Results for ' space of reasons'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  33
    Spacings - of reason and imagination in texts of Kant, Fichte, Hegel.John Sallis - 1987 - University of Chicago Press.
    And yet, in these very texts Sallis identifies outbreaks of spacing that would disrupt the tranquil space of reason. Rather than closure, he finds an opening of reason to imagination.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2. The Space of Reasons as Self-Consciousness.Eric Marcus - forthcoming - Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
    In reasoning, we draw conclusions from multiple premises. But thinkers can be fragmented. And if there is no single fragment of the agent that thinks all of the premises, then the agent cannot draw any conclusions from them. It follows that reasoning from multiple premises depends on their being thought together. But what is it to think premises together? What is the condition that contrasts with fragmentation? This paper provides an answer to this question that is simple but compelling: to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Schizophrenia, the space of reasons, and thinking as a motor process.John Campbell - 1999 - The Monist 82 (4):609-625.
    Ordinarily, if you say something like “I see a comet,” you might make a mistake about whether it is a comet that you see, but you could not be right about whether it is a comet but wrong about who is seeing it. There cannot be an “error of identification” in this case. In making a judgement like, “I see a comet,” there are not two steps, finding out who is seeing the thing and finding out what it is that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  4.  59
    Capitalism as a space of reasons: Analytic, neo-Hegelian Marxism?Justin Evans - 2021 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 47 (7):789-813.
    I suggest that we can read Marx in the light of recent analytic, neo-Hegelian thought. I summarize the Pittsburgh School philosophers’ claims about the myth of the given, the claim that human experience is conceptual all the way out, and that we live in a space of reasons. I show how Hegel has been read in those terms, and then apply that reading of Hegel to Marx’s argument that capital is akin to what Hegel called Geist, or spirit. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. Sellars and the Space of Reasons [Sellars y el espacio de las razones].John McDowell - unknown
    In Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind Sellars introduces the image of the space of reasons, and delineates a non-traditional empiricism, uncontaminated by the Myth of the Given. Brandom takes Sellars’s drift to be against empiricism as such, against the very idea that something deserving to be called “experience” could be relevant to the acquisition of empirical knowledge in any way except merely causally. In this paper I attack Brandom’s idea that we anyway need a concession to externalism (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  54
    How Far Can Genealogies Affect the Space of Reasons? Vindication, Justification and Excuses.Francesco Testini - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    Pragmatic vindicatory genealogies provide both a cause and a rationale and can thus affect the space of reasons. But how far is the space of reasons affected by this kind of genealogical argument? What normative and evaluative implications do these arguments have? In this paper, I unpack this issue into three different sub-questions and explain what kinds of reasons they provide, for whom are these reasons, and for what. In relation to this final sub-question (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Nonconceptual content and the "space of reasons".Richard G. Heck - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):483-523.
    In Mind and World, John McDowell argues against the view that perceptual representation is non-conceptual. The central worry is that this view cannot offer any reasonable account of how perception bears rationally upon belief. I argue that this worry, though sensible, can be met, if we are clear that perceptual representation is, though non-conceptual, still in some sense 'assertoric': Perception, like belief, represents things as being thus and so.
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   248 citations  
  8. Epistemic Injustice in the space of reasons.Matthew Congdon - 2015 - Episteme 12 (1):75-93.
    In this paper, I make explicit some implicit commitments to realism and conceptualism in recent work in social epistemology exemplified by Miranda Fricker and Charles Mills. I offer a survey of recent writings at the intersection of social epistemology, feminism, and critical race theory, showing that commitments to realism and conceptualism are at once implied yet undertheorized in the existing literature. I go on to offer an explicit defense of these commitments by drawing from the epistemological framework of John McDowell, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  9. Naturalizing the space of reasons.Bill Pollard - 2005 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 13 (1):69 – 82.
    Given the Sellarsian distinction between the space of causes and the space of reasons, the naturalist seeks to articulate how these two spaces are unproblematically related. In Mind and World (1996) John McDowell suggests that such a naturalism can be achieved by pointing out that we work our way into the space of reasons by the process of upbringing he calls Bildung. 'The resulting habits of thought and action', writes McDowell, 'are second nature' (p. 84). (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  10.  71
    Nonconceptual Content and the "Space of Reasons".Richard G. Heck Jr - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):483 - 523.
