Results for 'A. Falkenstein'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  13
    Ahead of the Curve: Responses From Patients in Treatment for Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder to Coronavirus Disease 2019.Jennie M. Kuckertz, Nathaniel Van Kirk, David Alperovitz, Jacob A. Nota, Martha J. Falkenstein, Meghan Schreck & Jason W. Krompinger - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
  2.  48
    Logic Works: A Rigorous Introduction to Formal Logic.Lorne Falkenstein, Scott Stapleford & Molly Kao - 2022 - New York: Routledge. Edited by Scott Stapleford & Molly Kao.
    Logic Works is a critical and extensive introduction to logic. It asks questions about why systems of logic are as they are, how they relate to ordinary language and ordinary reasoning, and what alternatives there might be to classical logical doctrines. It considers how logical analysis can be applied to carefully represent the reasoning employed in academic and scientific work, better understand that reasoning, and identify its hidden premises. Aiming to be as much a reference work and handbook for further, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  54
    The Role of Material Impressions in Reid's Theory of Vision: A Critique of Gideon Yaffe's “Reid on the Perception of the Visible Figure”.Lorne Falkenstein & Giovanni B. Grandi - 2003 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 1 (2):117-133.
    Reid maintained that the perceptions that we obtain from the senses of smell, taste, hearing, and touch are ‘suggested’ by corresponding sensations. However, he made an exception for the sense of vision. According to Reid, our perceptions of the real figure, position, and magnitude of bodies are suggested by their visible appearances, which are not sensations but objects of perception in their own right. These visible appearances have figure, position, and magnitude, as well as ‘colour,’ and the standard view among (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4.  7
    Demea's Departure Revisited.Lorne Falkenstein - 2023 - In Kenneth Williford (ed.), Hume's _Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion_: A Philosophical Apparaisal. Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge. pp. 155-69.
  5.  16
    Catalogue of the Cuneiform Tablets of the Wilberforce Eames Babylonian Collection in the New York Public Library, Tablets of the Time of the Third Dynasty of UrBusiness Documents of the Third Dynasty of Ur.A. Falkenstein, A. Leo Oppenheim, Léon Legrain & Leon Legrain - 1952 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 72 (1):40.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Was Kant a Nativist?Lorne Falkenstein - 1998 - In Patricia Kitcher (ed.), Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Critical Essays. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 21-44.
    This paper was originally published in _Journal of the History of Ideas_ 51 (1990): 573-597. Kant's claim that space and time are "forms of intuition" is contrasted with the nativist claim that space is an innate idea or construct of the mind and with the empiricist claim that space is given in or learned from experience. It is argued that the nativism/empiricism debate masks a more fundamental disagreement between sensationism and constructivism. Kant's account of space- and time-cognition is shown to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  33
    David Hume: Essays and Treatises on Philosophical Subjects.Lorne Falkenstein & Neil McArthur - 2013 - Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press.
    This is the first edition in over a century to present David Hume's Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Dissertation on the Passions, Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, and Natural History of Religion in the format he intended: collected together in a single volume. Hume has suffered a fate unusual among great philosophers. His principal philosophical work is no longer published in the form in which he intended it to be read. It has been divided into separate parts, only some of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  19
    Consciousness, Time, and Scepticism in Hume's Thought.Lorne Falkenstein - 2024 - New York: Routledge.
    David Hume’s philosophical work presents the reader with a perplexing mix of constructive accounts of empirically guided belief and destructive sceptical arguments against all belief. This book reconciles this conflict by showing that Hume intended his scepticism to be remedial. It immunizes us against the influence of “unphilosophical” causes of belief, determining us to proportion our beliefs to the evidence. In making this case, this book develops Humean positions on topics Hume did not discuss in detail but that are of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Hume on religion in the Enquiry concerning the principles of morals.Lorne Falkenstein - 2021 - In Esther Engels Kroeker & Willem Lemmens (eds.), Hume's an Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals : A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press.
