Results for ' cardinal sequence'

991 found
Order:
  1.  16
    Cardinal sequences.István Juhász & William Weiss - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 144 (1-3):96-106.
    In this article we characterize all those sequences of cardinals of length ω1 which are cardinal sequences of some compact scattered space . This extends the similar results from [R. La Grange, Concerning the cardinal sequence of a Boolean algebra, Algebra Universalis, 7 307–313] for such sequences of countable length. For ordinals between ω1 and ω2 we can only give a sufficient condition for a sequence of that length to be a cardinal sequence of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Cardinal sequences of LCS spaces under GCH.Juan Carlos Martinez & Lajos Soukup - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (9):1180-1193.
    Let denote the class of all cardinal sequences of length α associated with compact scattered spaces. Also put If λ is a cardinal and α λ1>>λn−1 and ordinals α0,…,αn−1 such that α=α0++αn−1 and where each .The proofs are based on constructions of universal locally compact scattered spaces.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  18
    A consistency result on cardinal sequences of scattered Boolean spaces.Juan C. Martínez - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (6):586-590.
    We prove that if GCH holds and τ = 〈κα : α < η 〉 is a sequence of infinite cardinals such that κα ≥ |η | for each α < η, then there is a cardinal-preserving partial order that forces the existence of a scattered Boolean space whose cardinal sequence is τ.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  16
    On uncountable cardinal sequences for superatomic Boolean algebras.Juan Carlos Martínez - 1995 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 34 (4):257-261.
    The countable sequences of cardinals which arise as cardinal sequences of superatomic Boolean algebras were characterized by La Grange on the basis of ZFC set theory. However, no similar characterization is available for uncountable cardinal sequences. In this paper we prove the following two consistency results:Ifθ = 〈κ α :α <ω 1〉 is a sequence of infinite cardinals, then there is a cardinal-preserving notion of forcing that changes cardinal exponentiation and forces the existence of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  5
    A consistency result on long cardinal sequences.Juan Carlos Martínez & Lajos Soukup - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (10):103017.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Laver Sequences for Extendible and Super-Almost-Huge Cardinals.Paul Corazza - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (3):963-983.
    Versions of Laver sequences are known to exist for supercompact and strong cardinals. Assuming very strong axioms of infinity, Laver sequences can be constructed for virtually any globally defined large cardinal not weaker than a strong cardinal; indeed, under strong hypotheses, Laver sequences can be constructed for virtually any regular class of embeddings. We show here that if there is a regular class of embeddings with critical point $\kappa$, and there is an inaccessible above $\kappa$, then it is (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  33
    Indiscernible sequences for extenders, and the singular cardinal hypothesis.Moti Gitik & William J. Mitchell - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 82 (3):273-316.
    We prove several results giving lower bounds for the large cardinal strength of a failure of the singular cardinal hypothesis. The main result is the following theorem: Theorem. Suppose κ is a singular strong limit cardinal and 2κ λ where λ is not the successor of a cardinal of cofinality at most κ. If cf > ω then it follows that o λ, and if cf = ωthen either o λ or {α: K o α+n} is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  8. Laver sequences for extendible and super-almost-huge cardinals.Paul Corazza - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (3):963-983.
    Versions of Laver sequences are known to exist for supercompact and strong cardinals. Assuming very strong axioms of infinity, Laver sequences can be constructed for virtually any globally defined large cardinal not weaker than a strong cardinal; indeed, under strong hypotheses, Laver sequences can be constructed for virtually any regular class of embeddings. We show here that if there is a regular class of embeddings with critical point κ, and there is an inaccessible above κ, then it is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  9.  16
    Large cardinals and basic sequences.Jordi Lopez-Abad - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (12):1390-1417.
    The purpose of this paper is to present several applications of combinatorial principles, well-known in Set Theory, to the geometry of infinite dimensional Banach spaces, particularly to the existence of certain basic sequences. We mention also some open problems where set-theoretical techniques are relevant.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  16
    Relations between cardinalities of the finite sequences and the finite subsets of a set.Navin Aksornthong & Pimpen Vejjajiva - 2018 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 64 (6):529-534.
