Results for ' stit logic'

965 found
Order:
  1.  56
    Stit -logic for imagination episodes with voluntary input.Christopher Badura & Heinrich Wansing - 2023 - Review of Symbolic Logic 16 (3):813-861.
    Francesco Berto proposed a logic for imaginative episodes. The logic establishes certain (in)validities concerning episodic imagination. They are not all equally plausible as principles of episodic imagination. The logic also does not model that the initial input of an imaginative episode is deliberately chosen.Stit-imagination logic models the imagining agent’s deliberate choice of the content of their imagining. However, the logic does not model the episodic nature of imagination. The present paper combines the two logics, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  34
    A STIT Logic for Reasoning About Social Influence.Emiliano Lorini & Giovanni Sartor - 2016 - Studia Logica 104 (4):773-812.
    In this paper we propose a method for modeling social influence within the STIT approach to action. Our proposal consists in extending the STIT language with special operators that allow us to represent the consequences of an agent’s choices over the rational choices of another agent.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  13
    A Stit Logic of Intentionality.Aldo Iván Ramírez Abarca & Jan Broersen - 2023 - In Carlos Areces & Diana Costa (eds.), Dynamic Logic. New Trends and Applications: 4th International Workshop, DaLí 2022, Haifa, Israel, July 31–August 1, 2022, Revised Selected Papers. Springer Verlag. pp. 125-153.
    We extend epistemic stit theory with a modality \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$I_\alpha \varphi $$\end{document}, meant to express that at some moment agent \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\alpha $$\end{document} had a present-directed intention toward the realization of \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\varphi $$\end{document}. The semantics is based on the extension of stit frames with special topologies associated to agents. The open sets of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. A Neutral Temporal Deontic STIT Logic.Kees van Berkel & Tim Lyon - 2019 - In P. Blackburn, E. Lorini & M. Guo (eds.), Logic, Rationality, and Interaction. Springer. pp. 340-354.
    In this work we answer a long standing request for temporal embeddings of deontic STIT logics by introducing the multi-agent STIT logic TDS . The logic is based upon atemporal utilitarian STIT logic. Yet, the logic presented here will be neutral: instead of committing ourselves to utilitarian theories, we prove the logic TDS sound and complete with respect to relational frames not employing any utilitarian function. We demonstrate how these neutral frames can (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  30
    Deontic epistemic stit logic distinguishing modes of mens rea.Jan Broersen - 2011 - Journal of Applied Logic 9 (2):137-152.
  6.  68
    Uncompactness of Stit Logics Containing Generalized Refref Conditionals.Ming Xu - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (4):485-506.
    In this paper we prove the uncompactness of every stit logic that contains a generalized refref conditional and is a sublogic of the stit logic with refref equivalence, a syntactical condition of uncompactness that covers infinitely many stit logics. This result is established through the uncompactness of every stit logic whose semantic structures contain no chain of busy choice sequences with cardinality , where is any natural number . The basic idea in the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. From BDI and stit to bdi-stit logic.Caroline Semmling & Heinrich Wansing - 2008 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 17 (1-2):185-207.
    Since it is desirable to be able to talk about rational agents forming attitudes toward their concrete agency, we suggest an introduction of doxastic, volitional, and intentional modalities into the multi-agent logic of deliberatively seeing to it that, dstit logic. These modalities are borrowed from the well-known BDI (belief-desire-intention) logic. We change the semantics of the belief and desire operators from a relational one to a monotonic neighbourhood semantic in order to handle ascriptions of conflicting but not (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8. Causal Agency and Responsibility: A Refinement of STIT Logic.Alexandru Baltag, Ilaria Canavotto & Sonja Smets - 2021 - In Alessandro Giordani & Jacek Malinowski (eds.), Logic in High Definition, Trends in Logical Semantics. Berlin, Germany: pp. 149-176.