  10.  9
    Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - University of Toronto Press.
    This book presents a paragraph-by-paragraph analysis of all of the major arguments and explanations in the "aesthetic" of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. The first part of the book aims to provide a clear analysis of the meanings of the terms Kant uses to name faculties and types of representation, the second offers a thorough account of the reasoning behind the "metaphysical" and "transcendental" expositions, and the third investigates the basis for Kant's major conclusions about space, time, appearances, things in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  11.  57
    Was Kant a Nativist?Lorne Falkenstein - 1990 - Journal of the History of Ideas 51 (4):573-597.
    (This paper has since been republished in _Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Critical Essays_, edited by Patricia Kitcher [Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998], 21-44.) Kant's claim that space and time are "forms of intuition" is contrasted with the nativist claim that space is an innate idea or construct of the mind and with the empiricist claim that space is given in or learned from experience. It is argued that the nativism/empiricism debate masks a more fundamental disagreement between sensationism and constructivism. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  19
    Reid's Critique of Berkely's Position on the Inverted Image.Lorne Falkenstein - 2018 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 16 (2):175-191.
    (Originally published in _Reid Studies_ 4 (2000-01): 35-51.) Reid and Berkeley disagreed over whether we directly perceive objects located outside of us in a surrounding space, commonly revealed by both vision and touch. Berkeley considered a successful account of erect vision to be crucial for deciding this dispute, at one point calling it ‘the principal point in the whole optic theory.’ Reid's critique of Berkeley's position on this topic is very brief, and appears to miss Berkeley's point. I argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  56
    Hume on the Idea of a Vacuum.Lorne Falkenstein - 2014 - Hume Studies 39 (2):131-168.
    Hume had two principal arguments for denying that we can have an idea of a vacuum, an argument from the non-entity of unqualified points and an argument from the impossibility of forming abstract ideas of manners of disposition. He also made two serious concessions to the opposed view that we can indeed form ideas of vacua, namely, that bodies that have nothing sensible disposed between them may permit the interposition of other bodies without any apparent motion or occlusion and that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. Hume on Manners of Disposition and the Ideas of Space and Time.Lorne Falkenstein - 1997 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79 (2):179-201.
    Scholars have almost universally agreed that Hume's account of space and time as manners of disposition of impressions is inconsistent with one of the most fundamental tenets of his empiricism: the thesis that all ideas are derived from simple impressions. This paper challenges that view and argues that Hume's position on the origin of our ideas of space and time is a profound, original, virtually unique, and even courageous approach to the problem of original space and time cognition, and a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  15. Hume on 'Genuine,' 'True,' and 'Rational' Religion.Lorne Falkenstein - 2009 - Eighteenth Century Thought 4 (1):171-201.
    Hume appears to have sometimes taken religion to be founded on reason, at other times to have taken it to be founded on faith, and at yet other times to be based on authority. All of these views can be found in the different pieces collected together in the second volume of his Essays and Treatises on Several Subjects. By means of an analysis of what Hume meant by "genuine religion," "true religion," and "rational religion," I uncover a consistent, sincere (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16. Kant’s Account of Sensation.Lorne Falkenstein - 1990 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (1):63-88.
    Kant defined ‘sensation’as ‘the effect of an object on the representative capacity, so far as we are affected by it.’ This is, to put it mildly, not one among his more elegant, clear or helpful sayings. And it is merely an instance of a more general malaise. Kant did not say as much about sensation as he should have, and his account-or lack of it-can be seen at the root of many of the difficulties that have plagued his readers.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  17.  97
    Reid’s Account of Localization.Lorne Falkenstein - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2):305-328.
    This paper contrasts three different positions taken by 18th century British scholars on how sensations, particularly sensations of colour and touch, come to be localized in space: Berkeley’s view that we learn to localize ideas of colour by associating certain purely qualitative features of those ideas with ideas of touch and motion, Hume’s view that visual and tangible impressions are originally disposed in space, and Reid’s view that we are innately disposed to refer appearances of colour to the end of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  18.  81
    Kant’s Account of Intuition.Lorne Falkenstein - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (2):165-193.
