Results for 'Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, kind‐crossing, demonstration, scientific discipline, essentialism, per se properties, definition, subordination'

979 found
Order:
  1. Aristotle on Kind‐Crossing.Philipp Steinkrüger - 2018 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 54:107-158.
    This paper concerns Aristotle's kind‐crossing prohibition. My aim is twofold. I argue that the traditional accounts of the prohibition are subject to serious internal difficulties and should be questioned. According to these accounts, Aristotle's prohibition is based on the individuation of scientific disciplines and the general kind that a discipline is about, and it says that scientific demonstrations must not cross from one discipline, and corresponding kind, to another. I propose a very different account of the prohibition. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  2.  20
    Posterior analytics II.11, 94b8-26: Final cause and demonstration.Michail Peramatzis - 2019 - Manuscrito 42 (4):323-351.
    I present the text at Posterior Analytics II.11, 94b8-26, offer a tentative translation, discuss the main construals offered in the literature, and argue for my own interpretation. Some of the general questions I discuss are the following: 1. What is the nature of the explanatory syllogisms offered as examples, especially in the case of the moving and the final cause? Are they scientific demonstrative explanations? In the case of the final cause, are they practical syllogisms? Are they productive? (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3. Essentialism and semantic theory in Aristotle: Posterior analytics, II, 7-10.Robert Bolton - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (4):514-544.
    This essay argues that aristotle's doctrine of nominal definition is his semantic theory for natural-Kind terms. It offers a new interpretation of that doctrine. On this interpretation nominal definitions are initial working theoretical accounts of natural kinds which serve as starting points for scientific inquiry. As such, Nominal definitions have existential import. They make an implicit reference to the most familiar actual instances of the kinds they define and they define the essences of those kinds by reference to those (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  4.  37
    Philoponus, On Aristotle, Posterior Analytics 1.19-34.Owen Goldin & Marije Martijn - unknown
    Aristotle described the scientific explanation of universal or general facts as deducing them through scientific demonstrations, that is, through syllogisms that met requirements he first formulated of logical validity and explanatoriness. In Chapters 19-23, he adds arguments for the further logical restrictions that scientific demonstrations can neither be indefinitely long nor infinitely extendible through the interposition of new middle terms. Chapters 24-26 argue for the superiority of universal over particular demonstration, of affirmative over negative demonstration, and of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. on Concept Formation.I. Aristotle & Posterior Analytics - 2010 - In David Charles (ed.), Definition in Greek Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 424.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Geometrical premisses in Aristotle’s Incessu animalium and kind-crossing.Lucas Angioni - 2018 - Anais de Filosofia Clássica 24 (12):53-71.
    At some point in the Incessu Animalium, Aristotle appeals to some geometrical claims in order to explain why animal progression necessarily involves the bending (of the limbs), and this appeal to geometrical claims might be taking as violating the recommendation to avoid “kind-crossing” (as found in the Posterior Analytic). But a very unclear notion of kind-crossing has been assumed in most debates. I will argue that kind-crossing in the Posterior Analytics does not mean any employment of premises from (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  7.  83
    Aristotle's De Motu Animalium and the Separability of the Sciences.Joan Kung - 1982 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (1):65-76.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Notes and Discussions ARISTOTLE'S "DE MOTU ANIMALIUM" AND THE SEPARABILITY OF THE SCIENCES In contrast to Plato's vision of a unified science of reality and with a profound effect on subsequent natural science and philosophy, Aristotle urges in the Posterior Analytics and elsewhere that scientific knowledge is to be pursued in limited, separable domains, each with its own true and necessary first principles for the explanation of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  15
    A Aristotle’s Theory of Scientific Demonstration in Posterior Analytics 1.2-9 and 1.13.Davi Bastos - 2020 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 30:03021-03021.
    I defend an interpretation of Aristotle’s _Posterior Analytics _Book I which distinguishes between two projects in different passages of that work: to explain what a given science is and to explain what properly scientific knowledge is. I present Aristotle’s theory in answer to ii, with special attention to his definition of scientific knowledge in 71b9-12 and showing how this is developed on chapters 1.2-9 and 1.13 into a solid Theory of Scientific Demonstration. The main point of this (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Aristotle’s prohibition rule on kind-crossing and the definition of mathematics as a science of quantities.Paola Cantù - 2010 - Synthese 174 (2):225-235.
