Results for ' Probability weighting'

988 found
Order:
  1.  9
    Nonlinear probability weighting can reflect attentional biases in sequential sampling.Veronika Zilker & Thorsten Pachur - 2022 - Psychological Review 129 (5):949-975.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  76
    Subjective Probability Weighting and the Discovered Preference Hypothesis.Gijs van de Kuilen - 2009 - Theory and Decision 67 (1):1-22.
    Numerous studies have convincingly shown that prospect theory can better describe risky choice behavior than the classical expected utility model because it makes the plausible assumption that risk aversion is driven not only by the degree of sensitivity toward outcomes, but also by the degree of sensitivity toward probabilities. This article presents the results of an experiment aimed at testing whether agents become more sensitive toward probabilities over time when they repeatedly face similar decisions, receive feedback on the consequences of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  8
    Probability weighting for losses and for gains among smallholder farmers in Uganda.Arjan Verschoor & Ben D’Exelle - 2020 - Theory and Decision 92 (1):223-258.
    Probability weighting is a marked feature of decision-making under risk. For poor people in rural areas of developing countries, how probabilities are evaluated matters for livelihoods decisions, especially the probabilities associated with losses. Previous studies of risky choice among poor people in developing countries seldom consider losses and do not offer a refined tracking of the probability-weighting function. We investigate probability weighting among smallholder farmers in Uganda, separately for losses and for gains, using a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Gender, Financial Risk, and Probability Weights.Helga Fehr-Duda, Manuele de Gennaro & Renate Schubert - 2006 - Theory and Decision 60 (2-3):283-313.
    Women are commonly stereotyped as more risk averse than men in financial decision making. In this paper we examine whether this stereotype reflects gender differences in actual risk-taking behavior by means of a laboratory experiment with monetary incentives. Gender differences in risk taking may be due to differences in valuations of outcomes or in probability weights. The results of our experiment indicate that value functions do not differ significantly between men and women. Men and women differ in their (...) weighting schemes, however. In general, women tend to be less sensitive to probability changes. They also tend to underestimate large probabilities of gains more strongly than do men. This effect is particularly pronounced when the decisions are framed in investment terms. As a result, women appear to be more risk averse than men in specific circumstances. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  5.  10
    Subjective Probability Weighting and the Discovered Preference Hypothesis.Gijs Kuilen - 2009 - Theory and Decision 67 (1):1-22.
    Numerous studies have convincingly shown that prospect theory can better describe risky choice behavior than the classical expected utility model because it makes the plausible assumption that risk aversion is driven not only by the degree of sensitivity toward outcomes, but also by the degree of sensitivity toward probabilities. This article presents the results of an experiment aimed at testing whether agents become more sensitive toward probabilities over time when they repeatedly face similar decisions, receive feedback on the consequences of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  6
    Gender, Financial Risk, and Probability Weights.Helga Fehr-Duda, Manuele Gennaro & Renate Schubert - 2006 - Theory and Decision 60 (2-3):283-313.
    Women are commonly stereotyped as more risk averse than men in financial decision making. In this paper we examine whether this stereotype reflects gender differences in actual risk-taking behavior by means of a laboratory experiment with monetary incentives. Gender differences in risk taking may be due to differences in valuations of outcomes or in probability weights. The results of our experiment indicate that value functions do not differ significantly between men and women. Men and women differ in their (...) weighting schemes, however. In general, women tend to be less sensitive to probability changes. They also tend to underestimate large probabilities of gains more strongly than do men. This effect is particularly pronounced when the decisions are framed in investment terms. As a result, women appear to be more risk averse than men in specific circumstances. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  7.  26
    Probability Weighting Functions Derived from Hyperbolic Time Discounting: Psychophysical Models and Their Individual Level Testing.Kazuhisa Takemura & Hajime Murakami - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  55
    Emotional balance and probability weighting.Narat Charupat, Richard Deaves, Travis Derouin, Marcelo Klotzle & Peter Miu - 2013 - Theory and Decision 75 (1):17-41.
