19 found
Order:
See also
Christine J. Thomas
Dartmouth College
Christine Thomas
Oklahoma State University
  1. Speaking of Something: Plato’s Sophist and Plato’s Beard.Christine J. Thomas - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (4):pp. 631-667.
    The Eleatic Visitor speaks forcefully when he insists, ‘Necessarily, whenever there is speech, it is speech of something; it is impossible for it not to be of something’. For ‘if it were not of anything, it would not be speech at all; for we showed that it is impossible for there to be speech that is speech of nothing’. Presumably, at 263c10, when he claims to have ‘shown’ that it is impossible for speech to be of nothing, the Visitor is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  2.  34
    SMEs and environmental responsibility: a policy perspective.Richard Blundel, Adrian Monaghan & Christine Thomas - 2013 - Business Ethics: A European Review 22 (3):246-262.
    Environmental policies to promote environmentally sustainable economic activity have often concentrated on larger firms. However, increasing attention is being paid to the role of small- and medium-sized enterprises (SMEs) and entrepreneurial actors. In this paper, we examine how policy tools are being used to improve the environmental performance of SMEs and to redirect entrepreneurial energies in more environmentally benign directions. The empirical section adopts a case-based comparative method to examine four instances of policymaking, drawn from different countries and industry sectors. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  72
    Plato on Metaphysical Explanation: Does 'Participating' Mean Nothing?Christine J. Thomas - 2014 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 7 (2):168.
    According to Aristotle, Plato's efforts at metaphysical explanation not only fail, they are nonsensical. In particular, Plato's appeals to Forms as metaphysically explanatory of the sensibles that participate in them is "empty talk" since "'participating' means nothing". I defend Plato against Aristotle's charge by identifying a particular, substantive model of metaphysical predication as the favored model of Plato's late ontology. The model posits two basic metaphysical predication relations: self-predication and participation. In order to understand the participation relation, it is important (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  68
    Theaetetus’ Snubness and the Contents of Plato’s Thoughts.Christine J. Thomas - 2002 - Ancient Philosophy 22 (1):53-74.
  5.  21
    Motor unit firing rates during spasms in thenar muscles of spinal cord injured subjects.Inge Zijdewind, Rob Bakels & Christine K. Thomas - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
  6.  45
    Plato's Introduction of Forms (review).Christine Jean Thomas - 2007 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 45 (3):485-486.
    Christine Jean Thomas - Plato's Introduction of Forms - Journal of the History of Philosophy 45:3 Journal of the History of Philosophy 45.3 485-486 Muse Search Journals This Journal Contents Reviewed by Christine J. Thomas Dartmouth College R. M. Dancy. Plato's Introduction of Forms. Cambridge-New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp. xii + 348. Cloth, $75.00. Russell Dancy's recent book could easily bear the title, 'A Socratic Theory of Definition'. The first two-thirds of the text extract and examine various tenets (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  29
    Colloquium 2: Plato on the Nature of Life Itself.Christine Thomas - 2003 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 18 (1):39-73.
  8.  7
    Gender and Politics at Ugarit: The Undoing of the Daughter of the Great Lady.Christine Neal Thomas - 2021 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 139 (2):287.
    The integral role of royal women in political systems structured by diplomatic marriage is revealed in a series of legal verdicts from a case that involved the rulers of Late Bronze Age Ugarit, Amurru, and Ḫatti. These verdicts adjudicate the divorce, loss of political status, and execution of a royal woman who was the wife of the king of Ugarit, the daughter and sister of two successive kings of Amurru, and the granddaughter and niece of two successive Hittite Great Kings. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  85
    Inquiry without names in Plato's cratylus.Christine J. Thomas - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (3):pp. 341-364.
    The interlocutors of Plato’s Cratylus agree that “it is far better to learn and to inquire from the things themselves than from their names”. Although surprisingly little attention has been paid to these remarks, at least some commentators view Plato as articulating a preference for direct, nonlinguistic cognitive access to the objects of inquiry. Another commentator takes Plato simply to recommend first-hand, yet linguistic, experience in addition to instruction from experts. This paper defends, in contrast to both interpretations, the view (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  10
    ‘Learning’ and Learning at Euthydemus 275d–278d.Christine J. Thomas - 2019 - Australasian Philosophical Review 3 (2):191-197.
    ABSTRACT Early in Plato’s Euthydemus, sophistical arguments threaten the intelligibility of the process of learning. According to M. M. McCabe, Socrates resists the sophists’ arguments by resisting their problematic replacement model of change. The replacement model proposes that one item (e.g., an unlearned one) is simply replaced with a nonidentical item (e.g., a learned one). Socrates is said to endorse a rival metaphysics of temporally extended, teleologically structured activities. The rival model allows an enduring subject to survive ‘aspect changes’ by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Names, Thoughts and Objects in Plato's "Cratylus", "Theaetetus" and "Sophist".Christine J. Thomas - 1999 - Dissertation, Cornell University
    In this dissertation I explore Plato's views about the nature of language and thought, and their relations to the world. Plato is sometimes thought to hold that meaningful terms do not require referents at all. Others argue that he holds a referential theory of meaning according to which the meaning of a term just is its referent. I reject both of these views, arguing that Plato thinks that a significant term must have a referent but that the referent of a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  1
    Plato.Christine J. Thomas - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 429–438.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction The Metaphysics of Action The Explanation of Action The Psychology of Action References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  30
    Plato's Prometheanism.Christine J. Thomas - 2006 - In David Sedley (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxxi: Winter 2006. Oxford University Press. pp. 31--203.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Plato's Prometheanism.Christine J. Thomas - 2006 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 31:203-231.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Socratic Wisdom: The Model of Knowledge in Plato’s Early Dialogues.Christine Thomas - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (4):590-593.
    Socrates expresses at least some interest in the knowledge of knowledge as an ability “to divide things and say that one is knowledge and the other is not knowledge”. If Hugh Benson’s characteristically lucid and careful book succeeds in its portrayal of Socrates as epistemologist, then the Charmides text is perhaps more optimistic than is often conceded. For unlike Gregory Vlastos’s Socrates, who was “no epistemologist, ” Benson’s promises “a philosophically complex, fundamentally coherent, and remarkably influential model of knowledge, ” (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  40
    The case of the etymologies in Plato's cratylus.Christine J. Thomas - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (2):218–226.
    The Cratylus contains Plato's most extensive study of the relation of language to reality and to the pursuit of wisdom. Yet the dialogue has remained relatively neglected in efforts to understand Plato's deepest metaphysical and epistemological commitments. The blame for such neglect lies largely in the dialogue's extensive, difficult, even mysterious etymological section. Recent attempts to make sense of the bulk of the Cratylus are shedding much welcome light on the important roles that the etymological analyses play in the dialogue (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  24
    Socratic Wisdom. [REVIEW]Christine Thomas - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (4):590-593.
    Socrates expresses at least some interest in the knowledge of knowledge as an ability “to divide things and say that one is knowledge and the other is not knowledge”. If Hugh Benson’s characteristically lucid and careful book succeeds in its portrayal of Socrates as epistemologist, then the Charmides text is perhaps more optimistic than is often conceded. For unlike Gregory Vlastos’s Socrates, who was “no epistemologist, ” Benson’s promises “a philosophically complex, fundamentally coherent, and remarkably influential model of knowledge, ” (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  18.  31
    False Beliefand the Meno Paradox. [REVIEW]Christine Thomas - 2004 - International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1):249-250.
  19.  56
    Plato on Parts and Wholes: the Metaphysics of Structure. [REVIEW]Christine J. Thomas - 2007 - The Classical Review 57 (1):33-35.