    We write and for the cardinalities of the set of finite sequences and the set of finite subsets, respectively, of a set which is of cardinality. With the axiom of choice (), for every infinite cardinal but, without, any relationship between and for an arbitrary infinite cardinal cannot be proved. In this paper, we give conditions that make and comparable for an infinite cardinal. Among our results, we show that, if we assume the axiom of choice for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  26
    Changing cardinal characteristics without changing ω-sequences or cofinalities.Heike Mildenberger & Saharon Shelah - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 106 (1-3):207-261.
    We show: There are pairs of universes V1V2 and there is a notion of forcing PV1 such that the change mentioned in the title occurs when going from V1[G] to V2[G] for a P-generic filter G over V2. We use forcing iterations with partial memories. Moreover, we implement highly transitive automorphism groups into the forcing orders.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  30
    No decreasing sequence of cardinals.Paul Howard & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (3-4):415-429.
    In set theory without the Axiom of Choice, we investigate the set-theoretic strength of the principle NDS which states that there is no function f on the set ω of natural numbers such that for everyn ∈ ω, f ≺ f, where for sets x and y, x ≺ y means that there is a one-to-one map g : x → y, but no one-to-one map h : y → x. It is a long standing open problem whether NDS implies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  8
    On certain arbitrarily long sequences of cardinals.John Truss - 1973 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 19 (14‐18):209-210.
  14.  5
    Two-Cardinal Derived Topologies, Indescribability and Ramseyness.Brent Cody, Chris Lambie-Hanson & Jing Zhang - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-29.
    We introduce a natural two-cardinal version of Bagaria’s sequence of derived topologies on ordinals. We prove that for our sequence of two-cardinal derived topologies, limit points of sets can be characterized in terms of a new iterated form of pairwise simultaneous reflection of certain kinds of stationary sets, the first few instances of which are often equivalent to notions related to strong stationarity, which has been studied previously in the context of strongly normal ideals. The non-discreteness (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  17
    Ernest Schimmerling. Covering properties of core models. Sets and proofs. (Leeds, 1997), London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series 258. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999, pp. 281–299. - Peter Koepke. An introduction to extenders and core models for extender sequences. Logic Colloquium '87 (Granada, 1987), Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics 129. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1989, pp. 137–182. - William J. Mitchell. The core model up to a Woodin cardinal. Logic, methodology and philosophy of science, IX (Uppsala, 1991), Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics 134, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1994, pp. 157–175. - Benedikt Löwe and John R. Steel. An introduction to core model theory. Sets and proofs (Leeds, 1997), London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series 258, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999, pp. 103–157. - John R. Steel. Inner models with many Woodin cardinals. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 65 no. 2 (1993), pp. 185–209. -.Martin Zeman - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):583-588.
  16.  10
    Cardinal characteristics on graphs.Nick Haverkamp - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (1):1 - 33.
    A cardinal characteristic can often be described as the smallest size of a family of sequences which has a given property. Instead of this traditional concern for a smallest realization of the given property, a basically new approach, taken in [4] and [5], asks for a realization whose members are sequences of labels that correspond to 1-way infinite paths in a labelled graph. We study this approach as such, establishing tools that are applicable to all these cardinal characteristics. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  14
    Free sequences in $${\mathscr {P}}\left( \omega \right) /\text {fin}$$.David Chodounský, Vera Fischer & Jan Grebík - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (7-8):1035-1051.
    We investigate maximal free sequences in the Boolean algebra \ {/}\text {fin}\), as defined by Monk :593–610, 2011). We provide some information on the general structure of these objects and we are particularly interested in the minimal cardinality of a free sequence, a cardinal characteristic of the continuum denoted \. Answering a question of Monk, we demonstrate the consistency of \. In fact, this consistency is demonstrated in the model of Shelah for \ :433–443, 1992). Our paper provides (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  22
    Free sequences in $${mathscr {P}}left /text {fin}$$ P ω / fin.David Chodounský, Vera Fischer & Jan Grebík - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (7-8):1035-1051.
    We investigate maximal free sequences in the Boolean algebra \ {/}\text {fin}\), as defined by Monk :593–610, 2011). We provide some information on the general structure of these objects and we are particularly interested in the minimal cardinality of a free sequence, a cardinal characteristic of the continuum denoted \. Answering a question of Monk, we demonstrate the consistency of \. In fact, this consistency is demonstrated in the model of Shelah for \ :433–443, 1992). Our paper provides (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  13
    Free sequences in $${mathscr {P}}left /text {fin}$$ P ω / fin.David Chodounský, Vera Fischer & Jan Grebík - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (7-8):1035-1051.
