Results for ' HISTORICAL INTENTIONALISM'

990 found
Order:
  1. Historical interpretation, intentionalism and philosophy of mind.Vivienne Brown - 2007 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 1 (1):25-62.
    Historiographic debates keep returning to issues of authorial intention in the interpretation of texts. This paper offers a response to these debates by differentiating between two versions of intentionalism, termed 'substantive intentionalism' and 'formal intentionalism', according to two different senses of 'identity' in the thesis that assigned meaning is identified with authorial intention, such that these two versions of intentionalism imply different ontological commitments to what are construed as the relevant authorial intentions. These distinctions and arguments (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2. Intentionalism, Intentional Realism, and Empathy.Karsten Stueber - 2009 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 3 (3):290-307.
    Contemporary philosophers of history and interpretation theorists very often deny the thesis of intentional realism, because they reject intentionalism or the thesis that an agent's or author's intentions are relevant for the interpretive practice of the human sciences. I will defend intentional realism by showing why it is wrong to whole-heartedly reject intentionalism and by clarifying the logical relation between intentionalism and intentional realism. I will do so by discussing the two central arguments against intentionalism; the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  23
    Weak Intentionalism and the Death of the Subject.Robin Dunford - 2011 - Intellectual History Review 21 (1):43-56.
    Does Bevir's weak intentionalism clash irredeemably with the rejection of conceptions of subjectivity in the work of Deleuze and the later Foucault? The paper examines the notion of the subject required by Bevir's weak intentionalism, before turning to the "rejection" of the subject found in the work of Deleuze and the later Foucault, suggesting that this rejection only rejects the subject as something fully autonomous and given in advance, and does not constitute a global rejection of any subject (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  49
    Intentionalism, intentionality, and reporting beliefs.Branko Mitrović - 2009 - History and Theory 48 (3):180-198.
    The dominant view of twentieth century analytic philosophy has been that all thinking is always in a language; that languages are vehicles of thought. In recent decades, however, the opposite view, that languages merely serve to express language-­‐independent thought-­‐contents or propositions, has been more widely accepted. The debate has a direct equivalent in the philosophy of history: when historians report the beliefs of historical figures, do they report the sentences or propositions that these historical figures believed to be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  59
    How to be an intentionalist.Mark Bevir - 2002 - History and Theory 41 (2):209–217.
    The general aim of this paper is to establish the plausibility of a postfoundational intentionalism. Its specific aim is to respond to criticisms of my work made by Vivienne Brown in a paper "On Some Problems with Weak Intentionalism for Intellectual History." Postfoundationalism is often associated with a new textualism according to which there is no outside to the text. In contrast, I suggest that postfoundationalists can legitimate our postulating intentions, actions, and other historical objects outside of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  45
    On some problems with weak intentionalism for intellectual history.Vivienne Brown - 2002 - History and Theory 41 (2):198–208.
    This paper argues that the notion of weak intentionalism in Mark Bevir's The Logic of the History of Ideas is incoherent. Bevir's proposal for weak intentionalism as procedural individualism relies on the argument that the object of study for historians of ideas is given by the beliefs that are expressed by individuals since these beliefs constitute the historical meaning of the work for those individuals as historical figures. Historical meanings are thus hermeneutic meanings. In the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  32
    Real realism: The galilean strategy, Philip Kitcher.Intentionalism Defended - 2001 - Philosophy 76 (2).
  8.  23
    2 the limits of the medical model: Historical epidemiology of intellectual disability in the united states Jeffrey P. Brosco.Historical Epidemiology Of Intellectual - 2010 - In Eva Feder Kittay & Licia Carlson (eds.), Cognitive Disability and its Challenge to Moral Philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  43
    Reception Theory and the Interpretation of Historical Meaning.Martyn P. Thompson - 1993 - History and Theory 32 (3):248-272.