    This paper outlines the history of the distinction between a higher and a lower cognitive function up to Kant. It is argued that Kant initially drew the distinction in Scholastic terms--as a distinction between a capacity to image particulars and a capacity to represent universals. However, features of his project in the Critique led him to reformulate the distinction in terms of immediacy and mediacy. Nonetheless, for certain purposes the older, Scholastic distinction retained its attractiveness, and this is the ground (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  55
    Hume and Reid on the Simplicity of the Soul.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - Hume Studies 21 (1):25-45.
    Reid is well known for rejecting the "philosophy of ideas"--a theory of mental representation that he claimed to find in its most vitriolic form in Hume. But there was another component of Hume's philosophy that exerted an equally powerful influence on Reid: Hume's attack on the notion of spiritual substance in _Treatise 1.4.5. I summarize this neglected aspect of Hume's philosophy and argue that much of Reid's epistemology can be explained as an attempt to buttress dualism against the effects of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20.  45
    Hume and Reid on the Perception of Hardness.Lorne Falkenstein - 2002 - Hume Studies 28 (1):27-48.
    This paper considers an objection to the Humean view that perception involves introspective acquaintance with representative images. The objection, originally raised by Thomas Reid and recently endorsed by Nicholas Wolterstorff, states that no representative image can be hard, and concludes that acquaintance with such images cannot therefore account for our perception of hardness. I argue in response that a case has not been made for denying that representative images can be hard. Hardness, as understood by Hume and Reid, is the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  94
    Intuition and construction in Berkeley's account of visual space.Lorne Falkenstein - 1994 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 32 (1):63-84.
    This paper examines Berkeley's attitude toward our perception of spatial relations on the two- dimensional visual field. This is a topic on which there has been some controversy. Historians of visual theory have tended to suppose that Berkeley took "all" spatial relations to be derived in the way our knowledge of depth is: from association of more primitive sensations which are themselves in no way spatial. But many philosophers commenting on Berkeley have supposed that he takes our awareness of two- (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22. Kant, Mendelssohn, Lambert, and the subjectivity of time.Lorne Falkenstein - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (2):227-251.
    On the basis of an examination of Kant's correspondence with Mendelssohn, 1766-1770, I argue that already in 1770 Kant had before him a decisive refutation of the view that time is imposed by the mind on its representations, and that Kant did not hold any such view of the subjectivity of time in his later work. Kant's mature view is that time is subjective only in the sense that it is the manner in which the empirically observable subject receives sensory (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  86
    Hume’s Finite Geometry: A Reply to Mark Pressman.Lorne Falkenstein - 2000 - Hume Studies 26 (1):183-185.
    In “Hume on Geometry and Infinite Divisibility in the Treatise”, H. Mark Pressman charges that “the geometry Hume presents in the Treatise faces a serious set of problems”. This may well be; however, at least one of the charges Pressman levels against Hume invokes a false dichotomy, and a second rests on a non sequitur.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  87
    A Double Edged Sword? Kant's Refutation Of Mendelssohn's Proof Of The Immortality Of The Soul And Its Implications For His Theory Of Matter.Lorne Falkenstein - 1998 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 29 (4):561-588.
    I argue that Kant's refutation of Mendelssohn's proof of the immortality of the soul also refutes his own proof of the permanence of material substance. To evade this result, Kant would have had to rely on premises that can only be established empirically. This difficulty brings up deep and disturbing difficulties with Kant's theory of matter and body in his Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science and suggests that his early Physical Monadology offered a better account, one he was constrained by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  44
    Nativism and the Nature of Thought in Reid's Account of Our Knowledge of the External World.Lorne Falkenstein - 2004 - In Terence Cuneo Rene van Woudenberg (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 156--179.