    We propose a refinement of STIT logic to make it suitable to model causal agency and responsibility in basic multi-agent scenarios in which agents can interfere with one another. We do this by supplementing STIT semantics, first, with action types and, second, with a relation of opposing between action types. We exploit these novel elements to represent a test for potential causation, based on an intuitive notion of expected result of an action, and two tests for actual (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Automating Agential Reasoning: Proof-Calculi and Syntactic Decidability for STIT Logics.Tim Lyon & Kees van Berkel - 2019 - In M. Baldoni, M. Dastani, B. Liao, Y. Sakurai & R. Zalila Wenkstern (eds.), PRIMA 2019: Principles and Practice of Multi-Agent Systems. Springer. pp. 202-218.
    This work provides proof-search algorithms and automated counter-model extraction for a class of STIT logics. With this, we answer an open problem concerning syntactic decision procedures and cut-free calculi for STIT logics. A new class of cut-free complete labelled sequent calculi G3LdmL^m_n, for multi-agent STIT with at most n-many choices, is introduced. We refine the calculi G3LdmL^m_n through the use of propagation rules and demonstrate the admissibility of their structural rules, resulting in auxiliary calculi Ldm^m_nL. In the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10. The Varieties of Ought-implies-Can and Deontic STIT Logic.Kees van Berkel & Tim Lyon - 2021 - In Fenrong Liu, Alessandra Marra, Paul Portner & Frederik Van De Putte (eds.), Deontic Logic and Normative Systems: 15th International Conference.
    STIT logic is a prominent framework for the analysis of multi-agent choice-making. In the available deontic extensions of STIT, the principle of Ought-implies-Can (OiC) fulfills a central role. However, in the philosophical literature a variety of alternative OiC interpretations have been proposed and discussed. This paper provides a modular framework for deontic STIT that accounts for a multitude of OiC readings. In particular, we discuss, compare, and formalize ten such readings. We provide sound and complete sequent-style (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  88
    Making a Start with the stit Logic Analysis of Intentional Action.Jan M. Broersen - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (4):499-530.
    This paper studies intentional action in stit logic. The formal logic study of intentional action appears to be new, since most logical studies of intention concern intention as a static mental state. In the formalization we distinguish three modes of acting: the objective level concerning the choices an agent objectively exercises, the subjective level concerning the choices an agent knows or believes to be exercising, and finally, the intentional level concerning the choices an agent intentionally exercises. Several (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  12. Cut-free Calculi and Relational Semantics for Temporal STIT Logics.Tim Lyon & Kees van Berkel - 2019 - In Francesco Calimeri, Nicola Leone & Marco Manna (eds.), Logics in Artificial Intelligence. Springer. pp. 803 - 819.
    We present cut-free labelled sequent calculi for a central formalism in logics of agency: STIT logics with temporal operators. These include sequent systems for Ldm , Tstit and Xstit. All calculi presented possess essential structural properties such as contraction- and cut-admissibility. The labelled calculi G3Ldm and G3Tstit are shown sound and complete relative to irreflexive temporal frames. Additionally, we extend current results by showing that also Xstit can be characterized through relational frames, omitting the use of BT+AC frames.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  40
    Inference as Doxastic Agency. Part I: The Basics of Justification Stit Logic.Grigory K. Olkhovikov & Heinrich Wansing - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (1):167-194.
    In this paper we consider logical inference as an activity that results in proofs and hence produces knowledge. We suggest to merge the semantical analysis of deliberatively seeing-to-it-that from stit theory and the semantics of the epistemic logic with justification from. The general idea is to understand proving that A as seeing to it that a proof of A is available. We introduce a semantics of various notions of proving as an activity and present a number of valid (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14.  5
    Restricted interpolation and lack thereof in stit logic.Grigory K. Olkhovikov - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (3):459-482.
