Results for 'Basis for admissible rules'

982 found
Order:
  1.  29
    Construction of an Explicit Basis for Rules Admissible in Modal System S4.Vladimir V. Rybakov - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):441-446.
    We find an explicit basis for all admissible rules of the modal logic S4. Our basis consists of an infinite sequence of rules which have compact and simple, readable form and depend on increasing set of variables. This gives a basis for all quasi-identities valid in the free modal algebra ℱS4 of countable rank.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2.  24
    A Basis in Semi-Reduced Form for the Admissible Rules of the Intuitionistic Logic IPC.Vladimir V. Rybakov, Mehmet Terziler & Vitaliy Remazki - 2000 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 46 (2):207-218.
    We study the problem of finding a basis for all rules admissible in the intuitionistic propositional logic IPC. The main result is Theorem 3.1 which gives a basis consisting of all rules in semi-reduced form satisfying certain specific additional requirements. Using developed technique we also find a basis for rules admissible in the logic of excluded middle law KC.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  34
    Admissible rules in the implication–negation fragment of intuitionistic logic.Petr Cintula & George Metcalfe - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2):162-171.
    Uniform infinite bases are defined for the single-conclusion and multiple-conclusion admissible rules of the implication–negation fragments of intuitionistic logic and its consistent axiomatic extensions . A Kripke semantics characterization is given for the structurally complete implication–negation fragments of intermediate logics, and it is shown that the admissible rules of this fragment of form a PSPACE-complete set and have no finite basis.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  4.  17
    The Admissible Rules of ${{mathsf{BD}_{2}}}$ and ${mathsf{GSc}}$.Jeroen P. Goudsmit - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (3):325-353.
    The Visser rules form a basis of admissibility for the intuitionistic propositional calculus. We show how one can characterize the existence of covers in certain models by means of formulae. Through this characterization, we provide a new proof of the admissibility of a weak form of the Visser rules. Finally, we use this observation, coupled with a description of a generalization of the disjunction property, to provide a basis of admissibility for the intermediate logics BD2 and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  59
    On the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic.Rosalie Iemhoff - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):281-294.
    We present a basis for the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic. Thereby a conjecture by de Jongh and Visser is proved. We also present a proof system for the admissible rules, and give semantic criteria for admissibility.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  6.  35
    Logical equations and admissible rules of inference with parameters in modal provability logics.V. V. Rybakov - 1990 - Studia Logica 49 (2):215 - 239.
    This paper concerns modal logics of provability — Gödel-Löb systemGL and Solovay logicS — the smallest and the greatest representation of arithmetical theories in propositional logic respectively. We prove that the decision problem for admissibility of rules (with or without parameters) inGL andS is decidable. Then we get a positive solution to Friedman''s problem forGL andS. We also show that A. V. Kuznetsov''s problem of the existence of finite basis for admissible rules forGL andS has a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7. On the Admissible Rules of Intuitionistic Propositional Logic.Rosalie Iemhoff - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):281-294.
    We present a basis for the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic. Thereby a conjecture by de Jongh and Visser is proved. We also present a proof system for the admissible rules, and give semantic criteria for admissibility.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  8.  40
    On unification and admissible rules in Gabbay–de Jongh logics.Jeroen P. Goudsmit & Rosalie Iemhoff - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (2):652-672.
    In this paper we study the admissible rules of intermediate logics. We establish some general results on extensions of models and sets of formulas. These general results are then employed to provide a basis for the admissible rules of the Gabbay–de Jongh logics and to show that these logics have finitary unification type.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9.  56
    Proof theory for admissible rules.Rosalie Iemhoff & George Metcalfe - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 159 (1-2):171-186.
    Admissible rules of a logic are those rules under which the set of theorems of the logic is closed. In this paper, a Gentzen-style framework is introduced for analytic proof systems that derive admissible rules of non-classical logics. While Gentzen systems for derivability treat sequents as basic objects, for admissibility, the basic objects are sequent rules. Proof systems are defined here for admissible rules of classes of modal logics, including K4, S4, and (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  10.  30
    On Finite Model Property for Admissible Rules.Vladimir V. Rybakov, Vladimir R. Kiyatkin & Tahsin Oner - 1999 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 45 (4):505-520.