    In The Varieties of Reference, Gareth Evans argues that the content of perceptual experience is nonconceptual, in a sense I shall explain momentarily. More recently, in his book Mind and World, John McDowell has argued that the reasons Evans gives for this claim are not compelling and, moreover, that Evans’s view is a version of “the Myth of the Given”: More precisely, Evans’s view is alleged to suffer from the same sorts of problems that plague sense-datum theories of perception. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  11. The space of reasons vs. the space of inference: Reply to Noe.Susan L. Hurley - 2002
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  5
    Exploring the Space of Reasons.David Bakhurst - 2011 - In The Formation of Reason. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 99–122.
    This chapter contains sections titled: McDowell on the Space of Reasons Brandom's Inferentialism Ilyenkov on the Ideal Conclusion.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  26
    Implicit Trust in the Space of Reasons and Implications for Technology Design: A Response to Justine Pila.Annamaria Carusi - 2009 - Social Epistemology 23 (1):25-43.
    In this issue, Pila (2009) has criticised the recommendations made by requirements engineers involved in the design of a grid technology for the support of distributed readings of mammograms made by Jirotka et al. (2005). The disagreement between them turns on the notion of “biographical familiarity” and whether it can be a sound basis for trust for the performances of professionals such as radiologists. In the first two sections, this paper gives an interpretation of the position of each side in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  22
    Aliens in the Space of Reasons? On the Interaction Between Humans and Artificial Intelligent Agents.Bert Heinrichs & Sebastian Knell - 2021 - Philosophy and Technology 34 (4):1569-1580.
    In this paper, we use some elements of the philosophical theories of Wilfrid Sellars and Robert Brandom for examining the interactions between humans and machines. In particular, we adopt the concept of the space of reasons for analyzing the status of artificial intelligent agents. One could argue that AIAs, like the widely used recommendation systems, have already entered the space of reasons, since they seem to make knowledge claims that we use as premises for further claims. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Animal action in the space of reasons.Susan Hurley - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (3):231-256.
    I defend the view that we should not overintellectualize the mind. Nonhuman animals can occupy islands of practical rationality: they can have contextbound reasons for action even though they lack full conceptual abilities. Holism and the possibility of mistake are required for such reasons to be the agent's reasons, but these requirements can be met in the absence of inferential promiscuity. Empirical work with animals is used to illustrate the possibility that reasons for action could be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  16. Naturalism and the Space of Reasons in Mind and World.T. H. Ho - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (1):49-62.
    This paper aims to show that many criticisms of McDowell’s naturalism of second nature are based on what I call ‘the orthodox interpretation’ of McDowell’s naturalism. The orthodox interpretation is, however, a misinterpretation, which results from the fact that the phrase ‘the space of reasons’ is used equivocally by McDowell in Mind and World. Failing to distinguish two senses of ‘the space of reasons’, I argue that the orthodox interpretation renders McDowell’s naturalism inconsistent with McDowell’s Hegelian (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  11
    Implicit trust in the space of reasons and implications for technology design: a response to Justine Pila: Implicit trust in the space of reasons: a response to Justine Pila.Annamaria Carusi - unknown
    In a recent paper, Pila has criticised the recommendations made by requirements engineers involved in the design of a grid technology for the support of distributed readings of mammograms made by Jirotka et al. The disagreement between them turns on the notion of ‘biographical familiarity’ and whether it can be a sound basis for trust for the performances of professionals such as radiologists. In the first two sections, the paper gives an interpretation of the position of each side in this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  58
    Life and the Space of Reasons: On Hegel’s Subjective Logic.Karen Ng - 2019 - Hegel Bulletin 40 (1):121-142.
    This paper defends Hegel’s positive contribution in the Subjective Logic and argues that it can be understood as presenting a compelling account of the space of reasons as a form of second nature. Taking Hegel’s praise of Kant’s conception of internal purposiveness and its connection to what he calls the Idea as a point of departure, I argue that Hegel’s theory of the Idea that concludes theLogicmust be understood in direct reference to Kant’s argument in the thirdCritiquethat purposiveness (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. In the space of reasons: selected essays of Wilfrid Sellars.Wilfrid Sellars - 2007 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Edited by Kevin Scharp & Robert Brandom.