    We consider the propositional logic equipped with Chellas stit operators for a finite set of individual agents plus the historical necessity modality. We settle the question of whether such a logic enjoys restricted interpolation property, which requires the existence of an interpolant only in cases where the consequence contains no Chellas stit operators occurring in the premise. We show that if action operators count as logical symbols, then such a logic has restricted interpolation property iff (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  13
    Tableaux for multi-agent deliberative-stit logic.Heinrich Wansing - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 503-520.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  16.  9
    Tableaux for multi-agent deliberative-stit logic.Heinrich Wansing - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 503-520.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  17. A dynamic logic of agency I: Stit, capabilities and powers.Andreas Herzig & Emiliano Lorini - 2010 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 19 (1):89-121.
    The aim of this paper, is to provide a logical framework for reasoning about actions, agency, and powers of agents and coalitions in game-like multi-agent systems. First we define our basic Dynamic Logic of Agency ( ). Differently from other logics of individual and coalitional capability such as Alternating-time Temporal Logic (ATL) and Coalition Logic, in cooperation modalities for expressing powers of agents and coalitions are not primitive, but are defined from more basic dynamic logic operators (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  18.  39
    Complexity Results of STIT Fragments.François Schwarzentruber - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (5):1001-1045.
    We provide a Kripke semantics for a STIT logic with the "next" operator. As the atemporal group STIT is undecidable and unaxiomatizable, we are interested in strict fragments of atemporal group STIT. First we prove that the satisfiability problem of a formula of the fragment made up of individual coalitions plus the grand coalition is also NEXPTIME-complete. We then generalize this result to a fragment where coalitions are in a given lattice. We also prove that if (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  93
    On the basic logic of STIT with a single agent.Ming Xu - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):459-483.
    We present in this paper an axiomatization of Belnap and Perloff's stit theory (a logic of "seeing to it that") with a single agent. The idea of the proof is to apply the notion of companion sets--the same notion as used in another paper by the author that showed the decidability of stit theory with a single agent and Refref equivalence.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  20.  18
    Simplified Tableaux for STIT Imagination Logic.Grigory K. Olkhovikov & Heinrich Wansing - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (6):981-1001.
    We show how to correct the analytic tableaux system from the paper Olkhovikov and Wansing, 259–279, 2018).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  15
    Proof-Theoretic Analysis of the Logics of Agency: The Deliberative STIT.S. Negri & E. Pavlović - 2020 - Studia Logica 109 (3):473-507.
    A sequent calculus methodology for systems of agency based on branching-time frames with agents and choices is proposed, starting with a complete and cut-free system for multi-agent deliberative STIT; the methodology allows a transparent justification of the rules, good structural properties, analyticity, direct completeness and decidability proofs.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  46
    An Axiomatic System and a Tableau Calculus for STIT Imagination Logic.Grigory K. Olkhovikov & Heinrich Wansing - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 47 (2):259-279.
    We formulate a Hilbert-style axiomatic system and a tableau calculus for the STIT-based logic of imagination recently proposed in Wansing. Completeness of the axiom system is shown by the method of canonical models; completeness of the tableau system is also shown by using standard methods.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  23. Axioms for deliberative stit.Ming Xu - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (5):505-552.
    Based on a notion of "companions to stit formulas" applied in other papers dealing with astit logics, we introduce "choice formulas" and "nested choice formulas" to prove the completeness theorems for dstit logics in a language with the dstit operator as the only non-truth-functional operator. The main logic discussed in this paper is the basic logic of dstit with multiple agents, other logics discussed include the basic logic of dstit with a single agent and some logics (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  24.  93
    Combinations of Stit with Ought and Know.Ming Xu - 2015 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 44 (6):851-877.
    This paper presents a short survey of recent developments in stit theories, with an emphasis on combinations of stit and deontic logic, and those of stit and epistemic logic.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  98
    Combinations of Stit and Actions.Ming Xu - 2010 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 19 (4):485-503.
