Results for 'Aristotelian Predication'

988 found
Order:
  1.  24
    The politics of modern reason: Politics, anti-politics and norms on continental philosophy, James Bohman.Quantification Parts & Aristotelian Predication - 1999 - The Monist 82 (2).
  2. Aristotelian predicables, universality and realism. The logic of comparison in topics as denying the view that Aristotle was a realist.Giampaolo Abbate - 2011 - Philosophica -- Revista Do Departamento de Filosofia da Faculdade de Letras de Lisboa 38:7-32.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Aristotelian predication, Augustine and the trinity.George Rudebusch - 1989 - The Thomist 53 (4):587 - 597.
    AUGUSTINE WISHED TO DEFEND AND MAKE AS INTELLIGIBLE AS POSSIBLE THE CHRISTIAN DOCTRINE OF THE TRINITY. I SHOW HOW AUGUSTINE WORKS WITH AN ARISTOTELIAN MODEL OF PREDICATION, DERIVES AN INCOMPLETENESS RESULT WITHIN THE STANDARD FORMS OF PREDICATION, AND ACCEPTS, WITH SOME QUALIFICATION, A NONSTANDARD FORM OF PREDICATION USED BY ARISTOTLE FOR PREDICATING PRIMARY SUBSTANCE OF MATTER.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  50
    Parts, Quantification and Aristotelian Predication.Mario Mignucci - 2000 - The Monist 83 (1):3-21.
    Reading through the Corpus Aristotelicum we come across a group of expressions meant to indicate predicative relations, which lead us to think that Aristotle connected predication to a part-whole relation. He frequently calls the ‘εἴδη’, “species”, ‘μέρη’, “parts”, of their genera. More generally, the universal is said to contain that of which it is true. In a parallel way, what is contained by something is also what is under something else. Again, it is quite common for him to consider (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5. An Aristotelian Theory of Predication?David Bostock - 2004 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27:141-75.
  6. An Aristotelian Theory of Predication?David Bostock - 2004 - In David Sedley (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxvii: Winter 2004. Clarendon Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7. Aristotelian-Scholastic ontology and predication in the Port-Royal logic.Ignacio Angelelli - 1998 - Medioevo 24:283-310.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  17
    On the interpretations of Aristotelian categorical propositions in the predicate calculus.S. Jaśkowski - 1969 - Studia Logica 24 (1):173-174.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  58
    On the interpretations of Aristotelian categorical propositions in the predicate calculus.Stanisław Jaśkowski - 1969 - Studia Logica 24 (1):161-172.
  10.  23
    Metaphysics: Aristotelian, Scholastic, Analytic.Lukás Novák, Daniel D. Novotný, Prokop Sousedík & David Svoboda (eds.) - 2012 - Ontos Verlag.
    Throughout the greater part of the twentieth century, both in the analytic and continental traditions, metaphysics was deemed to be passé. The last few decades, however, have witnessed a remarkable growth of interest among analytic philosophers in various traditional metaphysical topics, such as modality, truth, causality, etc. which resulted in the emergence of various forms of analytic metaphysics. The new forms of metaphysics differ from its traditional forms mostly in their methodology and in the range of proposed solutions to particular (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Predication, Things, and Kinds in Aristotle’s Metaphysics.Frank A. Lewis - 2011 - Phronesis 56 (4):350-387.
    What in Aristotle corresponds, in whole or (more likely) in part, to our contemporary notion of predication? This paper sketches counterparts in Aristotle's text to our theories of expression and of truth, and on this basis inquires into his treatment of sentences assigning an individual to its kinds. In some recent accounts, the Metaphysics offers a fresh look at such sentences in terms of matter and form, in contrast to the simpler theory on offer in the Categories . I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  14
    Kneale W.. Is existence a predicate? Aristotelian Society, supplemetary volume XV, London , pp. 154–174.C. H. Langford - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):60-61.
  13.  11
    W. Kneale. Is existence a predicate? Aristotelian Society, supplemetary volume XV, London (1936), pp. 154–174.C. H. Langford & W. V. Quine - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):60-61.
  14.  8
    Predication and Ontology: Studies and Texts on Avicennian and Post-Avicennian Readings of Aristotle’s ›Categories‹.Alexander Kalbarczyk - 2018 - Berlin: De Gruyter.