    Our investigation is concerned with the finite model property with respect to admissible rules. We establish general sufficient conditions for absence of fmp w. r. t. admissibility which are applicable to modal logics containing K4: Theorem 3.1 says that no logic λ containing K4 with the co-cover property and of width > 2 has fmp w. r. t. admissibility. Surprisingly many, if not to say all, important modal logics of width > 2 are within the scope of this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11.  33
    Criteria for admissibility of inference rules. Modal and intermediate logics with the branching property.Vladimir V. Rybakov - 1994 - Studia Logica 53 (2):203 - 225.
    The main result of this paper is the following theorem: each modal logic extendingK4 having the branching property belowm and the effective m-drop point property is decidable with respect to admissibility. A similar result is obtained for intermediate intuitionistic logics with the branching property belowm and the strong effective m-drop point property. Thus, general algorithmic criteria which allow to recognize the admissibility of inference rules for modal and intermediate logics of the above kind are found. These criteria are applicable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  11
    Admissible rules for six intuitionistic modal logics.Iris van der Giessen - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (4):103233.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  43
    Admissible Rules and the Leibniz Hierarchy.James G. Raftery - 2016 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (4):569-606.
    This paper provides a semantic analysis of admissible rules and associated completeness conditions for arbitrary deductive systems, using the framework of abstract algebraic logic. Algebraizability is not assumed, so the meaning and significance of the principal notions vary with the level of the Leibniz hierarchy at which they are presented. As a case study of the resulting theory, the nonalgebraizable fragments of relevance logic are considered.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  14.  26
    Even Tabular Modal Logics Sometimes Do Not Have Independent Base for Admissible Rules.Vladimir V. Rybakov - 1995 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 24 (1):37-40.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  38
    A note on admissible rules and the disjunction property in intermediate logics.Alexander Citkin - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (1):1-14.
    With any structural inference rule A/B, we associate the rule $${(A \lor p)/(B \lor p)}$$, providing that formulas A and B do not contain the variable p. We call the latter rule a join-extension ( $${\lor}$$ -extension, for short) of the former. Obviously, for any intermediate logic with disjunction property, a $${\lor}$$ -extension of any admissible rule is also admissible in this logic. We investigate intermediate logics, in which the $${\lor}$$ -extension of each admissible rule is (...). We prove that any structural finitary consequence operator (for intermediate logic) can be defined by a set of $${\lor}$$ -extended rules if and only if it can be defined through a set of well-connected Heyting algebras of a corresponding quasivariety. As we exemplify, the latter condition is satisfied for a broad class of algebraizable logics. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  69
    On the rules of intermediate logics.Rosalie Iemhoff - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (5):581-599.
    If the Visser rules are admissible for an intermediate logic, they form a basis for the admissible rules of the logic. How to characterize the admissible rules of intermediate logics for which not all of the Visser rules are admissible is not known. In this paper we give a brief overview of results on admissible rules in the context of intermediate logics. We apply these results to some well-known intermediate (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  17.  20
    Unification and admissible rules for paraconsistent minimal Johanssonsʼ logic J and positive intuitionistic logic IPC.Sergei Odintsov & Vladimir Rybakov - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (7-8):771-784.
    We study unification problem and problem of admissibility for inference rules in minimal Johanssonsʼ logic J and positive intuitionistic logic IPC+. This paper proves that the problem of admissibility for inference rules with coefficients is decidable for the paraconsistent minimal Johanssonsʼ logic J and the positive intuitionistic logic IPC+. Using obtained technique we show also that the unification problem for these logics is also decidable: we offer algorithms which compute complete sets of unifiers for any unifiable formula. Checking (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  24
    Some admissible rules in nonnormal modal systems.Timothy Williamson - 1993 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 34 (3):378-400.
