Results for 'Analytic Proposition'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  29
    Logically Analytic Propositions: A Posteriori?Mark Textor - 2001 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 18 (1):91 - 113.
  2.  28
    Analytic propositions and philosophical truths.Robert E. Gahringer - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (17):481-502.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  45
    The Analytic Proposition Underlying Kantian Hypothetical Imperatives.Alexandra Newton - 2017 - Kant Studien 108 (4):543-567.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Kant-Studien Jahrgang: 108 Heft: 4 Seiten: 543-567.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Analysis, Analytic Propositions, and Real Definitions.Donald C. Williams - 1935 - Analysis 3 (5):75 - 80.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  43
    Analytic method and Analytic Propositions in Kant's Groundwork.Michael H. McCarthy - 1976 - Dialogue 15 (4):565-582.
    At the beginning of the third Section of the Groundwork, Kant appears to state the synthetic a priori proposition which it is the business of that Section to justify. It is: “An absolutely good will is one whose maxim can always have as its content itself considered as a universal law.” I shall contend that a consideration of Kant's use of analytic method shows that he is committed to regard this proposition not as synthetic, but rather as (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Protasis in Prior Analytics: Proposition or Premise.J. Corcoran & G. Boger - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):151 - 2.
    The word pro-tasis is etymologically a near equivalent of pre-mise, pro-position, and ante-cedent—all having positional, relational connotations now totally absent in contemporary use of proposition. Taking protasis for premise, Aristotle’s statement (24a16) -/- A protasis is a sentence affirming or denying something of something…. -/- is not a definition of premise—intensionally: the relational feature is absent. Likewise, it is not a general definition of proposition—extensionally: it is too narrow. This paper explores recent literature on these issues.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  70
    Bolzano's Definition of Analytic Propositions.Yehoshoua Bar-Hillel - 1950 - Theoria 16 (2):91-117.
  8.  27
    Deductive foundation and analytic propositions.Ludwik Borkowski - 1966 - Studia Logica 19 (1):59 - 74.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  38
    Are some analytic propositions contingent?S. F. Barker - 1966 - Journal of Philosophy 63 (20):637-639.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  8
    Are There Analytic Propositions?Reginald Jackson - 1941 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 (2):68-68.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  29
    Are there Analytic Propositions?Reginald Jackson - 1939 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 39 (1):185-206.
  12.  43
    Analytical philosophy and analytical propositions.Irving M. Copi - 1953 - Philosophical Studies 4 (6):87 - 93.
  13.  6
    Jackson Reginald. Are there analytic propositions? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 39 , pp. 185–206.C. H. Langford - 1941 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 (2):68-68.
  14.  21
    Kant’s Definition on Analytic Proposition.R. K. Gupta - 1976 - International Studies in Philosophy 8:115-120.
  15.  7
    Kant’s Definition on Analytic Proposition.R. K. Gupta - 1976 - International Studies in Philosophy 8:115-120.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Implicit thoughts: Quine, Frege and Kant on analytic propositions.Verena Mayer - 2003 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 66 (1):61-90.
    Quine criticised the semantic notion of analyticity that is often attributed to Frege and Kant for presupposing an essentialist theory of meaning. In what follows I trace back the notion from Quine via Carnap to Frege and Kant, and eventually examine Kant's distinction between analytic and synthetic judgements in more detail. It turns out that the so called Frege-Kant-notion of analyticity can not be attributed to Kant. In contrast, Kant had a distinctly pragmatic notion of analytic judgements. According (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  47
    Questions of Form: Logic and Analytic Proposition From Kant to Carnap.Joëlle Proust - 1989 - Minneapolis, MN, USA: Univ of Minnesota Press.
  18.  10
    Questions of Form: Logic and Analytic Proposition From Kant to Carnap.Anastasios Albert Brenner (ed.) - 1989 - Minneapolis, MN, USA: Univ of Minnesota Press.