    We find suggestive evidence that emotional balance has an impact on probability weighting incremental to demographic controls. Specifically, low negative affectivity (implying high emotional balance) tends to be a characteristic of those whose probability weighting functions exhibit lower curvature and more neutral elevation. In other words, emotional balance seems to push people in the direction of normative expected utility theory.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  31
    Neural Dynamics of Processing Probability Weight and Monetary Magnitude in the Evaluation of a Risky Reward.Guangrong Wang, Jianbiao Li, Pengcheng Wang, Chengkang Zhu, Jingjing Pan & Shuaiqi Li - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  55
    Error Propagation in the Elicitation of Utility and Probability Weighting Functions.Pavlo Blavatskyy - 2006 - Theory and Decision 60 (2-3):315-334.
    Elicitation methods in decision-making under risk allow us to infer the utilities of outcomes as well as the probability weights from the observed preferences of an individual. An optimally efficient elicitation method is proposed, which takes the inevitable distortion of preferences by random errors into account and minimizes the effect of such errors on the inferred utility and probability weighting functions. Under mild assumptions, the optimally efficient method for eliciting utilities and probability weights is the following (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11.  38
    Self-Distancing Reduces Probability-Weighting Biases.Qingzhou Sun, Huanren Zhang, Liyang Sai & Fengpei Hu - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  15
    Feedback Influences Discriminability and Attractiveness Components of Probability Weighting in Descriptive Choice Under Risk.Shruti Goyal & Krishna P. Miyapuram - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10:450108.
    Our understanding of the decisions made under scenarios where both descriptive and experience-based information are available is very limited. Underweighting of small probabilities was observed in the gain domain when both description and experience were provided. The divergence observed from the prospect theory suggests a need for a separate or modified theory of decision making under risk. Recent studies suggest a possible role of probability weighting in the choice behaviour under risk. We investigated both gain and loss domains (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Solving the St. Petersburg Paradox in cumulative prospect theory: the right amount of probability weighting.Marie Pfiffelmann - 2011 - Theory and Decision 71 (3):325-341.
    Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT) does not explain the St. Petersburg Paradox. We show that the solutions related to probability weighting proposed to solve this paradox, (Blavatskyy, Management Science 51:677–678, 2005; Rieger and Wang, Economic Theory 28:665–679, 2006) have to cope with limitations. In that framework, CPT fails to accommodate both gambling and insurance behavior. We suggest replacing the weighting functions generally proposed in the literature by another specification which respects the following properties: (1) to solve the paradox, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  19
    Consistency of determined risk attitudes and probability weightings across different elicitation methods.Golo-Friedrich Bauermeister, Daniel Hermann & Oliver Musshoff - 2018 - Theory and Decision 84 (4):627-644.
    In comparing different risk elicitation methods under the assumptions of expected utility theory, previous studies have found significant differences in the elicited risk attitudes. This paper extends this line of research to consider cumulative prospect theory by comparing risk attitudes and probability weightings determined using two elicitation methods: the method by Tanaka et al. :557–571, 2010; TCN method) and the method by Wakker and Deneffe :1131–1150, 1996; WD method). We demonstrate that the two methods reveal significantly different mean values (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  48
    Expectations, Disappointment, and Rank-Dependent Probability Weighting.Philippe Delquié & Alessandra Cillo - 2006 - Theory and Decision 60 (2-3):193-206.
    We develop a model of Disappointment in which disappointment and elation arise from comparing the outcome received, not with an expected value as in previous models, but rather with the other individual outcomes of the lottery. This approach may better reflect the way individuals are liable to experience disappointment. The model obtained accounts for classic behavioral deviations from the normative theory, offers a richer structure than previous disappointment models, and leads to a Rank-Dependent Utility formulation in a transparent way. Thus, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  8
    Numeracy moderates the influence of task-irrelevant affect on probability weighting.Jakub Traczyk & Kamil Fulawka - 2016 - Cognition 151 (C):37-41.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  25
    Uncertainty plus prior equals rational bias: An intuitive Bayesian probability weighting function.John Fennell & Roland Baddeley - 2012 - Psychological Review 119 (4):878-887.