    We present a simple theory of actions against the background of branching time, based on which we propose two versions of an extended stit theory, one equipped with particular actions and the other with sets of such actions. After reporting some basic results of a formal development of such a theory, we briefly explore its connection to a version of branching ETL.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  26.  85
    Alternative axiomatics and complexity of deliberative stit theories.Philippe Balbiani, Andreas Herzig & Nicolas Troquard - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 37 (4):387 - 406.
    We propose two alternatives to Xu’s axiomatization of Chellas’s STIT. The first one simplifies its presentation, and also provides an alternative axiomatization of the deliberative STIT. The second one starts from the idea that the historic necessity operator can be defined as an abbreviation of operators of agency, and can thus be eliminated from the logic of Chellas’s STIT. The second axiomatization also allows us to establish that the problem of deciding the satisfiability of a (...) formula without temporal operators is NP-complete in the single-agent case, and is NEXPTIME-complete in the multiagent case, both for the deliberative and Chellas’s STIT. (shrink)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  27.  39
    Action types in stit semantics.John Horty & Eric Pacuit - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):617-637.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28.  81
    Epistemic logic meets epistemic game theory: a comparison between multi-agent Kripke models and type spaces.Paolo Galeazzi & Emiliano Lorini - 2016 - Synthese 193 (7):2097-2127.
    In the literature there are at least two main formal structures to deal with situations of interactive epistemology: Kripke models and type spaces. As shown in many papers :149–225, 1999; Battigalli and Siniscalchi in J Econ Theory 106:356–391, 2002; Klein and Pacuit in Stud Log 102:297–319, 2014; Lorini in J Philos Log 42:863–904, 2013), both these frameworks can be used to express epistemic conditions for solution concepts in game theory. The main result of this paper is a formal comparison between (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29. The deliberative stit: A study of action, omission, ability, and obligation. [REVIEW]John F. Horty & Nuel Belnap - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (6):583 - 644.
  30.  61
    Obligation and the conditional in stit theory.Kevin Davey - 2002 - Studia Logica 72 (3):339-362.
    In this paper, we consider two different ways in which modus-ponens type reasoning with conditional obligations may be formalized. We develop necessary and sufficient conditions for the validity of each, and make some philosophical observations about the differences between the minor premises that each formalization requires. All this is done within the context of the Belnap-Perloff stit theory.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  91
    Completeness of a Branching-Time Logic with Possible Choices.Roberto Ciuni & Alberto Zanardo - 2010 - Studia Logica 96 (3):393-420.
    In this paper we present BTC, which is a complete logic for branchingtime whose modal operator quantifies over histories and whose temporal operators involve a restricted quantification over histories in a given possible choice. This is a technical novelty, since the operators of the usual logics for branching-time such as CTL express an unrestricted quantification over histories and moments. The value of the apparatus we introduce is connected to those logics of agency that are interpreted on branching-time, as for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  32.  54
    Expressivity results for deontic logics of collective agency.Allard Tamminga, Hein Duijf & Frederik Van De Putte - 2021 - Synthese 198 (9):8733-8753.
    We use a deontic logic of collective agency to study reducibility questions about collective agency and collective obligations. The logic that is at the basis of our study is a multi-modal logic in the tradition of *stit* logics of agency. Our full formal language has constants for collective and individual deontic admissibility, modalities for collective and individual agency, and modalities for collective and individual obligations. We classify its twenty-seven sublanguages in terms of their expressive power. This (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  19
    Flickers of Freedom and Frankfurt-Style Cases in the Light of the New Compatibalism of the Stit Theory.Katarzyna Paprzycka - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Research 27:553-565.
    It is widely assumed that Frankfurt-style cases provide a reason for rejecting incompatibilism because they provide a reason for rejecting the requirement that the agent be able to do otherwise. One compatibilist strategy for dealing with the cases, pursued by Fischer and Ravizza, is to weaken the mentioned requirement. An analogous strategy on the part of the incompatibilist, which appears to be unexplored in the literature on moral responsibility, is exemplified in Belnap and Perloff ’s logic of agency. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. The Logic of Action and Control.Leona Mollica - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (5):1237-1268.