    _Questions of Form _was first published in 1989. Minnesota Archive Editions uses digital technology to make long-unavailable books once again accessible, and are published unaltered from the original University of Minnesota Press editions. In _Questions on Form_, Joelle Proust traces the concept of the analytic proposition from Kant's development of the notion down to its place in the work of Rudolf Carnap, a founder of logical empiricism and a key figure in contemporary analytic philosophy. Using a method (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  42
    Is "you can't fool all of the people all of the time" an analytical proposition?D. A. Rees - 1951 - Mind 60 (237):97-99.
    No categories
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  48
    Questions of Form: Logic and the Analytic Proposition from Kant to Carnap.Michael Friedman - 1992 - Noûs 26 (4):532-542.
  21.  8
    Bar-Hillel Y.. Bolzano's definition of analytic propositions. Methodos, Bd. 2 Heft 5 , S. 32–55; zugleich Theoria, Bd. 16 , S. 91–117. [REVIEW]Heinrich Scholz - 1952 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):119-122.
  22.  14
    Review: Y. Bar-Hillel, Bolzano's Definition of Analytic Propositions. [REVIEW]Heinrich Scholz - 1952 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):119-122.
  23. Joëlle Proust, Questions of Form: Logic and the Analytic Proposition from Kant to Carnap, trans. Anastasios Albert Brenner. [REVIEW]Frederick P. Van De Pitte - 1991 - Philosophy in Review 11 (1):60-62.
  24.  11
    Review: Reginald Jackson, Are There Analytic Propositions? [REVIEW]C. H. Langford - 1941 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 (2):68-68.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  72
    Analytic truths and grammatical propositions.Severin Schroeder - 2009 - In P. M. S. Hacker, Hans-Johann Glock & John Hyman (eds.), Wittgenstein and Analytic Philosophy: Essays for P. M. S. Hacker. Oxford University Press. pp. 83-108.
  26. Analytic a posteriori propositions.Virgil C. Aldrich - 1968 - Analysis 28 (6):200-202.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  5
    Propositional Analyis [review of Graham Stevens, The Russellian Origins of Analytical Philosophy ].David Blitz - 2009 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 29 (1):76-84.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:76 Reviews PROPOSITIONAL ANALYSIS David Blitz Philosophy Dept. and Peace Studies / Central Connecticut State U. New Britain, ct 06050, usa [email protected] Graham Stevens. The Russellian Origins of Analytical Philosophy: Bertrand Russell and the Unity of the Proposition. London and New York: Routledge, 2005. Pp. xii, 185. isbn: 978-0-415-36044-9 (hb). £80.00. us$155.95. Graham Stevens has written a short book on a diUcult subject: the unity of the (...). While the title of the volume is The Russellian Origins of Analytic Philosophy, the underlying theme is the comparatively little discussed problem of how the elements of a proposition come together to form a unity, as indicated in the book’s subtitle: “Bertrand Russell and the Unity of the Prop­ osition”. Stevens traces this concept, as a unifying thread or “central concern”, throughout Russell’s many philosophies which constitute for Stevens a “consis­ tent and constantly evolving philosophy” (p. 2) stretching from the earliest log­ ical writings to the later works of the 1930s and 1940s. This is an important and well written volume, which Russellians should have in their personal and uni­ versity libraries. That the “unity of the proposition” is a problem at all requires the reader to return to the neo-Hegelian idealism which Russell encountered as a student at Cambridge.1 Russell, inXuenced by Peano and Frege, broke with the doctrine of internal relations, defended by Bradley and others, according to which external relations are unreal and false appearance. However, an important element of idealism remains even during the Principia period, due to Russell’s continued belief that a proposition is a non-linguistic, non-mental, abstract entity; these elements are all of the same ontological kind, which can be identiWed through analysis and recombined so that their synthesis reconstitutes the original “unity of the proposition”. This turns out to be a very tall order which will occupy Russell for nearly half a century. Consider the standard example Russell gives: “Desdemona loves Cassio”. According to Russell, this proposition (independently of its truth or falsity) actually contains its “simple constituents”z—zwith “Desdemona” and “Cassio” being things and “loves” a concept. Russell, as a founder of analytic philosophy, has to defend the legitimacy of this analysis from the claim that it has reduced 1 Chapter 1: “Russell, Frege and the Analysis of Unities”. December 2, 2009 (5:28 pm) E:\CPBR\RUSSJOUR\TYPE2901\russell 29,1 060 red.wpd E:\CPBR\RUSSJOUR\TYPE2901\russell 29,1 060 red.wpd Reviews 77 the structured unity of the proposition into an unstructured set of parts (or heap) where the original order of combination has been lost. The problem of is that merely listing “Desdemona”, “Cassio” and “loves” does not indicate the way in which the terms