    In Predication and Ontology A. Kalbarczyk provides the first monograph-length study of the Arabic reception of Aristotle’s Categories. At the center of attention is the critical reappraisal of that treatise by Ibn Sīnā, better known in the Latin West as Avicenna. Ibn Sīnā’s reading of the Categories is examined in the context of his wider project of rearranging the transmitted body of philosophical knowledge. Against the background of the late ancient commentary tradition and subsequent exegetical efforts, Ibn Sīnā’s Kitāb (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  3
    Categorial predication.E. J. Lowe - 2013 - In David S. Oderberg (ed.), Classifying Reality. Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 5–22.
    When, for example, we say of something that it ‘is an object’, or ‘is an event’, or ‘is a property’, we are engaging in categorial predication: we are assigning something to a certain ontological category. Ontologicalcategorization is clearly a type of classification, but it differs radically from the types of classification that are involved in thetaxonomic practices of empirical sciences, as when a physicist saysof a certain particle that it ‘is an electron’, or when a zoologist saysof a certain (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  20
    The Predicative Role of ‘Being Good’ in Aristotle.Francesca Alesse - 2022 - Ancient Philosophy 42 (1):171-189.
    The article proposes a renewed analysis of the texts in which Aristotle claims that the term ‘good’ is spoken of in many ways and more precisely in as many ways as there are categories. After a revision of the traditional interpretations, a new reading of the texts is advanced in the light of the theory of predication described in Top. 103 b20-38 and Metaph. 1017 a7-30. The conclusion is that in the Aristotelian passages on the multivocity of ‘good’, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. The Aristotelian Alternative to Humean Bundles and Lockean Bare Particulars: Lowe and Loux on Material Substance .Robert Allen - manuscript
    Must we choose between reducing material substances to collections of properties, a’ la Berkeley and Hume or positing bare particulars, in the manner of Locke? Having repudiated the notion that a substance could simply be a collection of properties existing on their own, is there a viable alternative to the Lockean notion of a substratum, a being essentially devoid of character? E.J. Lowe and Michael Loux would answer here in the affirmative. Both recommend hylomorphism as an upgrade on the metaphysics (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Aristotelian versus Stoic logic.J. Banas - 2003 - Filozofia 58 (8):551-563.
    This paper deals with Aristotelian and Stoic logic. In the first part the author writes about the history of logic and shows, why Stoic logic had not been studied properly from the Middle Ages up to the beginning of the 20th century, when an increasing interest in the study of Stoic logic is visible. The paper describes the character of Aristotelian and Stoic logic respectively. Stoic logic is first introduced as a system of propositional logic. On this basis (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  39
    Reviews - Fred Sommers. The ordinary language tree. Mind, n.s. vol. 68 , pp. 160–185. - Fred Sommers. Predicability. Philosophy in America, edited by Max Black, Cornell University Press, Ithaca1965, pp. 262–281. - L. R. Reinhardt. Dualism and categories. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, n.s. vol. 66 , pp. 71–92. - David Massie. Sommers' tree theory, a reply to de Sousa. The Journal of philosophy, vol. 64 , pp. 185–193. - Susan Haack. Equivocality, a discussion of Sommers' views. Analysis , vol. 28 no. 5 , pp. 159–165. - R. van Straaten. Sommers' rule and equivocality. Analysis , vol. 29 no. 2 , pp. 58–61. - Dan Passell. On Sommers' logic of sense and nonsense. Mind, n.s. vol. 78 , pp. 132–133. - A. G. Elgood. Sommers' rules of sense. The philosophical quarterly, vol. 20 , pp. 166–169. [REVIEW]Jonathan Bennett - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (4):666-670.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  42
    Predicating Forms of Matter in Aristotle's "Metaphysics".Carl Page - 1985 - Review of Metaphysics 39 (1):57 - 82.
    ON A GENERAL READING of the Metaphysics and the treatises of the so-called Organon, the types of assertion which Aristotle would allow as genuine predications seem relatively straightforward. According to the Categories, for instance, a species is characteristically predicated of the individuals falling under it, while genera and differentiae are predicated both of the relevant species and their associated individuals. The predicates are, in these instances, universals in a familiar Aristotelian sense. Furthermore, these intra-categorial predications, such as "Socrates is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  13
    The gap between Parmenides’ argument on Being and his cosmology in the Aristotelian account.Bruno Loureiro Conte - 2023 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 33:03325-03325.
    In some of the Aristotelian accounts, Parmenides’ thesis is construed in opposition to the philosophy of nature; on the other hand, he is also depicted, in a different context, as a cosmologist, to whom the Stagirite (and a long tradition afterwards, ending with Simplicius) ascribes a theory of becoming and its principles. In this paper, I exhibit and analyse the relevant passages from Physics I 1-3, Metaphysics I 3 and 5 and On generation and corruption I 3, providing an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  46
    The Classical Aristotelian Hexagon Versus the Modern Duality Hexagon.Hans Smessaert - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (1-2):171-199.