    Inference and meaning -- Some reflections on language games -- Language as thought and as communication -- Meaning as functional classification : a perspective on the relation of syntax to semantics -- Naming and saying -- Grammar and existence : a preface to ontology -- Abstract entities -- Being and being known -- The lever of Archimedes -- Some reflections on thoughts and things -- Mental events -- Phenomenalism -- The identity approach to the mind-body problem -- Philosophy and the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  20.  26
    Animal Action in the Space of Reasons.Susan Hurley - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (3):231-257.
    I defend the view that we should not overintellectualize the mind. Nonhuman animals can occupy islands of practical rationality: they can have context‐bound reasons for action even though they lack full conceptual abilities. Holism and the possibility of mistake are required for such reasons to be the agent's reasons, but these requirements can be met in the absence of inferential promiscuity. Empirical work with animals is used to illustrate the possibility that reasons for action could be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  21.  47
    In the Space of Reasonable Doubt.Marion Vorms & Ulrike Hahn - 2019 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 15):3609-3633.
    This paper explores ‘reasonable doubt’ as an enlightening notion to think of reasoning and decision-making generally, beyond the judicial domain. The paper starts from a decision-theoretic understanding of the notion, whereby it can be defined in terms of degrees of belief and a probabilistic confirmation threshold for action. It then highlights some of the limits of this notion, and proposes a richer analysis of epistemic states and reasoning through the lens of ‘reasonable doubt’, which in turn is likely to supplement (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  53
    Out of the Space of Reasons: Argumentation, agents, and persons.Christopher W. Tindale - 2011 - Pragmatics and Cognition 19 (3):383-398.
    The paper investigates the `logical space of reasons' as a social space in which rational agents operate and persons in an important sense come to be. Building from an investigation of argumentative agents in Aristotle's Rhetoric, I discuss both interior and exterior criteria for personhood and propose that the latter shows how argumentation, as a principal activity of the space of reasons, results in the particular kinds of persons we recognize there as rational agents. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  26
    Case Classification, Similarities, Spaces of Reasons, and Coherences.Marcello Guarini - unknown
    A simple recurrent artificial neural network is used to classify situations as permissible or impermissible. The trained ANN can be understood as having set up a similarity space of cases at the level of its internal or hidden units. An analysis of the network’s internal representations is undertaken using a new visualization technique for state space approaches to understanding similarity. Insights from the literature on moral philosophy pertaining to contributory standards will be used to interpret the state (...) set up by the ANN as being structured by implicit reasons. The ANN, on its own, is not capable of explicitly representing or offering reasons to itself or others. That said, the low level similarity space set up by the network could be made available to higher order processes that exploit it for case-based reasoning. It is argued that for normative purposes, similarity could be seen as a contributor to procedural coherence in case-based reasoning and local forms of substantive coherence, but not to global forms of coherence given the computational complexity of managing those more ambitious forms of coherence. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Perceptual attention and the space of reasons.Johannes Roessler - 2011 - In Christopher Mole, Declan Smithies & Wayne Wu (eds.), Attention: Philosophical and Psychological Essays. Oxford University Press. pp. 274.
  25. How Genealogies Can Affect the Space of Reasons.Matthieu Queloz - 2020 - Synthese 197 (5):2005-2027.
    Can genealogical explanations affect the space of reasons? Those who think so commonly face two objections. The first objection maintains that attempts to derive reasons from claims about the genesis of something commit the genetic fallacy—they conflate genesis and justification. One way for genealogies to side-step this objection is to focus on the functional origins of practices—to show that, given certain facts about us and our environment, certain conceptual practices are rational because apt responses. But this invites (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  26.  38
    Living in the “space of reasons”: The “rationality debate” revisited.David Davies - 1999 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (3):231 – 244.
    Two questions are central to the “rationality debate” in the philosophy of social science. First, should we acknowledge differences in basic norms of epistemic and agential rationality, or in the content of perceptual experience, as the “best explanation” of radical differences in belief and practice? Second, can genuine understanding be achieved between cultures and research traditions that so differ in their beliefs and practices? I survey a number of responses to these questions, and suggest that one of these, “dialogical optimism”, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Meeting Others in the Space of Reasons: Fallibilism for Sellarsians.Mark Owen Webb - 2007 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 92 (1):217-231.