were originally combined or re­ lated. For reasons to be made clear later, this is referred to in the literature as the “narrow order problem”. In particular, the question arises as to how analysis enables us to assert that it is Desdemona who loves Cassio (supposing this to be the case), rather than the other way around (since love may not be requited). Stevens deals with logical form in a later chapter devoted to the problem of belief statements, but the notion applies here as well: analysis seems to have skip­ ped the logical form, the way in which the constituents are combined. But if the logical form is included, then there seems to be an extra constituent in the prop­ osition not given by direct inspection, and analysis would appear to have added something above and beyond what was there before the analysis. Adding linking relations to indicate how the components were originally combined does not help either. If there is some relation Lz which relates “Desdemona” and “loves” and another relation Rz which relates “loves” and “Cassio”, then there are Wve constituents, not three. Moreover, there is now room for inWnite regress, with a relation L2 linking “Desdemona” and L, R2 linking “loves” and “Cassio”, and so on. But without adding these additional items, there is an apparent failure of an­ alysis to fully provide the order of the elements present in the original... (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. The Russellian Origins of Analytical Philosophy: Bertrand Russell and the Unity of the Proposition.Graham Stevens - 2005 - New York: Routledge.
    This monograph reappraises the role of Bertrand Russell's philosophical works in establishing the analytical tradition in philosophy. It's main aims are to: * improve our understanding of the history of analytical philosophy * engage in the important disputes surrounding the interpretation of Russell's philosophy * make a contribution to central issues in current analytical philosophy. Drawing extensively from Russell's less well known and unpublished works, this book is a welcome addition to the literature and will undoubtedly find a place on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  29.  11
    Indeterminate Propositions in Prior Analytics I.41.Marko Malink - 2009 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 12 (1):165-189.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Locke, Analyticity and Trifling Propositions.R. Meyers - 1994 - Locke Studies 25.
  31.  13
    Analytic and Synthetic Propositions and Mathematical Logic.N. O. Lossky - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (4):291-291.
  32. An Analytic Approach to Dewey's Theory of Propositions and Warranted Assertions.Kamala Kuraari - 1984 - In R. Choudhury (ed.), Philosophy and Language: A Collection of Papers. Capital Pub. House. pp. 94.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  19
    Analytic and Synthetic Propositions.R. K. Gupta - 1982 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 64 (1):56-63.
  34. On the Quinean-analyticity of mathematical propositions.Gregory Lavers - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 159 (2):299-319.
    This paper investigates the relation between Carnap and Quine’s views on analyticity on the one hand, and their views on philosophical analysis or explication on the other. I argue that the stance each takes on what constitutes a successful explication largely dictates the view they take on analyticity. I show that although acknowledged by neither party (in fact Quine frequently expressed his agreement with Carnap on this subject) their views on explication are substantially different. I argue that this difference not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  45
    Are all necessary propositions analytic?Arthur Pap - 1949 - Philosophical Review 58 (4):299-320.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  15
    Hume's Fork and Analytic/Trifling Propositions.Wilf Backhaus - 1994 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 8 (2):79 - 96.
  37. Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes.Paul M. Churchland - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (2):67-90.
    Eliminative materialism is the thesis that our common-sense conception of psychological phenomena constitutes a radically false theory, a theory so fundamentally defective that both the principles and the ontology of that theory will eventually be displaced, rather than smoothly reduced, by completed neuroscience. Our mutual understanding and even our introspection may then be reconstituted within the conceptual framework of completed neuroscience, a theory we may expect to be more powerful by far than the common-sense psychology it displaces, and more substantially (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   870 citations  
  38. Are All A Priori Propositions and Inferences Analytic?A. C. Ewing - 1970 - International Logic Review 1:77-87.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  10
    The expected complexity of analytic tableaux analyses in propositional calculus.J. M. Plotkin & John W. Rosenthal - 1982 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (4):409-426.