    This is a wide ranging survey of the extent and nature of Reid's nativist commitments and of their implications for his account of perception and his realism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  33
    Localizing sensations: A reply to Anthony Quinton's trouble with Kant.Lorne Falkenstein - 1998 - Philosophy 73 (3):479-489.
    Anthony Quinton has argued that the trouble with Kant is that he does not take empirical experience to have any significant role to play in our knowledge of the world, and as a result is forced to take the imposition of a priori forms and categories to be arbitrary and unguided. While Quinton has pointed to a serious short-coming with those more rationalistic interpretations of Kant that would ascribe a dominant role to the understanding or the imagination in constituting experience, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  3
    Classical Empiricism.Lorne Falkenstein - 2013 - In Heather Dyke & Adrian Bardon (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Time. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 102–119.
    This chapter on classical empiricism is divided into three sections, namely, absolutism, idealism, and memory. Presentism poses a particular problem for the empiricist view that the idea of time arises from people's experience of the succession of their ideas. The view that time passes independently of the succession of ideas was shared by canonically empiricist philosophers, such as Gassendi, Locke, and Newton. The idea of time arises from a compound impression that consists of successively disposed simple impressions – impressions that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  68
    The psychology and epistemology of Hume's account of probable reasoning.Lorne Falkenstein - 2012 - In Alan Bailey & Dan O'Brien (eds.), The Continuum Companion to Hume. Continuum. pp. 104.
    This paper offers and account of the "system" of probable reasoning presented in Hume's Treatise and first Enquiry. The system is sceptical because it takes our beliefs to be the product of naturally occurring psychological mechanisms rather than logically sound judgment, and because it declares those beliefs to be ultimately unjustifiable. This paper explains how Hume was nonetheless able to provide for a logic of probable reasoning, grounded on natural, but unjustifiable beliefs.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  6
    Hume on Temporal Experience.Lorne Falkenstein - 2017 - In Ian Phillips (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Temporal Experience: Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 42-52.
    In Book 1, Part 2, Section 3 of his _Treatise of Human Nature_, David Hume argued that the idea of time arises from the experience of succession. In doing so, he raised a difficult question about the nature of that experience. The experience must be an experience had over time, not an experience of time. But how is that possible? This paper investigates how far mechanisms Hume appealed to when accounting for such related phenomena as causal inference, the understanding of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  8
    Kant's Transcendental Aesthetic.Lorne Falkenstein - 2006 - In Graham Bird (ed.), A Companion to Kant. Malden, MA, USA: Blackwell. pp. 140–153.
  31.  88
    Is perceptual space monadic?Lorne Falkenstein - 1989 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (June):709-713.
    Against the claims of Russell, Goodman, and Albert Casullo, this paper argues that the location of phenomena in visual space cannot be determined through reference to monadic local properties of the visual field.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  7
    11. Kant, Mendelssohn, Lambert, and the Subjectivity of Time.Lorne Falkenstein - 2004 - In Kant's Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. University of Toronto Press. pp. 334-355.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33.  43
    Reid’s Account of the “Geometry of Visibles”: Some Lessons from Helmholtz.Lorne Falkenstein - 2016 - Topoi 35 (2):485-510.
    Drawing on work done by Helmholtz, I argue that Reid was in no position to infer that objects appear as if projected on the inner surface of a sphere, or that they have the geometric properties of such projections even though they do not look concave towards the eye. A careful consideration of the phenomena of visual experience, as further illuminated by the practice of visual artists, should have led him to conclude that the sides of visible appearances either look (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  21
    Without Gallantry and Without Jealousy: The Development of Hume's Account of Sexual Virtues and Vices.Lorne Falkenstein - 2015 - Hume Studies 41 (2):137-170.