    We investigate maximal free sequences in the Boolean algebra \ {/}\text {fin}\), as defined by Monk :593–610, 2011). We provide some information on the general structure of these objects and we are particularly interested in the minimal cardinality of a free sequence, a cardinal characteristic of the continuum denoted \. Answering a question of Monk, we demonstrate the consistency of \. In fact, this consistency is demonstrated in the model of Shelah for \ :433–443, 1992). Our paper provides (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  9
    Controlling cardinal characteristics without adding reals.Martin Goldstern, Jakob Kellner, Diego A. Mejía & Saharon Shelah - 2021 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 21 (3):2150018.
    We investigate the behavior of cardinal characteristics of the reals under extensions that do not add new [Formula: see text]-sequences (for some regular [Formula: see text]). As an application, we show that consistently the following cardinal characteristics can be different: The (“independent”) characteristics in Cichoń’s diagram, plus [Formula: see text]. (So we get thirteen different values, including [Formula: see text] and continuum). We also give constructions to alternatively separate other MA-numbers (instead of [Formula: see text]), namely: MA for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  4
    Controlling cardinal characteristics without adding reals.Martin Goldstern, Jakob Kellner, Diego A. Mejía & Saharon Shelah - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 21 (3).
    We investigate the behavior of cardinal characteristics of the reals under extensions that do not add new <κ-sequences. As an application, we show that consistently the followi...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  6
    When cardinals determine the power set: inner models and Härtig quantifier logic.Jouko Väänänen & Philip D. Welch - forthcoming - Mathematical Logic Quarterly.
    We show that the predicate “x is the power set of y” is ‐definable, if V = L[E] is an extender model constructed from a coherent sequences of extenders, provided that there is no inner model with a Woodin cardinal. Here is a predicate true of just the infinite cardinals. From this we conclude: the validities of second order logic are reducible to, the set of validities of the Härtig quantifier logic. Further we show that if no L[E] model (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  8
    Ernest Schimmerling. Covering properties of core models. Sets and proofs. , London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series 258. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999, pp. 281–299. - Peter Koepke. An introduction to extenders and core models for extender sequences. Logic Colloquium '87 , Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics 129. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1989, pp. 137–182. - William J. Mitchell. The core model up to a Woodin cardinal. Logic, methodology and philosophy of science, IX , Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics 134, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1994, pp. 157–175. - Benedikt Löwe and John R. Steel. An introduction to core model theory. Sets and proofs , London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series 258, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999, pp. 103–157. - John R. Steel. Inner models with many Woodin cardinals. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 65 no. 2 , pp. 185–209. - Ernest Schimmerling. Combinatorial principles in the core mode. [REVIEW]Martin Zeman - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):583-588.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  34
    Cardinal Invariants and the Collapse of the Continuum by Sacks Forcing.Miroslav Repický - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (2):711 - 727.
    We study cardinal invariants of systems of meager hereditary families of subsets of ω connected with the collapse of the continuum by Sacks forcing S and we obtain a cardinal invariant yω such that S collapses the continuum to yω and y ≤ yω ≤ b. Applying the Baumgartner-Dordal theorem on preservation of eventually narrow sequences we obtain the consistency of y = yω < b. We define two relations $\leq _{0}^{\ast}$ and $\leq _{1}^{\ast}$ on the set $(^{\omega}\omega)_{{\rm (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  16
    Moti Gitik and Menachem Magidor. Extender based forcings. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 59 , pp. 445–460. - Moti Gitik and William J. Mitchell. Indiscernible sequences for extenders, and the singular cardinal hypothesis. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 82 , pp. 273–316. - Moti Gitik. Blowing up the power of a singular cardinal. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 80 , pp. 17–33. - Moti Gitik and Carmi Merimovich. Possible values for and. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 90 , pp. 193–241. - Moti Gitik. Blowing up power of a singular cardinal—wider gaps. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 116 , pp. 1–38. [REVIEW]Akihiro Kanamori - 2003 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (2):237-241.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  22
    Towers in filters, cardinal invariants, and luzin type families.Jörg Brendle, Barnabás Farkas & Jonathan Verner - 2018 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 83 (3):1013-1062.