  18.  14
    Probabilistic Inference: Task Dependency and Individual Differences of Probability Weighting Revealed by Hierarchical Bayesian Modeling.Moritz Boos, Caroline Seer, Florian Lange & Bruno Kopp - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  73
    Intergenerational impartiality: Replacing discounting by probability weighting[REVIEW]Yew-Kwang Ng - 2005 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 18 (3):237-257.
    Intergenerational impartiality requires putting the welfare of future generations at par with that of our own. However, rational choice requires weighting all welfare values by the respective probabilities of realization. As the risk of non-survival of mankind is strictly positive for all time periods and as the probability of non-survival is cumulative, the probability weights operate like discount factors, though justified on a morally justifiable and completely different ground. Impartial intertemporal welfare maximization is acceptable, though the welfare (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Imprecise Probability and the Measurement of Keynes's "Weight of Arguments".William Peden - 2018 - IfCoLog Journal of Logics and Their Applications 5 (4):677-708.
    Many philosophers argue that Keynes’s concept of the “weight of arguments” is an important aspect of argument appraisal. The weight of an argument is the quantity of relevant evidence cited in the premises. However, this dimension of argumentation does not have a received method for formalisation. Kyburg has suggested a measure of weight that uses the degree of imprecision in his system of “Evidential Probability” to quantify weight. I develop and defend this approach to measuring weight. I illustrate the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  10
    Probability learning of perceptual cues in the establishment of a weight illusion.Egon Brunswik & Hans Herma - 1951 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 41 (4):281.
  22.  31
    Weighted sets of probabilities and minimax weighted expected regret: a new approach for representing uncertainty and making decisions.Joseph Y. Halpern & Samantha Leung - 2015 - Theory and Decision 79 (3):415-450.
    We consider a setting where a decision maker’s uncertainty is represented by a set of probability measures, rather than a single measure. Measure-by-measure updating of such a set of measures upon acquiring new information is well known to suffer from problems. To deal with these problems, we propose using weighted sets of probabilities: a representation where each measure is associated with a weight, which denotes its significance. We describe a natural approach to updating in such a situation and a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  35
    Discussion. How to weight scientists' probabilities is not a big problem: Comment on Barnes.P. E. Meehl - 1999 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (2):283-295.
    Assuming it rational to treat other persons' probabilities as epistemically significant, how shall their judgements be weighted (Barnes [1998])? Several plausible methods exist, but theorems in classical psychometrics greatly reduce the importance of the problem. If scientists' judgements tend to be positively correlated, the difference between two randomly weighted composites shrinks as the number of judges rises. Since, for reasons such as representative coverage, minimizing bias, and avoiding elitism, we would rarely employ small numbers of judges (e.g. less than 10), (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  13
    A weighted probability model of coalition formation.S. S. Komorita - 1974 - Psychological Review 81 (3):242-256.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. The Weight of Reasons: A Framework for Ethics.Chris Tucker - forthcoming - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The book develops, defends, and applies an account of weighing reasons to resolve various issues in ethics. It tells you everything you ever wanted to know about weighing reasons and probably a lot of stuff you didn't want to know too. The excerpt provided here is the Table of Contents, the Introduction, and Chapter 1.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  44
    On probabilities and loss aversion.Horst Zank - 2010 - Theory and Decision 68 (3):243-261.
    This paper reviews the most common approaches that have been adopted to analyze and describe loss aversion under prospect theory. Subsequently, it is argued that loss aversion is a property of observable choice behavior and two new definitions of loss averse behavior are advocated. Under prospect theory, the new properties hold if the commonly used utility based measures of loss aversion are corrected by a probability based measure of loss aversion and their product exceeds 1. It is shown that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  13
    Optimal weighting for estimating generalized average treatment effects.Michele Santacatterina & Nathan Kallus - 2022 - Journal of Causal Inference 10 (1):123-140.