    Epistemic logics for subjects of bounded rationality are in effect nonnormal modal logics. Admissible rules are of interest in such logics. However, the usual methods for establishing admissibility employ Kripke models and are therefore inappropriate for nonnormal logics. This paper extends syntactic methods for a variety of rules and nonnormal logics. In doing so it answers a question asked by Chellas and Segerberg.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  19.  4
    Semantic Analysis of Interrogtatives as a Basis for Heuristic Rules.Witold Marciszewski - 1974 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 5:86-101.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Complexity of admissible rules.Emil Jeřábek - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (2):73-92.
    We investigate the computational complexity of deciding whether a given inference rule is admissible for some modal and superintuitionistic logics. We state a broad condition under which the admissibility problem is coNEXP-hard. We also show that admissibility in several well-known systems (including GL, S4, and IPC) is in coNE, thus obtaining a sharp complexity estimate for admissibility in these systems.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  21. Intermediate Logics and Visser's Rules.Rosalie Iemhoff - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (1):65-81.
    Visser's rules form a basis for the admissible rules of . Here we show that this result can be generalized to arbitrary intermediate logics: Visser's rules form a basis for the admissible rules of any intermediate logic for which they are admissible. This implies that if Visser's rules are derivable for then has no nonderivable admissible rules. We also provide a necessary and sufficient condition for the admissibility of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  22.  21
    Some Admissible Rules in Modal Systems with the Brouwerian Axiom.Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 4 (2):283-303.
    The paper studies the admissibility of some cancellation rules in normal modal systems with the Brouwerian axiom. For example, KDB and KTB are proved to admit the following rule: if ⊢ ¬ and ⊢ ⋄α ≡ ⋄β then ⊢ ¬. Two notions of the preservation of validity by a rule on a frame are defined; on both, the preservation of validity by the preceding rule is shown not to be a first-order condition. A speculative connection is suggested with logics (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  58
    Distributive-lattice semantics of sequent calculi with structural rules.Alexej P. Pynko - 2009 - Logica Universalis 3 (1):59-94.
    The goal of the paper is to develop a universal semantic approach to derivable rules of propositional multiple-conclusion sequent calculi with structural rules, which explicitly involve not only atomic formulas, treated as metavariables for formulas, but also formula set variables, upon the basis of the conception of model introduced in :27–37, 2001). One of the main results of the paper is that any regular sequent calculus with structural rules has such class of sequent models that a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  8
    Unifiability and Structural Completeness in Relation Algebras and in Products of Modal Logic S5.Wojciech Dzik & Beniamin Wróbel - 2015 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 44 (1/2):1-14.
    Unifiability of terms (and formulas) and structural completeness in the variety of relation algebras RA and in the products of modal logic S5 is investigated. Nonunifiable terms (formulas) which are satisfiable in varieties (in logics) are exhibited. Consequently, RA and products of S5 as well as representable diagonal-free n-dimensional cylindric algebras, RDfn, are almost structurally complete but not structurally complete. In case of S5n a basis for admissible rules and the form of all passive rules are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  18
    On Pellegrino and Thomasma’s Admission of a Dilemma and Inconsistency.Loretta M. Kopelman - 2019 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (6):677-697.
    Edmund Pellegrino and David Thomasma’s writings have had a worldwide impact on discourse about the philosophy of medicine, professionalism, bioethics, healthcare ethics, and patients’ rights. Given their works’ importance, it is surprising that commentators have ignored their admission of an unresolved and troubling dilemma and inconsistency in their theory. The purpose of this article is to identify and state what problems worried them and to consider possible solutions. It is argued that their dilemma stems from their concerns about how to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  20
    Decidability: theorems and admissible rules.Vladimir Rybakov - 2008 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 18 (2-3):293-308.
    The paper deals with a temporal multi-agent logic TMAZ, which imitates taking of decisions based on agents' access to knowledge by their interaction. The interaction is modelled by possible communication channels between agents in special temporal Kripke/hintikka-like models. The logic TMAZ distinguishes local and global decisions-making. TMAZ is based on temporal Kripke/hintikka models with agents' accessibility relations defined on states of all possible time clusters C(i) (where indexes i range over all integer numbers Z). The main result provides a decision (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  6
    Description of modal logics inheriting admissible rules for S4.V. Rybakov - 1999 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 7 (5):655-664.