    The article evaluates the Domain Postulate of the Classical Model of Science and the related Aristotelian prohibition rule on kind-crossing as interpretative tools in the history of the development of mathematics into a general science of quantities. Special reference is made to Proclus’ commentary to Euclid’s first book of Elements , to the sixteenth century translations of Euclid’s work into Latin and to the works of Stevin, Wallis, Viète and Descartes. The prohibition rule on kind-crossing formulated by Aristotle in (...) analytics is used to distinguish between conceptions that share the same name but are substantively different: for example the search for a broader genus including all mathematical objects; the search for a common character of different species of mathematical objects; and the effort to treat magnitudes as numbers. (shrink)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  10.  57
    Definition through Demonstration: The Two Types of Syllogisms in Posterior Analytics II.8.Greg Bayer - 1995 - Phronesis 40 (3):241-264.
    This paper highlights an important distinction underlying the possibility of inquiry, between first _identifying the subject of inquiry and ultimately _explaining it: that the former can be achieved before and without the latter is a presupposition of inquiry. I believe Aristotle is keenly aware of this in _Posterior Analytics, II.8, where he shows how a scientific demonstration can "manifest" a definition. I argue that such a demonstration consists of two sorts of syllogisms, one identifying the definiendum, the other explaining (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11.  34
    Definition through Demonstration: The Two Types of Syllogisms in Posterior Analytics II.8.Greg Bayer - 1995 - Phronesis 40 (3):241-264.
    This paper highlights an important distinction underlying the possibility of inquiry, between first _identifying the subject of inquiry and ultimately _explaining it: that the former can be achieved before and without the latter is a presupposition of inquiry. I believe Aristotle is keenly aware of this in _Posterior Analytics, II.8, where he shows how a scientific demonstration can "manifest" a definition. I argue that such a demonstration consists of two sorts of syllogisms, one identifying the definiendum, the other explaining (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  11
    La trattazione aristotelica delle scienze subordinate negli Analitici secondi.Piero Tarantino - 2012 - Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia 3:445-470.
    This paper explores Aristotle's remarks in Posterior Analytics on certain special disciplines that are subordinate to pure mathematical sciences. Optics, harmonics and mechanics prove their own contents by means of premises belonging to arithmetic or geometry. Even though subaltern sciences are exceptions to the prohibition on kind crossing, the premises to their demonstrations are legitimately appropriate to the relative conclusions. In order to delineate the demonstrative structure of subordinate sciences, Aristotle introduces the distinction between knowledge of a fact and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  74
    Atoms, complexes, and demonstration: Posterior analytics 96b15-25.Owen Goldin - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (4):707-727.
    There is agreement neither concerning the point that is being made in Posterior analytics 96b15–25 nor the issue Aristotle intends to address. There are two major lines of interpretation of this passage. According to one, sketched by Themistius and developed by Philoponus and Eustratius, Aristotle is primarily concerned with determining the definitions of the infimae species that fall under a certain genus. They understand Aristotle as arguing that this requires collating definitional predictions, seeing which are common to which species. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  34
    Varieties of Demonstration in Alfarabi.Riccardo Strobino - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 40 (1):42-62.
    This paper analyzes a classification of different types of demonstration introduced by Alfarabi in his Kitāb al-Burhān. Alfarabi identifies eight combinations of demonstrative syllogisms, grouped in function of the different types of per se relations expressed by their premises and conclusions, where terms are definitionally connected with one another. The list contains a total of thirty-nine moods illustrated by a rich array of examples drawn from various scientific disciplines, including arithmetic, geometry, and natural philosophy. The combinations and moods are (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  30
    Aristotle's Theory of the Unity of Science (review). [REVIEW]James H. Lesher - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (2):290-292.
    Malcolm Wilson begins his account of Aristotle’s philosophy of science by identifying a difficulty inherent in Aristotle’s general approach to understanding the nature of scientific thought: if we assume, with Aristotle, that the premises of a scientific demonstration must contain only terms predicable of a subject essentially (or per se) and ‘as such’ (or qua a particular kind of being), we risk being committed to a view of the sciences as a set of narrowly focused and unrelated areas (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  67
    Definitions and Hypotheses in Posterior Analytics 72 a 19-25 and 76 b 35-77 a 4.Blake Landor - 1981 - Phronesis 26:308.