    Certainty has proved to be a troublesome epistemological concept, which motivates many philosophers to be fallibilists. But fallibilism proves troublesome, too, as it is hard to state in a way that does not either imply skepticism, or deny that there are necessary truths. The Sellarsian idea of a space of reasons in which there are normative proprieties attached to epistemic positions allows for an understanding of fallibilism which allows that there is knowledge, there are necessary truths, and yet (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  58
    Implicit Trust in the Space of Reasons.Annamaria Carusi - 2009 - Journal of Social Epistemology 23 (1):25-43.
    Pila (2009) has criticised the recommendations made by requirements engineers involved in the design of a grid technology for the support of distributed readings of mammograms made by Jirotka et al. (2005). The disagreement between them turns on the notion of “biographical familiarity” and whether it can be a sound basis for trust for the performances of professionals such as radiologists. In the first two sections, this paper gives an interpretation of the position of each side in this disagreement and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  45
    Extending the Space of Reasons: Comments on Chapter Four of Understanding People.Adrian Haddock - 2007 - SWIF Philosophy of Mind 6 (1).
    Wilfrid Sellars employs the metaphor of the space of reasons to express a certain conception of knowledge: “in characterising an episode or state as that of knowing … one is placing it in the logical space of reasons, of justifying and being able to justify what one says”.1 A growing number of philosophers employ the same metaphor to express a conception of at least some (other) mental states: in characterising a state as that of belief, or (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  19
    Explication in the Space of Reasons: What Sellars and Carnap Could Offer to Each Other.Krisztián Pete & Adam Tamas Tuboly - 2024 - Topoi 43 (1):171-185.
    In this paper, we reconsider the highly underrated Carnap–Sellars relationship, arguing that Sellars might be able to provide an interesting resolution to some of Carnap’s finest problems around explication by offering a grand-scale picture of science/common-sense or manifest interactions. The narrative developed here points toward the need for some stratification and re-evaluation of a field of scholarship that all too often still engages in challenging and contradictory dichotomies, undermining the genuine intentions of scholars who were collaborating with, as well as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  26
    Mental life in the space of reasons.Svend Brinkmann - 2006 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 36 (1):1–16.
  32.  33
    Spacings—of Reason and Imagination—in Texts of Kant, Fichte, Hegel. [REVIEW]Chip Sills - 1989 - The Owl of Minerva 21 (1):122-124.
    It is ironic that deconstructive criticism reveals itself most patently as neo-formalism in its treatment of Hegel. Sallis’s book resumes all the by-now-canonical elements of the Derridean conception of Hegel: Hegel as the philosopher of “closure” par excellence, Hegel as the last figure in “the metaphysics of presence,” Hegel as the philosopher most clever at dissembling his ideological preoccupations behind a facade of “reason.”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Diminished rationality and the space of reasons.Maura Tumulty - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (4):pp. 601-629.
    Some theories of language, thought, and experience require their adherents to say unpalatable things about human individuals whose capacities for rational activity are seriously diminished. Donald Davidson, for example, takes the interdependence of the concepts of thought and language to entail that thoughts may only be attributed to an individual who is an interpreter of others’ speech. And John McDowell's account of human experience as the involuntary exercise of conceptual capacities can be applied easily only to individuals who make some (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  16
    Facing the Space of Reasons.Kevin Houser - 2016 - Levinas Studies 11 (1):121-148.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Facing the Space of ReasonsKevin Houser (bio)The Face and ExplanationAnalytic philosophers often appeal to reason and reasons to explain ethics. By Levinasian lights, this is backward. It is not because we are already open to reason that we are ethically open to others. It is through “the welcoming of [others] that the will opens to reason.” We do not respond to others’ needs because we are reasonable; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  18
    Facing the Space of Reasons.Kevin Houser - 2016 - Levinas Studies 11 (1):121-148.
    Analytic philosophers often appeal to Reason and reasons to explain ethical relations. By Levinasian lights, this is backwards. It is not because we are already open to Reason that we are ethically open to others. It is through “the welcoming of [others] that the will opens to Reason.” We do not respond to others’ needs because we are reasonable; being reasonable is itself “a response to . . . a face, [who already] speaks.” The structure of reason, theoretical or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Experience and the Space of Reasons.Mohammad Azadpur - 2020 - Sophia Perennis 17 (37):5-35.