    Peters and Westerståhl (Quantifiers in Language and Logic, 2006), and Westerståhl (New Perspectives on the Square of Opposition, 2011) draw a crucial distinction between the “classical” Aristotelian squares of opposition and the “modern” Duality squares of opposition. The classical square involves four opposition relations, whereas the modern one only involves three of them: the two horizontal connections are fundamentally distinct in the Aristotelian case (contrariety, CR vs. subcontrariety, SCR) but express the same Duality relation of internal negation (SNEG). (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  23.  93
    Aristotelian syllogisms and generalized quantifiers.Dag Westerståhl - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (4):577-585.
    The paper elaborates two points: i) There is no principal opposition between predicate logic and adherence to subject-predicate form, ii) Aristotle's treatment of quantifiers fits well into a modern study of generalized quantifiers.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  24. The Aristotelian-Kantian and Hegelian Approaches to Categories.Chong-Fuk Lau - 2008 - The Owl of Minerva 40 (1):77-114.
    This paper analyzes and compares the doctrines of categories of Aristotle, Kant and Hegel, each of which is first discussed separately. The paper explains the essential double perspective of the problem, showing how a logico-linguistic analysis of the form of rational discourse serves for them as an important clue to ontological problems. Although Aristotle and Kant’s doctrines differ significantly, they both endorse a kind of isomorphism between language/thought and reality. By contrast, Hegel, who takes a critical attitude toward the capability (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  24
    Some ontological problems concerning predication.Marek Rosiak - 1998 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 6:109.
    The Aristotelian double characterization of a primary substanceexploits the difference between the part-whole relation and the non-linguisticrelation of predication. A problem arises whether and how the second relationcould be reduced to something else. Such a reduction is explicitly declared orat least implicitly assumed in all version of conceptualism and nominalism.The moderate realism is often interpreted as a reductionism of this kindbut such interpretations do not seem corect. Only the so called resemblancetheory can be regarded as a successful attempt (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  17
    Geach, Aristotle and Predicate Logics.Alex Orenstein - 2015 - Philosophical Investigations 38 (1-2):96-114.
    Geach's account of the Aristotelian logic of categorical sentences supplemented the views shared by Frege, Russell, Quine and others. I argue that this particular predicate logic approach and Geach's points apply to only one variety of natural language categorical sentences. For example, it takes the universal categorical as a universal conditional “If anything is a man, then it is mortal”. A different natural language form can and should be invoked: “Every man is a mortal.” Employing special restricted quantifiers in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  87
    IX—Presupposition, Disagreement, and Predicates of Taste.Josh Parsons - 2013 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 113 (2pt2):163-173.
    ABSTRACTI offer a simple‐minded analysis of presupposition in which if a sentence has a presupposition, then both that sentence and its negation logically entail the presupposition; and in which sentence with failed presuppositions are neither true nor false. This account naturally generates an analysis of what it takes to disagree and what it takes to be at fault in a disagreement. A simple generalization gives rise to the possibility of disagreements in which no party is at fault, as is required (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  28. Causality and attribution in an Aristotelian Theory.Srećko Kovač - 2015 - In Arnold Koslow & Arthur Buchsbaum (eds.), The Road to Universal Logic: Festschrift for 50th Birthday of Jean-Yves Béziau, vol. 1. Cham, Heidelberg, etc.: Springer-Birkhäuser. pp. 327-340.
    Aristotelian causal theories incorporate some philosophically important features of the concept of cause, including necessity and essential character. The proposed formalization is restricted to one-place predicates and a finite domain of attributes (without individuals). Semantics is based on a labeled tree structure, with truth defined by means of tree paths. A relatively simple causal prefixing mechanism is defined, by means of which causes of propositions and reasoning with causes are made explicit. The distinction of causal and factual explanation are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  43
    On an aristotelian theory of universals.Arnold Cusmariu - 1979 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 57 (1):51 – 58.
    A theory purporting to solve the problem of universals must be able to explain predication, recurrence, and classification. How Platonism does this is well known. Here I take a hard look at an attempt by M.J. Cresswell to give an Aristotelian answer and show it to be a complete and utter failure. The answer does not eliminate commitment to universals and it is only half an answer anyway because it does not cover relational predicates, an omission that Russell (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30.  25
    The structure of Aristotelian logic.James Wilkinson Miller - 1938 - London,: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner & co..