    We give a necessary and sufficient condition for any modal logic with fmp to inherit all inference rules admissible in S4. Using this condition we describe all tabular modal logics inheriting inference rules admissible for S4.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  21
    Do Survival Values Form a Sufficient Basis for an Objective Morality: A Realist's Appraisal of the Rules of Human Conduct.C. Emerson Talmage - unknown
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  18
    A Short and Readable Proof of Cut Elimination for Two First-Order Modal Logics.Feng Gao & George Tourlakis - 2015 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 44 (3/4):131-147.
    A well established technique toward developing the proof theory of a Hilbert-style modal logic is to introduce a Gentzen-style equivalent (a Gentzenisation), then develop the proof theory of the latter, and finally transfer the metatheoretical results to the original logic (e.g., [1, 6, 8, 18, 10, 12]). In the first-order modal case, on one hand we know that the Gentzenisation of the straightforward first-order extension of GL, the logic QGL, admits no cut elimination (if the rule is included as primitive; (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  45
    New Consecution Calculi for R→t.Katalin Bimbó & J. Michael Dunn - 2012 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 53 (4):491-509.
    The implicational fragment of the logic of relevant implication, $R_{\to}$ is one of the oldest relevance logics and in 1959 was shown by Kripke to be decidable. The proof is based on $LR_{\to}$ , a Gentzen-style calculus. In this paper, we add the truth constant $\mathbf{t}$ to $LR_{\to}$ , but more importantly we show how to reshape the sequent calculus as a consecution calculus containing a binary structural connective, in which permutation is replaced by two structural rules that involve (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  31.  16
    Imwinkelried's Argument for Normative Ethical Testimony.David W. Barnes - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (2):234-241.
    Professor Imwinkelried has boldly attempted to justify the admissibility of normative ethical expertise in the face of a legal evidentiary rule requiring a scientific basis for expert testimony. Because ethical testimony is inherently unscientific, Professor Imwinkelried prudently focuses his analysis on circumstances where evidentiary requirements are less strict; those involving the legislative rather than adjudicative function of courts and those in which substantive law overrides normally rigorous evidentiary requirements. While both proposals may have merit and are thoughtful and creative, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  51
    Imwinkelried's Argument for Normative Ethical Testimony.David W. Barnes - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (2):234-241.
    Professor Imwinkelried has boldly attempted to justify the admissibility of normative ethical expertise in the face of a legal evidentiary rule requiring a scientific basis for expert testimony. Because ethical testimony is inherently unscientific, Professor Imwinkelried prudently focuses his analysis on circumstances where evidentiary requirements are less strict; those involving the legislative rather than adjudicative function of courts and those in which substantive law overrides normally rigorous evidentiary requirements. While both proposals may have merit and are thoughtful and creative, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  22
    Compassion as a basis for ethics in medical education.C. Leget & G. Olthuis - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (10):617-620.
    The idea that ethics is a matter of personal feeling is a dogma widespread among medical students. Because emotivism is firmly rooted in contemporary culture, the authors think that focusing on personal feeling can be an important point of departure for moral education. In this contribution, they clarify how personal feelings can be a solid basis for moral education by focusing on the analysis of compassion by the French phenomenologist Emmanuel Housset. This leads to three important issues regarding ethics (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  34.  30
    Admissible Bases Via Stable Canonical Rules.Nick Bezhanishvili, David Gabelaia, Silvio Ghilardi & Mamuka Jibladze - 2016 - Studia Logica 104 (2):317-341.
    We establish the dichotomy property for stable canonical multi-conclusion rules for IPC, K4, and S4. This yields an alternative proof of existence of explicit bases of admissible rules for these logics.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  69
    Admissibility of logical inference rules.Vladimir Vladimir Rybakov - 1997 - New York: Elsevier.