    In An. Post. I, 2, 72 a 8ff., Aristotle gives a description of the kinds of premisses that can occur in a demonstration. It is the purpose of this paper to explore some difficulties that arise in the interpretation of this passage and of the related passage at An. Post. I, 10, 76b 33 ff.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17. Syllogisms and existence in aristotle’s posterior analytics.Joseph Karbowski - 2019 - Manuscrito 42 (4):211-242.
    In this paper I examine how Aristotle thinks syllogisms establish existence. I argue against the traditional "Instantiation" reading and in favor of an alternative "causal" or "structural" account of existential syllogisms. On my interpretation, syllogisms establish the existence of kinds by revealing that they are per se unities whose features are causally underwritten by a single cause/essence. They do so by tracing correlations between propria--peculiar, coextensive features--of the kind in question.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  49
    Explaining an Eclipse: Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics 2.1-10.Travis Butler & Owen Goldin - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (1):149.
    In Explaining an Eclipse, Owen Goldin provides a book-length treatment of the first ten chapters of book 2 of the Posterior Analytics. Goldin’s aim is to answer one question: how can an Aristotelian demonstration show anything of scientific interest if all the premises are definitions? To this question Goldin gives his undivided attention.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The Formal Cause in the Posterior Analytics.Petter Sandstad - 2016 - Filozofski Vestnik 37 (3):7-26.
    I argue that Aristotle’s account of scientific demonstrations in the Posterior Analytics is centred upon formal causation, understood as a demonstration in terms of essence (and as innocent of the distinction between form and matter). While Aristotle says that all four causes can be signified by the middle term in a demonstrative syllogism, and he discusses at some length efficient causation, much of Aristotle’s discussion is foremost concerned with the formal cause. Further, I show that Aristotle had very (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  32
    Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein. [REVIEW]James Allen - 2018 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (2):362-363.
    David Bronstein’s book tackles Aristotle’s account, as presented in the Posterior Analytics, of knowledge, or rather a privileged form of it, ‘scientific knowledge’ or ‘understanding.’ We know in this way by grasping arguments of a certain kind, demonstrations, for which reason Aristotle devotes much of his attention in the Posterior Analytics to demonstrative argument. The subject is as important as anything in Aristotle, and it presents challenges as difficult as any confronting his interpreters elsewhere, which Bronstein’s book (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. The Meaning of ΝΟΥΣ in the Posterior Analytics.James H. Lesher - 1973 - Phronesis 18 (1):44 - 68.
    In his Posterior Analytics Aristotle confronted a problem that threatened his vision of scientific knowledge as an axiomatic system: if scientific knowledge is demonstrative in character, and if the axioms of a science cannot themselves be demonstrated, then the most basic of all scientific principles will remain unknown. In the famous concluding chapter of this work (II 19), he claimed to solve this problem by distinguishing two kinds of knowledge: we cannot have epistêmê of the first (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  22.  5
    Explaining an Eclipse: Aristotle's Posterior Analytics 2.1-10. [REVIEW]Ian Bell - 1997 - Review of Metaphysics 50 (4):893-893.
    The aim of this book is twofold: first, to arrive at a coherent interpretation of Aristotle's account of definition in APo. 2.1-10; and second, to show how what Aristotle says there sheds light on the way in which per se attributes belong to their subjects.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. In what sense there is no science of corruptible things: an analysis of Posterior Analytics I 8.Lucas Angioni - 2009 - Cadernos de História E Filosofia da Ciéncia 19 (1):61-87.
    Aristotle claims that the object of scientific knowledge cannot be otherwise, and at Posterior Analytics I-8 he adds that there is no scientific knowledge of corruptible objects. These claims have been traditionally understood in terms of a strict requirement of eternal existence: objects of genuine scientific knowledge must be eternal in the sense that they must exist eternally. Sometimes the "eternal existence" is taken by scholars as equivalent to the timeless truth of universal propositions. In this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24. Aristotle's Architectonic Sciences.Monte Johnson - 2015 - In David Ebrey (ed.), Theory and Practice in Aristotle's Natural Science. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. pp. 163-186.