    Throughout their writings, John McDowell and Richard Rorty draw on Kant’s influential account of experience. For Rorty, Kant is the antagonist who succumbs to foundationalism or what Sellars calls the Myth of the Given and Wittgenstein is the hero who helps in overcoming the siren call of the Myth. McDowell, however, is ambivalent toward Kant. With Sellars, he applauds Kant as the hero who helped us vanquish the Myth of the Given. But he argues that Kant failed to recognize the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  43
    Spacings—of Reason and Imagination—in Texts of Kant, Fichte, Hegel. [REVIEW]Chip Sills - 1989 - The Owl of Minerva 21 (1):122-124.
    It is no secret that Hegel, along with Vico, whom he never read, and Rousseau, whom he read with enthusiasm, regarded poetic meaning as historically prior to prosaic meaning - the figurative preceded the literal, the tropological antedated the logical per se. Indeed, Hegel went so far, in his Aesthetic, as to qualify poetry as “Man’s original grasp of truth”. Since, as we know, for Hegel the true is the whole, it would seem that this original grasp of the truth (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Agency in the Space of Reasons. A Comment on The Castle.Josep E. Corbi - 2021 - In Tomas Koblízek and Petr Kotátko (ed.), Lessons From Kafka. Prague, Czechia: pp. 113-140.
    The received view about rationalizing explanations divides our psychological status into two kinds: beliefs and desires. In *The Retrieval of Ethics*, Talbot Brewer makes a case against this view. In this paper, I examine our experience as readers of *The Castle* by Franz Kafka to support Brewer's critical program, that is, his challenge to the received view. I will argue, however, that a proper analysis of this experience poses a serious problem to Brewer's alternative approach, that is, to his attempt (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Locating the Space of Reasons.Jennifer Church - 2006 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 25 (1):85-96.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  64
    Intersubjectivity and the “Space of Reasons”: Fichte in the Post-Analytic Context.Peter Dews - 2008 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 29 (1):133-159.
  41. Experience and the Space of Reasons: The Problem of Non-Doxastic Justification.Hamid Vahid - 2008 - Erkenntnis 69 (3):295-313.
    It is not difficult to make sense of the idea that beliefs may derive their justification from other beliefs. Difficulties surface when, as in certain epistemological theories, one appeals to sensory experiences to give an account of the structure of justification. This gives rise to the so-called problem of ‘nondoxastic justification’, namely, the problem of seeing how sensory experiences can confer justification on the beliefs they give rise to. In this paper, I begin by criticizing a number of theories that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  48
    Knowledge First” and “The Space of Reasons.Jiaming Chen - 2016 - Philosophical Forum 47 (3-4):425-437.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  6
    Knowledge and the Space of Reasons: The Ideas of John McDowell and Paul Hirst.Geoffrey Hinchliffe - 2014 - Philosophy of Education 70:107-114.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Inhabiting the space of reasoning.Jeremy Wanderer - 2010 - Analysis 70 (2):367-378.
  45.  41
    Intersubjectivity in the space of reason.Barbara Fultner - 2001 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 27 (1):107-114.
    Representing, and Discursive Commitment (reviewed by Barbara Fultner).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  41
    Epistemic injustice in the space of reasons – erratum.Matthew Congdon - 2015 - Episteme 12 (3):427-427.
  47. John Sallis, SPACINGS-of Reason and Imagination IN TEXTS of Kant, Fichte, Hegel Reviewed by.Chernor M. Jalloh - 1988 - Philosophy in Review 8 (2):71-73.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  8
    Intentionality and the" social" space of reasons.Raffaela Giovagnoli - 2005 - Epistemologia 28 (1).
  49. Intersubjectivity in the Space of Reasons.Robert B. Brandom - 2001 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 27 (1):107-114.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  15
    Particularism and the space of moral reasons.Benedict Smith - 2011 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    By explicitly addressing moral knowledge from a particularists perspective, this book can engage with an established and vibrant area of moral philosophy whilst making a distinctive and productive contribution to a relatively neglected dimension of it.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000