    The aim of this book is to present the fundamental theoretical results concerning inference rules in deductive formal systems. Primary attention is focused on: admissible or permissible inference rules the derivability of the admissible inference rules the structural completeness of logics the bases for admissible and valid inference rules. There is particular emphasis on propositional non-standard logics (primary, superintuitionistic and modal logics) but general logical consequence relations and classical first-order theories are also considered. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  36.  64
    Admissibility of structural rules for contraction-free systems of intuitionistic logic.Roy Dyckhoff & Sara Negri - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (4):1499-1518.
    We give a direct proof of admissibility of cut and contraction for the contraction-free sequent calculus G4ip for intuitionistic propositional logic and for a corresponding multi-succedent calculus: this proof extends easily in the presence of quantifiers, in contrast to other, indirect, proofs. i.e., those which use induction on sequent weight or appeal to admissibility of rules in other calculi.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  8
    Admissibility of structural rules for extensions of contraction-free sequent calculi.R. Dyckhoff & S. Negri - 2001 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 9 (4):541-548.
    The contraction-free sequent calculus G4 for intuitionistic logic is extended by rules following a general rule-scheme for nonlogical axioms. Admissibility of structural rules for these extensions is proved in a direct way by induction on derivations. This method permits the representation of various applied logics as complete, contraction- and cut-free sequent calculus systems with some restrictions on the nature of the derivations. As specific examples, intuitionistic theories of apartness and order are treated.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Admissibility of Structural Rules for Contraction-Free Systems of Intuitionistic Logic.Roy Dyckhoff & Sara Negri - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (4):1499-1518.
    We give a direct proof of admissibility of cut and contraction for the contraction-free sequent calculus G4ip for intuitionistic propositional logic and for a corresponding multi-succedent calculus: this proof extends easily in the presence of quantifiers, in contrast to other, indirect, proofs. i.e., those which use induction on sequent weight or appeal to admissibility of rules in other calculi.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  84
    A moral basis for corporate philanthropy.Bill Shaw & Frederick R. Post - 1993 - Journal of Business Ethics 12 (10):745 - 751.
    The authors argue that corporate philanthropy is far too important as a social instrument for good to depend on ethical egoism for its support. They claim that rule utilitarianism provides a more compelling, though not exclusive, moral foundation. The authors cite empirical and legal evidence as additional support for their claim.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  40.  42
    Externalities as a Basis for Regulation: A Philosophical View.Rutger Claassen - 2016 - Journal of Institutional Economics 12 (3):541-563.
    Externalities are an important concept in economic theories of market failure, aiming to justify state regulation of the economy. This article explores the concept of externalities from a philosophical perspective. It criticizes the utilitarian nature of economic analyses of externalities, showing how they cannot take into account values like freedom and justice. It then develops the analogy between the concept of externalities and the 'harm principle' in political philosophy. It argues that the harm principle points to the need for a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. A new basis for allocating livers for transplant.Robert M. Veatch - 2000 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 10 (1):75-80.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 10.1 (2000) 75-80 [Access article in PDF] Bioethics Inside the Beltway: A New Basis for Allocating Livers for Transplant Robert M. Veatch The Department of Health and Human Services (DHHS) and the United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS), the private organization with the government contract to manage the national organ transplant program, are in the midst of a protracted dispute over how livers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  34
    The ethical basis for performing cardiopulmonary resuscitation only after informed consent in selected patient groups admitted to hospital.Philip Berry & Iona Heath - 2017 - Clinical Ethics 12 (3):111-116.
    Cardiopulmonary resuscitation is frequently performed on patients who, in retrospect, had a very low chance of survival. This is because all patients are ‘For cardiopulmonary resuscitation’ on admission to hospital by default, and delays occur before cardiopulmonary resuscitation can be ‘de-prescribed’. This article reviews the nature of potential harms caused by futile cardiopulmonary resuscitation, the reasons why de-prescription may be delayed, recent legal judgements relevant to timely do not attempt cardiopulmonary resuscitation decision making, and the possible detrimental effects of do (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. How (Not) to Argue for the Rule of Rescue. Claims of Individuals versus Group Solidarity.Marcel Verweij - 2015 - In Gohen Glen, Daniels Norman & Eyal Nir (eds.), Identified versus Statistical Victims. An Interdisciplinary Perspective. Oxford University Press. pp. 137-149.