    Aristotle rejected the idea of a single, overarching super-science or “theory of everything”, and he presented a powerful and influential critique of scientific unity. In theory, each science observes the facts unique to its domain, and explains these by means of its own proper principles. But even as he elaborates his prohibition on kind-crossing explanations (Posterior Analytics 1.6-13), Aristotle points out that there are important exceptions—that some sciences are “under” others in that they depend for their explanations on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Comprehension, Demonstration, and Accuracy in Aristotle.Breno Zuppolini - 2020 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 58 (1):29-48.
    according to aristotle's posterior analytics, scientific expertise is composed of two different cognitive dispositions. Some propositions in the domain can be scientifically explained, which means that they are known by "demonstration", a deductive argument in which the premises are explanatory of the conclusion. Thus, the kind of cognition that apprehends those propositions is called "demonstrative knowledge".1 However, not all propositions in a scientific domain are demonstrable. Demonstrations are ultimately based on indemonstrable principles, whose knowledge is called "comprehension".2 (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26.  5
    Aristotle's Posterior analytics.Hippocrates George Aristotle & Apostle - 1976 - Oxford: Clarendon Press. Edited by Jonathan Barnes.
  27.  11
    Avicenna's Theory of Science: Logic, Metaphysics, Epistemology by Riccardo Strobino.Thérèse-Anne Druart - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (2):326-327.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Avicenna's Theory of Science: Logic, Metaphysics, Epistemology by Riccardo StrobinoThérèse-Anne DruartRiccardo Strobino. Avicenna's Theory of Science: Logic, Metaphysics, Epistemology. Oakland: University of California Press, 2021. Pp. xvi + 428. Hardback, $95.00.Strobino's remarkable book does not simply present Avicenna's theory of science; it also highlights the importance of demonstration not only for logic but also for metaphysics and epistemology. Hence, Strobino's work is essential to appreciate and better understand (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Syllogism, demonstration, and definition in Aristotle's Topics and Posterior Analytics.James Allen - 2011 - In Michael Frede, James V. Allen, Eyjólfur Kjalar Emilsson, Wolfgang-Rainer Mann & Benjamin Morison (eds.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy: Essays in Memory of Michael Frede. Summer 2011. Vol. 40. Oxford University Press. pp. 40--63.
  29. Syllogism, Demonstration, and Definition in Aristotle's Topics and Posterior Analytics.James Allen - 2011 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 40:63-90.
  30.  15
    Aristotle on dialectic and definition in scientific inquiry.Fabián Mié - 2022 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 32:e03216.
    By framing Aristotle’s dialectic in the broader context of scientific inquiry and demonstration, this paper is aimed at showing of what use the “reputable opinions” can be for grasping the principles of sciences, as declared in Topics I.2. It argues that such a use cannot imply ‒ at any stage of inquiry ‒ a replacement of the logic and intrinsic goals of demonstration by those proper to dialectic. However, it also defends a substantive (but still modest) contribution of dialectic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  77
    Posterior Analytics.Aristotle . - 1976 - Oxford University Press UK. Edited by Jonathan Barnes.
    For the second edition, the translation has been completely rewritten and the commentary has been thoroughly revised in the light of recent scholarship.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  32.  67
    Nous and Two Kinds of Epistêmê in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics.Zeev Perelmuter - 2010 - Phronesis 55 (3):228-254.
    At the beginning of Posterior Analytics 2.19 Aristotle reminds us that we cannot claim demonstrative knowledge unless we know immediate premisses, the archai of demonstrations. By the end of the chapter he explains why the cognitive state whereby we get to know archai must be Nous. In between, however, Aristotle describes the process of the acquisition of concepts, not immediate premisses. How should we understand this? There is a general agreement that it is Nous by means of which we (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  33
    Aristotle and Crossing the Boundaries between the Sciences.Lindsay Judson - 2019 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 101 (2):177-204.
    On the basis of what Aristotle says in the Posterior Analytics about how sciences are differentiated and about the impermissibility of ‘kind-crossing’, many commentators suppose that when it comes to his scientific practice, Aristotle treats the boundaries of the sciences as impermeable, so that if subject-matter X is the business of one science, it simply cannot be the business of another. I call this the impermeable boundary theory of the sciences: knowledge is divided into watertight compartments, determined by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34. From Inquiry to Demonstrative Knowledge: Essays on Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, Apeiron, vol. 43, no. 2-3.J. Lesher (ed.) - 2010 - Kelowna BC, Canada: Academic Printing and Publishing.