    In this paper I argue that Hume's thought on comportment between the sexes developed over time. In the Treatise he was interested in explaining why the world seeks to impose artificial virtues of chastity and modesty on women and girls, and how it manages to do this so successfully. But as time passed he became increasingly concerned with justice towards women and the role of free interactions between the sexes in facilitating sociability. While his later work continues to explain the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  9
    Theories of Perception I: Berkeley and His Recent Predecessors.Lorne Falkenstein - 2014 - In Aaron Garrett (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Eighteenth Century Philosophy. London: Routledge. pp. 338-59.
    A survey of work on the philosophy of perception, mind, and mental representation by Berkeley and his early modern predecessors, notably Descartes, Hobbes, Malebranche, and Locke.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  98
    Condillac's paradox.Lorne Falkenstein - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (4):403-435.
    : I argue that Condillac was committed to four mutually inconsistent propositions: that the mind is unextended, that sensations are modifications of the mind, that colours are sensations, and that colours are extended. I argue that this inconsistency was not just the blunder of a second-rate philosopher, but the consequence of a deep-seated tension in the views of early modern philosophers on the nature of the mind, sensation, and secondary qualities and that more widely studied figures, notably Condillac's contemporaries, Hume (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  8
    Moral Disagreement.Lorne Falkenstein - 2021 - In Esther Engels Kroeker & Willem Lemmens (eds.), Hume's an Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals : A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press. pp. 238-56.
    This paper argues that Hume was first and foremost a moral psychologist and a determinist, not a moralist. When confronting the fact of moral disagreement, notably in "A Dialogue" affixed to his moral enquiry, he maintained that it is not psychologically possible to approve of the conflicting norms of other cultures, except in the case of sometimes approving of individuals in other cultures for abiding by those objectionable norms rather than fomenting cultural upheaval. All cultures should nonetheless agree on the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  61
    Berkeley's Argument for Other Minds.Lorne Falkenstein - 1990 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 7 (4):431 - 440.
    The literature on Berkeley is almost unanimous in taking this claim to know the existence of other finite spirits to rest on an argument from analogy. I show that this is not so and that Berkeley uses a causal argument to prove that there are other minds. Questions of the degree to which it is legitimate for Berkeley to appeal to causes, particularly occasional causes, are addressed in the process.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  20
    Humean Contiguity.Lorne Falkenstein & David Welton - 2001 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 18 (3):279 - 296.
    We argue that Hume was wrong to identify constant conjunction in time as the sole associative principle responsible for belief. On principles that can be grounded on his own account, constant contiguity in space ought to produce the same effect. We close by examining some of the ways in which a recognition of the influence of contiguity relations might have assisted Hume in resolving problems that otherwise arise with his accounts of causality and objectivity.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Reid's Critique of Berkeley's Position on the Inverted Image.Lorne Falkenstein - 2000 - Reid Studies 4 (1):35-51.
    (This article was republished in lightly re-edited form in _Journal of Scottish Philosophy_ 16 (2018) 175-91.) Reid and Berkeley disagreed over whether we directly perceive objects located outside of us in a surrounding space, commonly revealed by both vision and touch. Berkeley considered a successful account of erect vision to be crucial for deciding this dispute, at one point calling it ‘the principal point in the whole optic theory.’ Reid's critique of Berkeley's position on this topic is very brief, and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  6
    Hume's Project in 'The Natural History of Religion'.Lorne Falkenstein - 2003 - Religious Studies 39 (1):1-21.
    There are good reasons to think that at least a part of Hume's project in the ‘The natural history of religion’ was to buttress a philosophical critique of the reasonableness of religious belief undertaken in other works, and to attack a fundamentalist account of the history of religion and the foundations of morality. But there are also problems with supposing that Hume intended to achieve either of these goals. I argue that two problems in particular – accounting for Hume's neglect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  4
    Theories of Perception II: After Berkeley.Lorne Falkenstein - 2014 - In Aaron Garrett (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Eighteenth Century Philosophy. London: Routledge. pp. 360-80.