    Originally published in 1938. This compact treatise is a complete treatment of Aristotle’s logic as containing negative terms. It begins with defining Aristotelian logic as a subject-predicate logic confining itself to the four forms of categorical proposition known as the A, E, I and O forms. It assigns conventional meanings to these categorical forms such that subalternation holds. It continues to discuss the development of the logic since the time of its founder and address traditional logic as it existed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  31. The Structure of Aristotelian Logic.James Wilkinson Miller - 1938 - London,: Routledge.
    Originally published in 1938. This compact treatise is a complete treatment of Aristotle’s logic as containing negative terms. It begins with defining Aristotelian logic as a subject-predicate logic confining itself to the four forms of categorical proposition known as the _A, E, I _and_ O_ forms. It assigns conventional meanings to these categorical forms such that subalternation holds. It continues to discuss the development of the logic since the time of its founder and address traditional logic as it existed (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  44
    Goodness: Attributive and predicative.Michael-John Turp - 2016 - Les ateliers de l'éthique/The Ethics Forum 11 (2-3):70-87.
    Michael-John Turp | : There is little consensus concerning the truth or reference conditions for evaluative terms such as “good” and “bad.” In his paper “Good and Evil,” Geach proposed that we distinguish between attributive and predicative uses of “good.” Foot, Thomson, Kraut, and others have put this distinction to use when discussing basic questions of value theory. In §§1-2, I outline Geach’s proposal and argue that attributive evaluation depends on a prior grasp of the kind of thing that is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Temporal parts and complex predicates.Thomas Sattig - 2002 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 102 (3):279–286.
    Those who believe that ordinary things have temporal as well as spatial parts must give an account of the truth conditions of temporally modified predications of the form ‘a is F at t ’ in terms of temporal parts. I will argue that the friend of temporal parts is committed to an account of temporal predication that is incompatible with the classical principle of predicate abstraction.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34. Symposium: Is Existence a Predicate?W. Kneale & G. E. Moore - 1936 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 15 (1):154-188.
  35.  56
    Existential Assumptions for Aristotelian Logic.Phillip H. Wiebe - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Research 16:321-328.
    This paper addresses the question of what existential assumptions are needed for the Aristotelian interpretation of the relationships between the four categorical propositions. The particular relationships in question are those unique to the Aristotelian logic, namely, contrariety, subcontrariety, subaltemation, conversion by limitation, and contraposition by limitation. The views of several recent authors of logic textbooks are surveyed. While most construe the Aristotelian logic as capable of being preserved by assuming that the subject class has a member, Irving (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  20
    Existential Assumptions for Aristotelian Logic.Phillip H. Wiebe - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Research 16:321-328.
    This paper addresses the question of what existential assumptions are needed for the Aristotelian interpretation of the relationships between the four categorical propositions. The particular relationships in question are those unique to the Aristotelian logic, namely, contrariety, subcontrariety, subaltemation, conversion by limitation, and contraposition by limitation. The views of several recent authors of logic textbooks are surveyed. While most construe the Aristotelian logic as capable of being preserved by assuming that the subject class has a member, Irving (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  1
    The Interpretation(s) of Predication.Uwe Meixner - 2012 - In Lukás Novák, Daniel D. Novotný, Prokop Sousedík & David Svoboda (eds.), Metaphysics: Aristotelian, Scholastic, Analytic. Ontos Verlag. pp. 229-246.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. What Is a Perfect Syllogism in Aristotelian Syllogistic?Theodor Ebert - 2015 - Ancient Philosophy 35 (2):351-374.
    The question as to what makes a perfect Aristotelian syllogism a perfect one has long been discussed by Aristotelian scholars. G. Patzig was the first to point the way to a correct answer: it is the evidence of the logical necessity that is the special feature of perfect syllogisms. Patzig moreover claimed that the evidence of a perfect syllogism can be seen for Barbara in the transitivity of the a-relation. However, this explanation would give Barbara a different status (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39.  38
    A Cube of Opposition for Predicate Logic.Jørgen Fischer Nilsson - 2020 - Logica Universalis 14 (1):103-114.
    The traditional square of opposition is generalized and extended to a cube of opposition covering and conveniently visualizing inter-sentential oppositions in relational syllogistic logic with the usual syllogistic logic sentences obtained as special cases. The cube comes about by considering Frege–Russell’s quantifier predicate logic with one relation comprising categorical syllogistic sentence forms. The relationships to Buridan’s octagon, to Aristotelian modal logic, and to Klein’s 4-group are discussed.GraphicThe photo shows a prototype sculpture for the cube.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. From Plato to Frege: Paradigms of Predication in the History of Ideas. [REVIEW]Uwe Meixner - 2009 - Metaphysica 10 (2):199-214.