    In causal inference, a variety of causal effect estimands have been studied, including the sample, uncensored, target, conditional, optimal subpopulation, and optimal weighted average treatment effects. Ad hoc methods have been developed for each estimand based on inverse probability weighting and on outcome regression modeling, but these may be sensitive to model misspecification, practical violations of positivity, or both. The contribution of this article is twofold. First, we formulate the generalized average treatment effect to unify these causal estimands (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. A new defence of probability discounting.Kian Mintz-Woo - 2017 - In Adrian Walsh, Säde Hormio & Duncan Purves (eds.), The Ethical Underpinnings of Climate Economics. Oxford: Routledge. pp. 87-102.
    When probability discounting (or probability weighting), one multiplies the value of an outcome by one's subjective probability that the outcome will obtain in decision-making. The broader import of defending probability discounting is to help justify cost-benefit analyses in contexts such as climate change. This chapter defends probability discounting under risk both negatively, from arguments by Simon Caney (2008, 2009), and with a new positive argument. First, in responding to Caney, I argue that small costs (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29. Probability in Everettian Quantum Mechanics.Peter J. Lewis - 2010 - Manuscrito 33 (1):285--306.
    The main difficulty facing no-collapse theories of quantum mechanics in the Everettian tradition concerns the role of probability within a theory in which every possible outcome of a measurement actually occurs. The problem is two-fold: First, what do probability claims mean within such a theory? Second, what ensures that the probabilities attached to measurement outcomes match those of standard quantum mechanics? Deutsch has recently proposed a decision-theoretic solution to the second problem, according to which agents are rationally required (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  30.  31
    Weighted averaging, Jeffrey conditioning and invariance.Denis Bonnay & Mikaël Cozic - 2018 - Theory and Decision 85 (1):21-39.
    Jeffrey conditioning tells an agent how to update her priors so as to grant a given probability to a particular event. Weighted averaging tells an agent how to update her priors on the basis of testimonial evidence, by changing to a weighted arithmetic mean of her priors and another agent’s priors. We show that, in their respective settings, these two seemingly so different updating rules are axiomatized by essentially the same invariance condition. As a by-product, this sheds new light (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  6
    Modified Weights-of-Evidence Modeling with Example of Missing Geochemical Data.Daojun Zhang & Frits Agterberg - 2018 - Complexity 2018:1-12.
    Weights of evidence and logistic regression are two loglinear methods for mineral potential mapping. Both models are limited by their respective basic assumptions in application. Ideally, WofE indicator patterns have the property of conditional independence with respect to the point pattern of mineral deposits to be predicted; in LR, there supposedly are no interactions between the point pattern and two or more of the indicator patterns. If the CI assumption is satisfied, estimated LR coefficients become approximately equal to WofE contrasts (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Weight for Stephen Finlay.Daan Evers - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 163 (3):737-749.
    According to Stephen Finlay, ‘A ought to X’ means that X-ing is more conducive to contextually salient ends than relevant alternatives. This in turn is analysed in terms of probability. I show why this theory of ‘ought’ is hard to square with a theory of a reason’s weight which could explain why ‘A ought to X’ logically entails that the balance of reasons favours that A X-es. I develop two theories of weight to illustrate my point. I first look (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  27
    PROBabilities from EXemplars (PROBEX): a “lazy” algorithm for probabilistic inference from generic knowledge.Peter Juslin & Magnus Persson - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (5):563-607.
    PROBEX (PROBabilities from EXemplars), a model of probabilistic inference and probability judgment based on generic knowledge is presented. Its properties are that: (a) it provides an exemplar model satisfying bounded rationality; (b) it is a “lazy” algorithm that presumes no pre‐computed abstractions; (c) it implements a hybrid‐representation, similarity‐graded probability. We investigate the ecological rationality of PROBEX and find that it compares favorably with Take‐The‐Best and multiple regression (Gigerenzer, Todd, & the ABC Research Group, 1999). PROBEX is fitted to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  34. Probability and Certainty.Jonny Blamey - 2008 - Praxis 1 (1).
    Probability can be used to measure degree of belief in two ways: objectively and subjectively. The objective measure is a measure of the rational degree of belief in a proposition given a set of evidential propositions. The subjective measure is the measure of a particular subject’s dispositions to decide between options. In both measures, certainty is a degree of belief 1. I will show, however, that there can be cases where one belief is stronger than another yet both beliefs (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  87
    The weights of evidence.Dale A. Nance - 2008 - Episteme 5 (3):pp. 267-281.