    The rule of rescue holds that special weight should be given to protecting the lives of assignable individuals in need, implying that less weight is given to considerations of cost-effectiveness. This is sometimes invoked as an argument for funding or reimbursing life-saving treatment in public healthcare even if the costs of such treatment are extreme. At first sight one might assume that an individualist approach to ethics—such as Scanlon’s contractualism—would offer a promising route to justification of the rule of rescue. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  62
    Logic, Mathematics, and the A Priori, Part II: Core Logic as Analytic, and as the Basis for Natural Logicism.Neil Tennant - 2014 - Philosophia Mathematica 22 (3):321-344.
    We examine the sense in which logic is a priori, and explain how mathematical theories can be dichotomized non-trivially into analytic and synthetic portions. We argue that Core Logic contains exactly the a-priori-because-analytically-valid deductive principles. We introduce the reader to Core Logic by explaining its relationship to other logical systems, and stating its rules of inference. Important metatheorems about Core Logic are reported, and its important features noted. Core Logic can serve as the basis for a foundational program (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45.  33
    The machine basis for the Dasein: On the prospects for an existential functionalism. [REVIEW]Gordon G. Globus - 1986 - Man and World 19 (1):55-72.
    Heidegger has provided a profound account of human existence in terms of the to-be-da. Even though Heidegger disregarded its brain machine basis (and even though brain scientists disregard Heidegger), the issue of the Dasein's machine basis is raised by the empirically extremely well confirmed “supervenience” of the Dasein on the brain. Since the Turing machine will not do as basis for the Dasein, as Dreyfus has shown, contemporary functionalism cannot resolve the issue. Instead an “existential functionalism,” which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  18
    Inference Rules in Nelson’s Logics, Admissibility and Weak Admissibility.Sergei Odintsov & Vladimir Rybakov - 2015 - Logica Universalis 9 (1):93-120.
    Our paper aims to investigate inference rules for Nelson’s logics and to discuss possible ways to determine admissibility of inference rules in such logics. We will use the technique offered originally for intuitionistic logic and paraconsistent minimal Johannson’s logic. However, the adaptation is not an easy and evident task since Nelson’s logics do not enjoy replacement of equivalences rule. Therefore we consider and compare standard admissibility and weak admissibility. Our paper founds algorithms for recognizing weak admissibility and admissibility (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  15
    Admissible Inference Rules in the Linear Logic of Knowledge and Time LTK.Erica Calardo - 2006 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 14 (1):15-34.
    The paper investigates admissible inference rules for the multi-modal logic LTK, which describes a combination of linear time and knowledge. This logic is semantically defined as the set of all ℒ.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Can the Maximin Principle Serve as a Basis for Climate Change Policy?Greg Bognar - 2011 - The Monist 94 (3):329-348.
    The precautionary approach has been widely considered reasonable for many issues in environmental policy, including climate change. It has also been recognized, however, that standard formulations of the precautionary principle suffer from many difficulties. An influential strategy to avoid these difficulties is to formulate a narrow version of the principle on the basis of the maximin rule. Rawls proposed that following the maximin rule can be rational under certain conditions. Defenders of this strategy argue that these conditions are approximated (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  21
    A note on globally admissible inference rules for modal and superintuitionistic logics.V. V. Rimatski & V. V. Rybakov - 2005 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 34 (2):93-99.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  11
    Intermediate logics preserving admissible inference rules of heyting calculus.Vladimir V. Rybakov - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):403-415.
    The aim of this paper is to look from the point of view of admissibility of inference rules at intermediate logics having the finite model property which extend Heyting's intuitionistic propositional logic H. A semantic description for logics with the finite model property preserving all admissible inference rules for H is given. It is shown that there are continuously many logics of this kind. Three special tabular intermediate logics λ, 1 ≥ i ≥ 3, are given which (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 982