    This collection of essays is the product of a conference on Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics (Apo) held at the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in 2009. The essays address three main questions: (1) “How does the APo model of scientific knowledge, focused as it is on the construction of syllogisms, relate to the scientific accounts Aristotle presents elsewhere, especially in the biological treatises?’ (2) ‘How do the arguments and views presented in the APo relate to other (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Imagination.Amy Kind (ed.) - 2016 - New York: Routledge.
    Imagination occupies a central place in philosophy, going back to Aristotle. However, following a period of relative neglect there has been an explosion of interest in imagination in the past two decades as philosophers examine the role of imagination in debates about the mind and cognition, aesthetics and ethics, as well as epistemology, science and mathematics. This outstanding _Handbook_ contains over thirty specially commissioned chapters by leading philosophers organised into six clear sections examining the most important aspects of the philosophy (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  36.  78
    Nous and Two Kinds of Epistêmê in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics.Zeev Perelmuter - 2010 - Phronesis 55 (3):228-254.
    Aristotle in Physics I,1 says some strange-sounding things about how we come to know wholes and parts, universals and particulars. In explicating these, Simplicius distinguishes an initial rough cognition of a thing as a whole, an intermediate “cognition according to the definition and through the elements,” and a final cognition of how the thing's many elements are united: only this last is πιστήμη. Simplicius refers to the Theaetetus for the point about what is needed for πιστήμη and the ways that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  32
    Interpreting Aristotle's Posterior analytics in late antiquity and beyond.Frans A. J. de Haas, Mariska Leunissen & Marije Martijn (eds.) - 2010 - Boston: Brill.
    This volume collects Late Ancient, Byzantine and Medieval appropriations of Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, addressing the logic of inquiry, concept formation, the question whether metaphysics is a science, and the theory of demonstration.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  52
    Aristotle’s Theory of Language and Meaning. [REVIEW]Fred Miller - 2004 - Review of Metaphysics 57 (3):640-641.
    Part I deals with language and knowledge. Chapter 1: Plato’s Cratylus presents two opposing views of meaning—naturalism and conventionalism—and finds both wanting. Aristotle’s De Interpretatione offers a compromise between these views: the relations between written and spoken words and between spoken words and mental states are conventional, but that between mental states and the objects they represent is natural. Chapter 2: Aristotle holds a correspondence theory of truth, and he treats necessity as a property that a statement has in relation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Aristotle and the necessity of scientific knowledge.Lucas Angioni - manuscript
    This is a translation, made by myself, of the paper to be published in Portuguese in the journal Discurso, 2020, in honour of the late professor Oswaldo Porchat. I discuss what Aristotle was trying to encode when he said that the object of scientific knowledge is necessary, or that what we know (scientifically) cannot be otherwise etc. The paper is meant as a continuation of previous papers—orientated towards a book on the Posterior Analytics—and thus does not discuss in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  74
    Aristotle on definition (review).Devin Henry - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (3):pp. 478-480.
    Aristotle on Definition is an exceptional piece of scholarship. Its arguments are carefully justified, sophisticated, and far-reaching. Those interested in Aristotle's theory of definition will find this book a nice compliment to David Charles' Meaning and Essence. Whereas Charles examines Aristotle's theory of syllogistic definitions, Deslauriers focuses mainly on the concept of immediate definitions .It is impossible to do justice to the entire book. In what follows I shall attempt to isolate one of its main lines of argument to give (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  37
    Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics.David Bronstein - 2016 - Oxford: Oxford University Press UK.
    David Bronstein sheds new light on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics--one of the most important, and difficult, works in the history of western philosophy--by arguing that it is coherently structured around two themes of enduring philosophical interest: knowledge and learning. He argues that the Posterior Analytics is a sustained examination of scientific knowledge, an elegantly organized work in which Aristotle describes the mind's ascent from sense-perception of particulars to scientific knowledge of first principles. Bronstein goes on to highlight (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  42.  7
    Metaphysics as an Aristotelian science.Ian Bell - 2004 - Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.