    Interest in the Keynesian concept of evidential weight has led to divergent views concerning the burden of proof in adjudication. It is argued that Keynes's concept is properly engaged only in the context of one special kind of decision, the decision whether or not the evidence is ripe for a decision on the underlying merits, whether the latter decision is based on probability, relative plausibility, coherence or otherwise. As a general matter, this question of ripeness is appropriately assigned to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  38
    The weight of rhetoric: Studies in cultural delirium.Thomas B. Farrell - 2008 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 41 (4):pp. 467-487.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Weight of Rhetoric: Studies in Cultural DeliriumThomas B. FarrellThere is something of this anachronistic doggedness in all importance, and to use it as a criterion of thought is to impose on thought a spellbound fixity, and a loss of self-reflection. The great themes are nothing other than primeval rumblings which cause the animal to pause and try to bring them forth once again. This does not mean that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  72
    Inferring Probability Comparisons.Matthew Harrison-Trainor, Wesley H. Holliday & Thomas Icard - 2018 - Mathematical Social Sciences 91:62-70.
    The problem of inferring probability comparisons between events from an initial set of comparisons arises in several contexts, ranging from decision theory to artificial intelligence to formal semantics. In this paper, we treat the problem as follows: beginning with a binary relation ≥ on events that does not preclude a probabilistic interpretation, in the sense that ≥ has extensions that are probabilistically representable, we characterize the extension ≥+ of ≥ that is exactly the intersection of all probabilistically representable extensions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  18
    Weight in discretionary decision-making.D. Herling - 1999 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 19 (4):583-604.
    House of Lords authority in Tesco v Secretary of State for the Environment [1995] 1 WLR 759 has reinforced the well-established principle that judicial review will distinguish between relevant and irrelevant considerations pertaining to the exercise of a power, and leave the weighing of the relevant ones to the decision-maker. It has also problematized the principle by insisting that relevant factors may adequately be taken into account even where the decision-maker allows them no influence (subject to challenge for irrationality). It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  10
    The Weight I Just Can’t Lose.Shelley Lynn Meyers - 2014 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 4 (2):4-6.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Weight I Just Can’t LoseShelley Lynn MeyersI have always been a “fat person”. According to the medical definition though, I have not always been obese. I have spent most of my life on a journey from chubby to obese, finally ending at my current “overweight” status. After years of struggling with obesity I had gastric bypass surgery, finally losing enough weight to be “normal.” However, regardless of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. The structure of epistemic probabilities.Nevin Climenhaga - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 177 (11):3213-3242.
    The epistemic probability of A given B is the degree to which B evidentially supports A, or makes A plausible. This paper is a first step in answering the question of what determines the values of epistemic probabilities. I break this question into two parts: the structural question and the substantive question. Just as an object’s weight is determined by its mass and gravitational acceleration, some probabilities are determined by other, more basic ones. The structural question asks what probabilities (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  41. The balance and weight of reasons.Nicholas Makins - 2023 - Theoria 89 (5):592-606.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a detailed characterisation of some ways in which our preferences reflect our reasons. I will argue that practical reasons can be characterised along two dimensions that influence our preferences: their balance and their weight. This is analogous to a similar characterisation of the way in which probabilities reflect the balance and weight of evidence in epistemology. In this paper, I will illustrate the distinction between the balance and weight of reasons, and show (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  5
    Multisensor-Weighted Fusion Algorithm Based on Improved AHP for Aircraft Fire Detection.Rui Wang, Yahui Li, Hui Sun & Kaixin Yang - 2021 - Complexity 2021:1-10.
    Aiming at the high false alarm rate when using single sensor to detect fire in aircraft cabin, a multisensor data fusion method is proposed to detect fire. First, the weights of multiple factors, that is, temperature, smoke concentration, CO concentration, and infrared ray intensity in the event of fire, were calculated by using the improved analytic hierarchy process method on each sensor node of wireless sensor network, and the probability of fire event in the cabin was evaluated by multivariable-weighted (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  89
    Predictive Probability and Analogy by Similarity in Inductive Logic.Maria Concetta Di Maio - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (3):369 - 394.
