have been, at one time or another, formulated within empirical science or its border disciplines are so contrived as to be incapable of test by any conceivable evidence; they are therefore qualified as pseudo- [p. 42:] hypotheses, which assert nothing, and which therefore have no explanatory or predictive force whatever. This verdict applies, for example, to the neo-vitalist speculations about entelechies or vital forces, and to the "telefinalist hypothesis" propounded by Lecomte du Noüy. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  32.  96
    A BULLET for Invariance: Another Argument against the Invariance Criterion for Logical Terms.Alexandra Zinke - 2018 - Journal of Philosophy 115 (7):382-388.
    According to the classical invariance criterion, a term is logical if and only if its extension is isomorphism-invariant. However, a number of authors have devised examples that challenge the sufficiency of this condition: accepting these examples as logical constants would introduce objectionable contingent elements into logic. Recently, Gil Sagi has responded that these objections are based on a fallacious inference from the modal status of a sentence to the modal status of the proposition expressed by that sentence. The present (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  22
    Aesthetics and the Problem of Meaning. The Application to Aesthetics of the Logical Positivists' Verifiability Criterion of Cognitive Meaning. [REVIEW]Monroe C. Beardsley - 1953 - Journal of Philosophy 50 (1):22-23.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. A Hierarchy of Logical Constants.Alexandra Zinke - 2017 - In Arazim Pavel & Lavicka Tomas (eds.), Logica Yearbook. College Publications. pp. 305-316.
    The paper provides a new argument against the classical invariance criterion for logical terms: if all terms with a permutation invariant extension qualify as logical, then for any arbitrary true contingent sentence K of the meta-language, there would be a logically true object-language sentence 'φ' such that K follows from the sentence 'φ is true'. Thus, many logically true sentences would be a posteriori. To prevent this fatal consequence, we propose to alter the invariance criterion: not only the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. The concept of logical consequence.William H. Hanson - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):365-409.
    In the first section, I consider what several logicians say informally about the notion of logical consequence. There is significant variation among these accounts, they are sometimes poorly explained, and some of them are clearly at odds with the usual technical definition. In the second section, I first argue that a certain kind of informal account—one that includes elements of necessity, generality, and apriority—is approximately correct. Next I refine this account and consider several important questions about it, including the appropriate (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  36. Quine's criterion of ontological commitment.A. Pampapathy Rao - 1971 - Simla,: Indian Institute of Advanced Study.
  37.  42
    The scientists' criterion of true observation.D. G. Ellson - 1963 - Philosophy of Science 30 (1):41-52.
    A theory of true observation is developed as a generalization of the method of inter-observer agreement that scientists use to determine the objectivity and reliability of observations. A true observation is defined as a statement included in a set of statements in which there is statistical dependence and perfect agreement between the statements made by a universe of experimentally independent persons. Meaningfulness--the existence of an objective referent--for each form of statement included in the set is inferred from statistical dependence, correct (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. The Formal-Structural View of Logical Consequence.Gila Sher - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (2):241-261.
    This paper offers a response to William’s Hanson’s criticism of Sher’s formal-structural conception of logical consequence and logical constants.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  39.  37
    Körner's criterion of relevance and analytic tableaux.Joachim Schröder - 1992 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 21 (2):183 - 192.
  40.  22
    The Concept of Logical Consequence.William H. Hanson - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):365-409.
    In the first section, I consider what several logicians say informally about the notion of logical consequence. There is significant variation among these accounts, they are sometimes poorly explained, and some of them are clearly at odds with the usual technical definition. In the second section, I first argue that a certain kind of informal account—one that includes elements of necessity, generality, and apriority—is approximately correct. Next I refine this account and consider several important questions about it, including the appropriate (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  41. Referential consistency as a a criterion of meaning.Steven James Bartlett - 1982 - Synthese 52 (2):267 - 282.