    We investigate which filters onωcan contain towers, that is, a modulo finite descending sequence without any pseudointersection. We prove the following results:Many classical examples of nice tall filters contain no towers.It is consistent that tall analytic P-filters contain towers of arbitrary regular height.It is consistent that all towers generate nonmeager filters, in particular Borel filters do not contain towers.The statement “Every ultrafilter contains towers.” is independent of ZFC.Furthermore, we study many possible logical implications between the existence of towers in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27.  19
    The large cardinals between supercompact and almost-huge.Norman Lewis Perlmutter - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (3-4):257-289.
    I analyze the hierarchy of large cardinals between a supercompact cardinal and an almost-huge cardinal. Many of these cardinals are defined by modifying the definition of a high-jump cardinal. A high-jump cardinal is defined as the critical point of an elementary embedding j:V→M\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${j: V \to M}$$\end{document} such that M is closed under sequences of length sup{j|f:κ→κ}\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\sup\{{j\,|\,f: \kappa \to \kappa}\}}$$\end{document}. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  58
    Making all cardinals almost Ramsey.Arthur W. Apter & Peter Koepke - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (7-8):769-783.
    We examine combinatorial aspects and consistency strength properties of almost Ramsey cardinals. Without the Axiom of Choice, successor cardinals may be almost Ramsey. From fairly mild supercompactness assumptions, we construct a model of ZF + ${\neg {\rm AC}_\omega}$ in which every infinite cardinal is almost Ramsey. Core model arguments show that strong assumptions are necessary. Without successors of singular cardinals, we can weaken this to an equiconsistency of the following theories: “ZFC + There is a proper class of regular (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29.  12
    Successive cardinals with no partial square.John Krueger - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (1-2):11-21.
    We construct a model in which for all 1 ≤ n < ω, there is no stationary subset of ${\aleph_{n+1} \cap {\rm cof}(\aleph_n)}$ which carries a partial square.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  22
    Forcing with Sequences of Models of Two Types.Itay Neeman - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (2):265-298.
    We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work of Friedman and Mitchell on forcing to add clubs in cardinals larger than $\aleph_{1}$, with finite conditions. We use the two-type approach to give a new proof of the consistency of the proper forcing axiom. The new proof uses a finite support forcing, as opposed to the countable support iteration in the standard proof. The distinction is important (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  31.  27
    Indiscernible sequences in a model which fails to have the order property.Rami Grossberg - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1):115-123.
    Basic results on the model theory of substructures of a fixed model are presented. The main point is to avoid the use of the compactness theorem, so this work can easily be applied to the model theory of L ω 1 ,ω and its relatives. Among other things we prove the following theorem: Let M be a model, and let λ be a cardinal satisfying λ |L(M)| = λ. If M does not have the ω-order property, then for every (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  12
    Factorials and the finite sequences of sets.Nattapon Sonpanow & Pimpen Vejjajiva - 2019 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 65 (1):116-120.
    We write for the cardinality of the set of finite sequences of a set which is of cardinality. With the Axiom of Choice (), for every infinite cardinal where is the cardinality of the permutations on a set which is of cardinality. In this paper, we show that “ for every cardinal ” is provable in and this is the best possible result in the absence of. Similar results are also obtained for : the cardinality of the set (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33.  14
    Consecutive Singular Cardinals and the Continuum Function.Arthur W. Apter & Brent Cody - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (2):125-136.
    We show that from a supercompact cardinal $\kappa$, there is a forcing extension $V[G]$ that has a symmetric inner model $N$ in which $\mathrm {ZF}+\lnot\mathrm {AC}$ holds, $\kappa$ and $\kappa^{+}$ are both singular, and the continuum function at $\kappa$ can be precisely controlled, in the sense that the final model contains a sequence of distinct subsets of $\kappa$ of length equal to any predetermined ordinal. We also show that the above situation can be collapsed to obtain a model (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  12
    Club guessing sequences and filters.Tetsuya Ishiu - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (4):1037-1071.