    The λ-continuum of inductive methods was derived from an assumption, called λ-condition, which says that the probability of finding an individual having property $x_{j}$ depends only on the number of observed individuals having property $x_{j}$ and on the total number of observed individuals. So, according to that assumption, all individuals with properties which are different from $x_{j}$ have equal weight with respect to that probability and, in particular, it does not matter whether any individual was observed having some (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44. Calibrated probabilities and the epistemology of disagreement.Barry Lam - 2013 - Synthese 190 (6):1079-1098.
    This paper assesses the comparative reliability of two belief-revision rules relevant to the epistemology of disagreement, the Equal Weight and Stay the Course rules. I use two measures of reliability for probabilistic belief-revision rules, calibration and Brier Scoring, to give a precise account of epistemic peerhood and epistemic reliability. On the calibration measure of reliability, epistemic peerhood is easy to come by, and employing the Equal Weight rule generally renders you less reliable than Staying the Course. On the Brier-Score measure (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45.  84
    Probability and determinism.Jan Von Plato - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):51-66.
    This paper discusses different interpretations of probability in relation to determinism. It is argued that both objective and subjective views on probability can be compatible with deterministic as well as indeterministic situations. The possibility of a conceptual independence between probability and determinism is argued to hold on a general level. The subsequent philosophical analysis of recent advances in classical statistical mechanics (ergodic theory) is of independent interest, but also adds weight to the claim that it is possible (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  46.  20
    Probability and Determinism.Jan Platvono - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):51-.
    This paper discusses different interpretations of probability in relation to determinism. It is argued that both objective and subjective views on probability can be compatible with deterministic as well as indeterministic situations. The possibility of a conceptual independence between probability and determinism is argued to hold on a general level. The subsequent philosophical analysis of recent advances in classical statistical mechanics is of independent interest, but also adds weight to the claim that it is possible to justify (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  47. The Weight of Tradition in the Formation of the Name Signs of the Deaf in China.Yau Shun-Chiu - 1996 - Diogenes 44 (175):55-65.
    The Chinese are probably the most particular people in the world when it comes to their names. As the Chinese proverb says, “worse than being born under a bad star is to receive a bad name.” For this reason it is difficult, if not impossible, to evaluate the role of name signs in China without a certain knowledge of the Chinese tradition regarding the attribution of names. A legal Chinese name is made up of a family name, monosyllabic with some (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  61
    Probability Dynamics.Amos Nathan - 2006 - Synthese 148 (1):229-256.
    Probability dynamics’ (PD) is a second-order probabilistic theory in which probability distribution d X = (P(X 1), . . . , P(X m )) on partition U m X of sample space Ω is weighted by ‘credence’ (c) ranging from −∞ to +∞. c is the relative degree of certainty of d X in ‘α-evidence’ α X =[c; d X ] on U m X . It is shown that higher-order probabilities cannot provide a theory of PD. PD (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  63
    Keynesian Uncertainty and the Weight of Arguments.Jochen Runde - 1990 - Economics and Philosophy 6 (2):275.
    In Chapter 12 of the General Theory, on “The State of Long-Term Expectation,” Keynes writes: “It would be foolish, in forming our expectations, to attach great weight to matters which are very uncertain”. In a footnote to this sentence, Keynes points out that by “very uncertain” he does not mean the same as “very improbable” and refers to the chapter on “The Weight of Arguments” in his earlier Treatise on Probability. The purpose of this article, in the first place, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  50.  71
    Rationality as weighted averaging.Keith Lehrer - 1983 - Synthese 57 (3):283 - 295.
    Weighted averaging is a method for aggregating the totality of information, both regimented and unregimented, possessed by an individual or group of individuals. The application of such a method may be warranted by a theorem of the calculus of probability, simple conditionalization, or Jeffrey's formula for probability kinematics, all of which average in terms of the prior probability of evidence statements. Weighted averaging may, however, be applied as a method of rational aggregation of the probabilities of diverse (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 988