    NOTE TO THE READER - December, 2021 ●●●●● -/- After a long period of time devoted to research in other areas, the author returned to the subject of this paper in a book-length study, CRITIQUE OF IMPURE REASON: Horizons of Possibility and Meaning. In this book (Chapter 11, “The Metalogic of Meaning”), the position developed in the 1982 paper, "Referential Consistency as a Criterion of Meaning", has been substantively revised and several important corrections made. It is recommended that readers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  42. The Metaphysics of Logical Consequence.Alexandra Zinke - 2013 - Dissertation, University of Konstanz
    The book discusses the central notion of logic, the concept of logical consequence, and its model-theoretic definition as truth-preservation in all models. Whether the model-theoretic definition captures the modal and epistemological features of our pre-theoretic notion depends on what models model. The book argues that, given a non-formal understanding of models, the universal quantifier used in the definition of consequence must be restricted: if literally all models had to be considered, no argument would ever be logically valid. A central challenge (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  36
    Russell Bertrand. Logical positivism. Revue Internationale de philosophie , vol. 4 , pp. 3–19.Carnap Rudolf. Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de philosophie , vol. 4 , pp. 20–40.Hempel Carl G.. Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning. Revue Internationale de philosophie , vol. 4 , pp. 41–63.Feigl Herbert. The mind-body problem in the development of logical empiricism. Revue Internationale de philosophie , vol. 4 , pp. 64–83.Barzin Marcel. L'empirisme logique. Revue Internationale de philosophie , vol. 4 , pp. 84–94.Feigl Herbert. Selected bibliography of logical empiricism. Revue Internationale de philosophie , vol. 4 , pp. 95–102. [REVIEW]Mieczysław Choynowski - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 16 (4):292-298.
  44.  52
    A. J. Ayer. Editor's introduction. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 3–28; also first paperback edition, The Free Press, New York 1966, pp. 3–28. - Bertrand Russell. Logical atomism. A reprint of XXV 333. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 31–50; also ibid., pp. 31–50. - Moritz Schlick. Positivism and realism. A reprint of XVI 67. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 82–107; also ibid., pp. 82–107. - Carl G. Hempel. The empiricist criterion of meaning. A reprint of XVI 293. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 108–129; also ibid., pp. 108–129. - Rudolf Carnap. The old and the new logic. English translation of 3525 by Isaac Levi. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 133–146; also ibid., pp. 133–146. - Hans Hahn. Logic, mathematics and k. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):312-312.
  45.  38
    The formal-structural view of logical consequence: A reply to Gila Sher.William H. Hanson - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (2):243-258.
    In a recent discussion article in this journal, Gila Sher responds to some of my criticisms of her work on what she calls the formal-structural account of logical consequence. In the present paper I reply and attempt to advance the discussion in a constructive way. Unfortunately, Sher seems to have not fully understood my 1997. Several of the defenses she mounts in her 2001 are aimed at views I do not hold and did not advance in my 1997. Most prominent (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  50
    The Formal-Structural View of Logical Consequence: A Reply to Gila Sher.William H. Hanson - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (2):243-258.
    In a recent discussion article in this journal, Gila Sher responds to some of my criticisms of her work on what she calls the formal-structural account of logical consequence. In the present paper I reply and attempt to advance the discussion in a constructive way. Unfortunately, Sher seems to have not fully understood my 1997. Several of the defenses she mounts in her 2001 are aimed at views I do not hold and did not advance in my 1997. Most prominent (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47.  18
    A matrix criterion of Halldén completeness.Zdzis law Dywan - 2012 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 41 (3/4):145-148.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  18
    Interpretation of De Finetti coherence criterion in Łukasiewicz logic.Daniele Mundici - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2):235-245.
    De Finetti gave a natural definition of “coherent probability assessment” β:E→[0,1] of a set E={X1,…,Xm} of “events” occurring in an arbitrary set of “possible worlds”. In the particular case of yes–no events, , Kolmogorov axioms can be derived from his criterion. While De Finetti’s approach to probability was logic-free, we construct a theory Θ in infinite-valued Łukasiewicz propositional logic, and show: a possible world of is a valuation satisfying Θ, β is coherent iff it is a convex combination of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  85
    Hypothetico-Deductivism: The Current State of Play; The Criterion of Empirical Significance: Endgame.Ken Gemes - 1998 - Erkenntnis 49 (1):1 - 20.
    : Any precise version of H-D needs to handle various problems, most notably, the problem of selective confirmation: Precise formulations of H-D should not have the consequence that where S confirms T, for any T', S confirms T&T'. It is the perceived failure of H-D to solve such problems that has lead John Earman to recently conclude that H-D is "very nearly a dead horse". This suggests the following state of play: H-D is an intuitively plausible idea that breaks down (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  50.  27
    Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning.Carl Gustav Hempel - 1950 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4 (11):41-63.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
1 — 50 / 988