    We investigate club guessing sequences and filters. We prove that assuming V=L, there exists a strong club guessing sequence on μ if and only if μ is not ineffable for every uncountable regular cardinal μ. We also prove that for every uncountable regular cardinal μ, relative to the existence of a Woodin cardinal above μ, it is consistent that every tail club guessing ideal on μ is precipitous.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35.  16
    Completeness of the Gödel–Löb Provability Logic for the Filter Sequence of Normal Measures.Mohammad Golshani & Reihane Zoghifard - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):163-174.
    Assuming the existence of suitable large cardinals, we show it is consistent that the Provability logic $\mathbf {GL}$ is complete with respect to the filter sequence of normal measures. This result answers a question of Andreas Blass from 1990 and a related question of Beklemishev and Joosten.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  9
    On categoricity in successive cardinals.Sebastien Vasey - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-19.
    We investigate, in ZFC, the behavior of abstract elementary classes categorical in many successive small cardinals. We prove for example that a universal $\mathbb {L}_{\omega _1, \omega }$ sentence categorical on an end segment of cardinals below $\beth _\omega $ must be categorical also everywhere above $\beth _\omega $. This is done without any additional model-theoretic hypotheses and generalizes to the much broader framework of tame AECs with weak amalgamation and coherent sequences.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  6
    On categoricity in successive cardinals.Sebastien Vasey - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (2):545-563.
    We investigate, in ZFC, the behavior of abstract elementary classes categorical in many successive small cardinals. We prove for example that a universal $\mathbb {L}_{\omega _1, \omega }$ sentence categorical on an end segment of cardinals below $\beth _\omega $ must be categorical also everywhere above $\beth _\omega $. This is done without any additional model-theoretic hypotheses and generalizes to the much broader framework of tame AECs with weak amalgamation and coherent sequences.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  15
    Factorials of infinite cardinals in zf part I: Zf results.Guozhen Shen & Jiachen Yuan - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (1):224-243.
    For a set x, let ${\cal S}\left$ be the set of all permutations of x. We prove in ZF several results concerning this notion, among which are the following: For all sets x such that ${\cal S}\left$ is Dedekind infinite, $\left| {{{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left} \right| < \left| {{\cal S}\left} \right|$ and there are no finite-to-one functions from ${\cal S}\left$ into ${{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left$, where ${{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left$ denotes the set of all permutations of x which move only finitely many elements. For all sets (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  29
    Factorials of infinite cardinals in zf part II: Consistency results.Guozhen Shen & Jiachen Yuan - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (1):244-270.
    For a set x, let S(x) be the set of all permutations of x. We prove by the method of permutation models that the following statements are consistent with ZF: (1) There is an infinite set x such that |p(x)|<|S(x)|<|seq^1-1(x)|<|seq(x)|, where p(x) is the powerset of x, seq(x) is the set of all finite sequences of elements of x, and seq^1-1(x) is the set of all finite sequences of elements of x without repetition. (2) There is a Dedekind infinite set (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  72
    Sets constructible from sequences of ultrafilters.William J. Mitchell - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (1):57-66.
    In [4], Kunen used iterated ultrapowers to show that ifUis a normalκ-complete nontrivial ultrafilter on a cardinalκthenL[U], the class of sets constructive fromU, has only the ultrafilterU∩L[U] and this ultrafilter depends only onκ. In this paper we extend Kunen's methods to arbitrary sequencesUof ultrafilters and obtain generalizations of these results. In particular we answer Problem 1 of Kunen and Paris [5] which asks whether the number of ultrafilters onκcan be intermediate between 1 and 22κ. If there is a normalκ-complete ultrafilterUonκsuch (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  41.  10
    N-Berkeley cardinals and weak extender models.Raffaella Cutolo - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (2):809-816.
    For a given inner model N of ZFC, one can consider the relativized version of Berkeley cardinals in the context of ZFC, and ask if there can exist an “N-Berkeley cardinal.” In this article we provide a positive answer to this question. Indeed, under the assumption of a supercompact cardinal $\delta $, we show that there exists a ZFC inner model N such that there is a cardinal which is N-Berkeley, even in a strong sense. Further, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  15
    Muchnik degrees and cardinal characteristics.Benoit Monin & André Nies - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (2):471-498.