    In this paper I propose and motivate a logic of the interdefined concepts of making true and control, understood as intensional propositional operators to be indexed to an agent. While bearing a resemblance to earlier logics in the tradition, the motivations, semantics, and object language theory differ on crucial points. Applying this logic to widespread formal theories of agency, I use it as a framework to argue against the ubiquitous assumption that the strongest actions or options available to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  31
    Decidability of an Xstit Logic.Gillman Payette - 2014 - Studia Logica 102 (3):577-607.
    This paper presents proofs of completeness and decidability of a non-temporal fragment of an Xstit logic. This shows a distinction between the non-temporal fragments of Xstit logic and regular stit logic since the latter is undecidable. The proof of decidability is via the finite model property. The finite model property is shown to hold by constructing a filtration. However, the set that is used to filter the models isn’t simply closed under subformulas, it has more complex (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. Refining Labelled Systems for Modal and Constructive Logics with Applications.Tim Lyon - 2021 - Dissertation, Technischen Universität Wien
    This thesis introduces the "method of structural refinement", which serves as a means of transforming the relational semantics of a modal and/or constructive logic into an 'economical' proof system by connecting two proof-theoretic paradigms: labelled and nested sequent calculi. The formalism of labelled sequents has been successful in that cut-free calculi in possession of desirable proof-theoretic properties can be automatically generated for large classes of logics. Despite these qualities, labelled systems make use of a complicated syntax that explicitly incorporates (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  20
    Logic of alternative-I.Maiko Yamamori, Takashi Yagisawa, Ryota Akiyoshi, Takuro Onishi & Yasuo Deguchi - 2022 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 1 (2):1-16.
    This paper aims to construct a logic of alternative-I that provides a proper conceptual framework for talk of possible-I in decision-making context, and thereby solves what we call the paradox of possible-I. The model of our logic, Alt-I model, is an adaptation of N. Belnap’s branching-time model, and the STIT (see to it that) operator defined on the model serves to represent choices and decisions made by actual and counterfactual agents. We conclude this paper by discussing the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  23
    Indistinguishability, Choices, and Logics of Agency.Alberto Zanardo - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (6):1215-1236.
    This paper deals with structures ${\langle{\bf T}, I\rangle}$ in which T is a tree and I is a function assigning each moment a partition of the set of histories passing through it. The function I is called indistinguishability and generalizes the notion of undividedness. Belnap’s choices are particular indistinguishability functions. Structures ${\langle{\bf T}, I\rangle}$ provide a semantics for a language ${\mathcal{L}}$ with tense and modal operators. The first part of the paper investigates the set-theoretical properties of the set of indistinguishability (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  41
    Decidability of Logics Based on an Indeterministic Metric Tense Logic.Yan Zhang & Kai Li - 2015 - Studia Logica 103 (6):1123-1162.
    This paper presents two general results of decidability concerning logics based on an indeterministic metric tense logic, which can be applied to, among others, logics combining knowledge, time and agency. We provide a general Kripke semantics based on a variation of the notion of synchronized Ockhamist frames. Our proof of the decidability is by way of the finite frame property, applying subframe transformations and a variant of the filtration technique.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Remarks on the logic of imagination. A step towards understanding doxastic control through imagination.Heinrich Wansing - 2017 - Synthese 194 (8):2843-2861.
    Imagination has recently attracted considerable attention from epistemologists and is recognized as a source of belief and even knowledge. One remarkable feature of imagination is that it is often and typically agentive: agents decide to imagine. In cases in which imagination results in a belief, the agentiveness of imagination may be taken to give rise to indirect doxastic control and epistemic responsibility. This observation calls for a proper understanding of agentive imagination. In particular, it calls for the development of a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  41.  92
    A dynamic logic of agency II: Deterministic dla {\mathcal{dla}} , coalition logic, and game theory.Emiliano Lorini - 2010 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 19 (3):327-351.