    The dissertation's primary task is to discern to what extent the investigations contained in Aristotle's Metaphysics conform to the model of science developed in the Posterior Analytics. It concludes that the Metaphysics substantially follows the model of the Analytics in studying the causes and attributes of a specific nature, although it makes significant departures especially in its conception of the principles of being and substance. ;Two introductory chapters discuss respectively Aristotle's conception of science in the Analytics and the problems (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43. Some remarks against non-epistemic accounts of immediate premises in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics.Breno Zuppolini - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):29-43.
    Most interpretations of Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics believe that the term ‘ameson’ is used to describe the principles or foundations of a given system of justification or explanation as epistemically prior to or more fundamental than the other propositions in the system. Epistemic readings (as I shall call them) arguably constitute a majority in the secondary literature. This predominant view has been challenged by Robin Smith (1986) and Michael Ferejohn (1994; 2013), who propose interpretations that should be classified as non-epistemic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Aristotle on multiple demonstration.Elena Comay del Junco - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (5):902-920.
    How many scientific demonstrations can a single phenomenon have? This paper argues that, according to Aristotle's theory of scientific knowledge as laid out in the Posterior Analytics, a single conclusion may be demonstrated via more than one explanatory middle term. I also argue that this model of multiple demonstration is put into practice in the biological writings. This paper thereby accomplishes two related goals: it clarifies certain relatively obscure passages of the Posterior Analytics and uses them (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Attempts by Avicenna and Ibn al-Nafīs to Expand the Field of the Transference of Demonstration in the Context of the Relationship Between Geometry and Medicine.Bakhadir Musametov - 2021 - Nazariyat, Journal for the History of Islamic Philosophy and Sciences 7 (1):37-71.
    This paper aims to deal with the disputes on transferring demonstration between the various sciences in the context of the medicine-geometry relationship. According to Aristotle’s metabasis-prohibition, these two sciences should be located in separate compartments due to the characteristics of their subject-matter. However, a thorough analysis of the critical passage in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics on circular wounds forces a revision of the boundaries of the interactions between sciences, since subsequently Avicenna, on the grounds of this passage, would widen the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Aristotle’s contrast between episteme and doxa in its context (Posterior Analytics I.33).Lucas Angioni - 2019 - Manuscrito 42 (4):157-210.
    Aristotle contrasts episteme and doxa through the key notions of universal and necessary. These notions have played a central role in Aristotle’s characterization of scientific knowledge in the previous chapters of APo. They are not spelled out in APo I.33, but work as a sort of reminder that packs an adequate characterization of scientific knowledge and thereby gives a highly specified context for Aristotle’s contrast between episteme and doxa. I will try to show that this context introduces a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  47.  28
    Posterior Analytics.Jonathan Barnes (ed.) - 1994 - Oxford University Press on Demand.
    BL Features of the new edition: The translation has been completely rewritten, and the commentary thoroughly revised in the light of recent scholarship There is an additional glossary, and extended bibliography The Posterior Analytics contains some of Aristotle's most influential thoughts in logic, epistemology, metaphysics, and the philosophy of science. The first book expounds and develops the notions of a demonstrative argument and of a formal, axiomatized science; the second discusses a cluster of problems raised by the axioms or (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  48.  8
    VII. Definitions, I: The Per Se.Richard D. McKirahan - 1992 - In Principles and Proofs: Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstrative Science. Princeton University Press. pp. 80-102.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  4
    The Concept of Work Ability.Per-Anders Tengland - 2011 - Journal of Occupational Rehabilitation 21 (2):275-285.
    Introduction: The concept of ” work ability” is central for many sciences, especially for those related to working life and to rehabilitation. It is one of the important concepts in legislation regulating sickness insurance. How the concept is defined therefore has important normative implications. The concept is, however, often not sufficiently well defined. Aim and Method: The objective of this paper is to clarify, through conceptual analysis, what the concept can and should mean, and to propose a useful definition for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  17
    Should Animals Have Political Rights?Per-Anders Svärd - 2022 - Journal of Animal Ethics 12 (2):210-212.
    A common view of politics is that it is reducible to applied ethics. If politics, in a classic phrase, is about “who gets what, when, and how,” then the task of normative political theory would simply be to tell us who is morally entitled to get whatever the “what” is in that statement.This view, however, can easily reduce politics to a dizzying vortex of actions to assess from an ethical perspective. And while the task of moral philosophy may be precisely (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 979