    A mass problem is a set of functions $\omega \to \omega $. For mass problems ${\mathcal {C}}, {\mathcal {D}}$, one says that ${\mathcal {C}}$ is Muchnik reducible to ${\mathcal {D}}$ if each function in ${\mathcal {C}}$ is computed by a function in ${\mathcal {D}}$. In this paper we study some highness properties of Turing oracles, which we view as mass problems. We compare them with respect to Muchnik reducibility and its uniform strengthening, Medvedev reducibility.For $p \in [0,1]$ let ${\mathcal {D}}$ (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  48
    Computable Diagonalizations and Turing’s Cardinality Paradox.Dale Jacquette - 2014 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 45 (2):239-262.
    A. N. Turing’s 1936 concept of computability, computing machines, and computable binary digital sequences, is subject to Turing’s Cardinality Paradox. The paradox conjoins two opposed but comparably powerful lines of argument, supporting the propositions that the cardinality of dedicated Turing machines outputting all and only the computable binary digital sequences can only be denumerable, and yet must also be nondenumerable. Turing’s objections to a similar kind of diagonalization are answered, and the implications of the paradox for the concept of a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Iterated Forcing and Coherent Sequences.M. C. Mcdermott - 1983
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  30
    Mice with finitely many Woodin cardinals from optimal determinacy hypotheses.Sandra Müller, Ralf Schindler & W. Hugh Woodin - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 20 (Supp01):1950013.
    We prove the following result which is due to the third author. Let [Formula: see text]. If [Formula: see text] determinacy and [Formula: see text] determinacy both hold true and there is no [Formula: see text]-definable [Formula: see text]-sequence of pairwise distinct reals, then [Formula: see text] exists and is [Formula: see text]-iterable. The proof yields that [Formula: see text] determinacy implies that [Formula: see text] exists and is [Formula: see text]-iterable for all reals [Formula: see text]. A consequence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  38
    Diamonds, compactness, and measure sequences.Omer Ben-Neria - 2019 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 19 (1):1950002.
    We establish the consistency of the failure of the diamond principle on a cardinal [Formula: see text] which satisfies a strong simultaneous reflection property. The result is based on an analysis of Radin forcing, and further leads to a characterization of weak compactness of [Formula: see text] in a Radin generic extension.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  10
    Coding by club-sequences.David Asperó - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 142 (1):98-114.
    Given any subset A of ω1 there is a proper partial order which forces that the predicate xA and the predicate xω1A can be expressed by -provably incompatible Σ3 formulas over the structure Hω2,,NSω1. Also, if there is an inaccessible cardinal, then there is a proper partial order which forces the existence of a well-order of Hω2 definable over Hω2,,NSω1 by a provably antisymmetric Σ3 formula with two free variables. The proofs of these results involve a technique for manipulating (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  6
    More on cardinal invariants of Boolean algebras.Andrzej Rosłanowski & Saharon Shelah - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 103 (1-3):1-37.
    We address several questions of Donald Monk related to irredundance and spread of Boolean algebras, gaining both some ZFC knowledge and consistency results. We show in ZFC that . We prove consistency of the statement “there is a Boolean algebra such that ” and we force a superatomic Boolean algebra such that , and . Next we force a superatomic algebra such that and a superatomic algebra such that . Finally we show that consistently there is a Boolean algebra of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  28
    The Consistency Strength of $$\aleph{\omega}$$ and $$\aleph_{{\omega}1}$$ Being Rowbottom Cardinals Without the Axiom of Choice.Arthur W. Apter & Peter Koepke - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (6):721-737.
    We show that for all natural numbers n, the theory “ZF + DC $_{\aleph_n}$ + $\aleph_{\omega}$ is a Rowbottom cardinal carrying a Rowbottom filter” has the same consistency strength as the theory “ZFC + There exists a measurable cardinal”. In addition, we show that the theory “ZF + $\aleph_{\omega_1}$ is an ω 2-Rowbottom cardinal carrying an ω 2-Rowbottom filter and ω 1 is regular” has the same consistency strength as the theory “ZFC + There exist ω 1 (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  34
    Distributive proper forcing axiom and cardinal invariants.Huiling Zhu - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (5-6):497-506.
    In this paper, we study the forcing axiom for the class of proper forcing notions which do not add ω sequence of ordinals. We study the relationship between this forcing axiom and many cardinal invariants. We use typical iterated forcing with large cardinals and analyse certain property being preserved in this process. Lastly, we apply the results to distinguish several forcing axioms.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 991