  40.  25
    The Russellian Origins of Analytical Philosophy: Bertrand Russell and the Unity of the Proposition.Severin Schroeder - 2006 - International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2):246-248.
  41.  95
    ‘They had added not a single tiny proposition’: The Reception of the Prior Analytics in the First Half of the Twelfth Century.Christopher J. Martin - 2010 - Vivarium 48 (1-2):159-192.
    A study of the reception of Aristotle's Prior Analytics in the first half of the twelfth century. It is shown that Peter Abaelard was perhaps acquainted with as much as the first seven chapters of Book I of the Prior Analytics but with no more. The appearance at the beginning of the twelfth century of a short list of dialectical loci which has puzzled earlier commentators is explained by noting that this list formalises the classification of extensional relations between general (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Sentence, Proposition, Judgment, Statement, and Fact: Speaking about the Written English Used in Logic.John Corcoran - 2009 - In W. A. Carnielli (ed.), The Many Sides of Logic. College Publications. pp. 71-103.
    The five English words—sentence, proposition, judgment, statement, and fact—are central to coherent discussion in logic. However, each is ambiguous in that logicians use each with multiple normal meanings. Several of their meanings are vague in the sense of admitting borderline cases. In the course of displaying and describing the phenomena discussed using these words, this paper juxtaposes, distinguishes, and analyzes several senses of these and related words, focusing on a constellation of recommended senses. One of the purposes of this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43. Non‐Propositional Attitudes.Alex Grzankowski - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (12):1123-1137.
    Intentionality, or the power of minds to be about, to represent, or to stand for things, remains central in the philosophy of mind. But the study of intentionality in the analytic tradition has been dominated by discussions of propositional attitudes such as belief, desire, and visual perception. There are, however, intentional states that aren't obviously propositional attitudes. For example, Indiana Jones fears snakes, Antony loves Cleopatra, and Jane hates the monster under her bed. The present paper explores such mental (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  44.  48
    R. Cartwright. Propositions. Analytical philosophy, edited by R. J. Butler, Barnes & Noble, Inc., New York1962, pp. 81–103. [REVIEW]Alan Ross Anderson - 1964 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 29 (3):139.
  45.  7
    The Russellian Origins of Analytical Philosophy: Bertrand Russell and the Unity of the Proposition[REVIEW]Severin Schroeder - 2006 - International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2):246-248.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  21
    Lossky N. O.. Analytic and synthetic propositions and mathematical logic. International Universities Press, Inc., New York 1953, 16 pp. [REVIEW]Christopher Blake - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (4):291-291.
  47.  27
    Review: N. O. Lossky, Analytic and Synthetic Propositions and Mathematical Logic. [REVIEW]Christopher Blake - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (4):291-291.
  48.  68
    Propositional Attitudes.J. A. Fodor - 1978 - The Monist 61 (4):501-523.
    Some philosophers hold that philosophy is what you do to a problem until it’s clear enough to solve it by doing science. Others hold that if a philosophical problem succumbs to empirical methods, that shows it wasn’t really philosophical to begin with. Either way, the facts seem clear enough: questions first mooted by philosophers are sometimes coopted by people who do experiments. This seems to be happening now to the question: “what are propositional attitudes?” and cognitive psychology is the science (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  49. Designating propositions.Jeffrey C. King - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):341-371.
    Like many, though of course not all, philosophers, I believe in propositions. I take propositions to be structured, sentence-like entities whose structures are identical to the syntactic structures of the sentences that express them; and I have defended a particular version of such a view of propositions elsewhere. In the present work, I shall assume that the structures of propositions are at least very similar to the structures of the sentences that express them. Further, I shall assume that ordinary names (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  50.  25
    Some observations on the distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions.Robert E. Gahringer - 1954 - Journal of Philosophy 51 (15):425-436.
1 — 50 / 1000