    A survey of work on perception, mind, and mental representation by 18th century philosophers after Berkeley, notably Robert Smith, William Porterfield, David Hume, Etienne de Condillac, and Thomas Reid.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  53
    Kant's Empiricism.Lorne Falkenstein - 1997 - Review of Metaphysics 50 (3):547 - 589.
    It might seem inappropriate to describe Kant as an empiricist. He believed, contrary to the basic empiricist principle, that there are nontrivial propositions that can be known independently of experience. He devoted virtually all of his efforts as a researcher to discovering how it is possible for us to have this "synthetic a priori" knowledge. However, Kant also believed that there are some things that we can know only through sensory experience. Though he did not give these empirical propositions the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Berkeley on Situation and Inversion.Lorne Falkenstein - 2015 - In Patricia Easton (ed.), The Battle of the Gods and Giands Redux: Papers Presented to Thomas M. Lennon. Leiden: Brill. pp. 300-23.
    Over _Principles_ 42-43, Berkeley worried that we might "in truth" see things existing at a distance from us, in which case they could not plausibly be supposed to exist independently of being perceived. He went on to say that he had developed his new theory of vision to address this worry. This paper argues that the worry is serious and that Berkeley was right to think that it would take nothing less than a theory of vision to address it. The (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  43
    Dualism And The Experimentum Crucis.Lorne Falkenstein - 2016 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (1):212-217.
    This book symposium contribution focuses on James Van Cleve's assertion that Reid's dualistic commitments are not essential to his other doctrines. I argue to the contrary that his critique of what he called the philosophy of ideas depends on a tacit assumption of dualism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Hume's Reply to the Achilles Argument.Lorne Falkenstein - 2008 - In Thomas M. Lennon (ed.), The Achilles of Rationalist Psychology. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 193-214.
    Book 1, Part 4, Section 5 of Hume’s Treatise is taken up with a response to an argument for the immateriality of the soul that Hume considered “remarkable,” and that Kant was later to describes as the “Achilles” (the strongest) of all the arguments for this conclusion. This paper surveys versions of the argument offered by Cudworth, Bayle, and Clarke before going on to argue that Hume’s own treatment of the argument departs from the standard in a number of important (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  23
    Kant’s First Argument in the Metaphysical Expositions.Lorne Falkenstein - 1989 - Proceedings of the Sixth International Kant Congress 2 (1):219-227.
    This paper argues that Kant's first argument in the metaphysical expositions defends a foundational insight on which much of the rest of his thought depends: that our experience of the spatial properties and relations of things is not based on comparison of the things (matters) found in space or on any form of reasoning (causal or demonstrative). Spatial and temporal relations are originally given in sensory intuition, not constructed or inferred.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  45
    Reid's response to Hume's perceptual relativity argument.Lorne Falkenstein - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):25-49.
    Reid declared Hume's appeal to variation in the magnitude of a table with distance to be the best argument that had ever been offered for the ‘ideal hypothesis’ that we experience nothing but our own mental states. Reid's principal objection to this argument fails to apply to minimally visible points. He did establish that we have reason to take our perceptions to be caused by external objects. But his case that we directly perceive external objects is undermined by what Hume (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  13
    Spaces and Times.L. Falkenstein - 1986 - Idealistic Studies 16 (1):1-11.
    Recently it has been argued that there are conceivable situations in which we would be led to think of our experiences as belonging to two different, entirely disconnected spaces or times. From this it follows that there is no necessity in the claim that all our experiences must be conceived of as belonging together in one space or time. Let us call the claim that all our experiences must belong to one space and time the connectedness hypothesis, and the counterclaim (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  2
    Spaces and Times.L. Falkenstein - 1986 - Idealistic Studies 16 (1):1-11.
    Recently it has been argued that there are conceivable situations in which we would be led to think of our experiences as belonging to two different, entirely disconnected spaces or times. From this it follows that there is no necessity in the claim that all our experiences must be conceived of as belonging together in one space or time. Let us call the claim that all our experiences must belong to one space and time the connectedness hypothesis, and the counterclaim (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000