    One of the perennial questions of philosophy concerns the simple statements which say that an object is so and so or that such and such objects are so and so related: simple predicative statements. Do such statements have an ontological basis, and if so, what is that basis? The answer to this question determines—or in any case, is expressive of—a specific fundamental outlook on the world. In the course of the history of Western philosophy, various philosophers have given various answers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  12
    Temporal Parts and Complex Predicates.Thomas Sattig - 2002 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 102 (3):279-286.
  42.  8
    Symposium: Is Existence a Predicate?W. Kneale & G. E. Moore - 1936 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 15 (1):154-188.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  14
    Muslim Philosophers on Affirmative Judgement with Negative Predicate.Seyyed Mohammad Ali Hodjati - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (S3):749-780.
    According to Aristotelian logic, in categorical logic, there are three kinds of judgements (qaḍīyya): affirmative, negative, and metathetic (ma‘dūla). Khūnajī, a famous Muslim logician in the 13th century, introduces a different judgement (or statement) entitled “affirmative judgement with the negative predicate” (mūjiba al-sāliba al-maḥmūl; henceforth, ANP judgement). Although in the Arabic language, formally, ANP judgement is similar to definite negative (sāliba muḥaṣṣala) and also metathetic judgements, the way of its construction is different from both of them and its truth (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  77
    Whatever Binds the World’s Innermost Core Together Outline of a General Theory of Ontic Predication.Luc Schneider - 2013 - Axiomathes 23 (2):419-442.
    Nexuses such as exemplification are the fundamental ties that structure reality as a whole. They are “formal” in the sense of constituting the form, not the matter of reality and they are “transcendental” inasmuch as they transcend the categorial distinctions between the denizens of reality, including that between existents and non-existents. I shall advocate a moderately particularist view about (external) nexuses and argue that it provides not only the best solution to Bradley’s regress, but also an elegant account of symmetrical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  49
    Empirical evidence of Aristotle’s concepts of predication and opposition.Joseph F. Rychlak - 1990 - Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 10 (1):45-50.
    In the past four or five years I have been especially dependent on Aristotle's writings as I have initiated a series of experiments that can legitimately be called empirical efforts to prove Aristotelian conceptions to be true. In actuality, of course, I am trying to prove my own theory to be true—that is, worthy of consideration because it is consistent with observed human actions. However, by extension, I am surely seeking evidence for Aristotle's image of human cognition. There are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  12
    Empirical evidence of Aristotle’s concepts of predication and opposition.Joseph F. Rychlak - 1990 - Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 10 (1):45-50.
    In the past four or five years I have been especially dependent on Aristotle's writings as I have initiated a series of experiments that can legitimately be called empirical efforts to prove Aristotelian conceptions to be true. In actuality, of course, I am trying to prove my own theory to be true—that is, worthy of consideration because it is consistent with observed human actions. However, by extension, I am surely seeking evidence for Aristotle's image of human cognition. There are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  15
    XI—Rules, Moral Rules and the Subjects of Moral Predicates.Glenn Langford - 1969 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 69 (1):187-206.
    Glenn Langford; XI—Rules, Moral Rules and the Subjects of Moral Predicates, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 69, Issue 1, 1 June 1969, Pages 187–.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Robert litteral.Rhetorical Predicates & Time Topology In Anggor - 1972 - Foundations of Language 8:391.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  87
    Substance and Predication in Aristotle by Frank Lewis. [REVIEW]Gareth B. Matthews - 1993 - Review of Metaphysics 46 (3):624-625.
    In this ambitious and challenging book, Frank Lewis aims to make clear the relation between the early metaphysical theory of Aristotle's Categories and the later theory of the central books of Aristotle's Metaphysics; to show, with each theory, how Aristotle positions himself in relation to Plato's theory of Forms; and to locate Aristotle's treatment of purely accidental entities within a more general Aristotelian theory of compounds.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. An intensional Leibniz semantics for aristotelian logic.Klaus Glashoff - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (2):262-272.
    Since Freges terms were meant to refer always to sets, that is, entities composed of individuals. Classical philosophy up to Leibniz and Kant had a different view on this questionBegriffes syntaxhighercorresponding to the idea which Leibniz used in the construction of his characteristic numbers. Thus, this paper is an addendum to Corcorans theory via predicate logic.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
1 — 50 / 988