    We continue the work initiated in Herzig and Lorini (J Logic Lang Inform, in press) whose aim is to provide a minimalistic logical framework combining the expressiveness of dynamic logic in which actions are first-class citizens in the object language, with the expressiveness of logics of agency such as STIT and logics of group capabilities such as CL and ATL. We present a logic called ( Deterministic Dynamic logic of Agency ) which supports reasoning about (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42. Modelowanie działań i norm w logice deontycznej.Piotr Kulicki & Robert Trypuz - 2013 - In Jerzy Juchnowski & Robert Wiszniowski (eds.), Współczesna teoria i praktyka badań społecznych i humanistycznych. Tom 1. Adam Marszałek.
    In the paper we provide an overview of issues related to the models used in the research on the logic of norms and actions. We present two models of the variability of the world: temporal (acyclic) and atemporal (cyclic). In the first one the past is always clearly defined, and the future is potentially “branched”. The second type of model allows for a return to the situation that took place. Next we describe different approaches towards agency modeling. We present (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  6
    Propositional Q-Logic.Wolfl Stefan - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (5):387-414.
    Topic of the paper is Q-logic – a logic of agency in its temporal and modal context. Q-logic may be considered as a basal logic of agency since the most important stit-operators discussed in the literature can be defined or axiomatized easily within its semantical and syntactical framework. Its basic agent dependent operator, the Q-operator (also known as Δ- or cstit-operator), which has been discussed independently by F. v. Kutschera and B. F. Chellas, is investigated (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44. An Investigation in the Logics of Seeing-to-It-That.Ming Xu - 1996 - Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh
    Based on the branching time theory proposed by Prior and Thomason, this thesis is devoted to characterizing the causal aspect of agency by considering a sentence "$\alpha$ sees to it that A" as asserting a causal relation between a choice made by the agent $\alpha$ and a fact described in the sentence A. The phrase "see to it that" is abbreviated as stit. This thesis provides conceptual analyses of stit and develops some modal logics of stit in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Agency and Deontic Logic by John Horty. [REVIEW]P. McNamara - 2004 - Mind 113 (447):179-185.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  87
    Doxastic Decisions, Epistemic Justification, and The Logic of Agency.Heinrich Wansing - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (1):201-227.
    A prominent issue in mainstream epistemology is the controversy about doxastic obligations and doxastic voluntarism. In the present paper it is argued that this discussion can benefit from forging links with formal epistemology, namely the combined modal logic of belief, agency, and obligation. A stit-theory-based semantics for deontic doxastic logic is suggested, and it is claimed that this is helpful and illuminating in dealing with the mentioned intricate and important problems from mainstream epistemology. Moreover, it is argued (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  47.  30
    What groups do, can do, and know they can do: an analysis in normal modal logics.Jan Broersen, Andreas Herzig & Nicolas Troquard - 2009 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 19 (3):261-289.
    We investigate a series of logics that allow to reason about agents' actions, abilities, and their knowledge about actions and abilities. These logics include Pauly's Coalition Logic CL, Alternating-time Temporal Logic ATL, the logic of ‘seeing-to-it-that' (STIT), and epistemic extensions thereof. While complete axiomatizations of CL and ATL exist, only the fragment of the STIT language without temporal operators and without groups has been axiomatized by Xu (called Ldm). We start by recalling a simplification of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  13
    Party contributions from non-classical logics.Contributions From Non-Classical Logics - 2004 - In S. Rahman J. Symons (ed.), Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Kluwer Academic Publisher. pp. 457.
  49. 94 the Question of Grammar in Logical Inx'estigations.Later Developments In Logic - 2003 - In Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka (ed.), Phenomenology World-Wide. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 94.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  10
    In Memoriam.Informal Logic - 2023 - Informal Logic 44 (1):165.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 965