    The paper examines the very different insights of theorists into the interpretation of historical meaning of literary reception and Anglo-American theorists of the "new" history of political thought . Among the former, readers create meaning; among the latter, authorial intended meanings are fundamental. Both perspectives are valuable, but one-sided. The differences between them arise from different perspectives on the character of a text. But those perspectives are not as incompatible as has been supposed, especially by reception theorists. By examining (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. Michel Dion.Historical Change According To Milan - 2009 - In Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka (ed.), Existence, historical fabulation, destiny. Springer Verlag. pp. 77.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. pp. x+ 82, S6. 00 paper (210.50 hardback).Historical Explanation Reconsidered - 1985 - Philosophical Investigations 8 (1).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  6
    Kenneth W. Stikkers.Constructivism In Historical - 2009 - In Larry A. Hickman, Stefan Neubert & Kersten Reich (eds.), John Dewey between pragmatism and constructivism. New York: Fordham University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Laura J. Snyder.is Evidence Historical - 1994 - In Peter Achinstein & Laura J. Snyder (eds.), Scientific Methods: Conceptual and Historical Problems. Krieger Pub. Co..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  11
    Richard G. Ely.Mandelbaum On Historical - 2001 - In Geoffrey Roberts (ed.), The History and Narrative Reader. Routledge.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  2
    The Under-Development of 'Business Ethics'.An Historical - 1997 - Ethical Perspectives 4 (2):105.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Symposium: On David Harvey's “The New Imperialism”.Historical Materialism - 2006 - Historical Materialism 14 (4):3-166.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Human, all too human.Historical Versus - 2005 - In Keith Ansell-Pearson (ed.), How to Read Nietzsche. Norton.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Emplotment and the problem of truth.Historical White - 2001 - In Geoffrey Roberts (ed.), The History and Narrative Reader. Routledge. pp. 375--389.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The agenda for religion/science: Guest editorials K. Helmut Reich what needs to be done in order to bring the science-and-religion dialogue forward? Whose broad experience? How great the audience? From grand dreaming to problem solving.Three Historical Probes & Nicola Hoggard Creegan - forthcoming - Zygon.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. 27. Co-creation with all and for all—of all that is most important. Note. Part VI will be published in one of the forthcoming issues. [REVIEW]Co-Creating Historical & Non-Adjectival Universalism - forthcoming - Dialogue and Universalism.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Impulsive Impressions.Thomas Blacksoncorresponding Author School of Historical Philosophical - 2017 - Rhizomata 5 (1).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  6
    Authors and Editors.Western Historical Thinking - 2010 - In Richard Corrigan (ed.), Ethics: A University Guide. Progressive Frontiers Pubs..
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. the Meaning of Nationalism'.Llyod Kramer & Historical Narrative - 1997 - Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (1):529.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Jill Lepore “Just the Facts, Ma'am,” March 24, 2008. A history of history and fiction.Elizabeth Barnes, W. B. Berthoff, Charles Brockden Brown’S. Historical‘Sketches & Leo Braudy - 1985 - Journal of the History of Ideas 46:405-416.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  4
    Mind and Body in 18th Century Medicine: A Study Based on Jerome Gaub's De Regimine Mentis.L. J. Rather & Wellcome Historical Medical Museum and Library - 1965 - Univ of California Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Sailing the Seas of Cheese.Erik Anderson - 2010 - Contemporary Aesthetics 8.
    Memphis Elvis is cool; Vegas Elvis is cheesy. How come? To call something cheesy is, ostensibly, to disparage it, and yet cheesy acts are some of the most popular in popular culture today. How is this possible? The concepts of cheese, cheesy, and cheesiness play an important and increasingly ubiquitous role in popular culture today. I offer an analysis of these concepts, distinguishing them from nearby concepts like kitchy and campy. Along the way I draw attention to the important roles (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. Max Scheler, Cousin of Disjunctivism.Mattia Riccardi - 2016 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15 (3):443-454.
    Disjunctivism has triggered an intense discussion about the nature of perceptual experience. A question in its own right concerns possible historical antecedents of the position. So far, Frege and Husserl are the most prominent names that have been mentioned in this regard. In my paper I shall argue that Max Scheler deserves a particularly relevant place in the genealogy of disjunctivism for three main reasons. First, Scheler’s view of perceptual experience is distinctively disjunctivist, as he explicitly argues that perceptions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  5
    Agency and transformation: motives, mediation and motion.Nick Hopwood & Annalisa Sannino (eds.) - 2023 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Researchers need the concept of agency to address diverse and urgent social problems of our time. Cultural-historical activity theory, originally started with Vygotsky, is widely used in education, psychology, sociology, and transdisciplinary contexts. Scholars and students in diverse disciplines will benefit from this volume.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  38
    Perspectives on activity theory.Yrjö Engeström, Reijo Miettinen & Raija-Leena Punamäki-Gitai (eds.) - 1999 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Activity theory is an interdisciplinary approach to human sciences that originates in the cultural-historical psychology school, initiated by Vygotsky, Leont'ev, and Luria. It takes the object-oriented, artifact-mediated collective activity system as its unit of analysis, thus bridging the gulf between the individual subject and the societal structure. This volume is the first comprehensive presentation of contemporary work in activity theory, with 26 original chapters by authors from ten countries. In Part I of the book, central theoretical issues are discussed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  30. Commonsense Faculty Psychology: Reidian Foundations for Computational Cognitive Science.John-Christian Smith - 1985 - Dissertation, The University of Arizona
    This work locates the historical and conceptual foundations of cognitive science in the "commonsense" psychology of the philosopher Thomas Reid. I begin with Reid's attack on his rationalist and empiricist competitors of the 17th and 18th centuries. I then present his positive theory as a sophisticated faculty psychology appealing to innateness of mental structure. Reidian psychological faculties are equally trustworthy, causally independent mental powers, and I argue that they share nine distinct properties. This distinguishes Reidian 'intentionalism' from idealist (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  3
    Perception.Barry Maund - 2003 - Chesham, Bucks: Routledge.
    The philosophical issues raised by perception make it one of the central topics in the philosophical tradition. Debate about the nature of perceptual knowledge and the objects of perception comprises a thread that runs through the history of philosophy. In some historical periods the major issues have been predominantly epistemological and related to scepticism, but an adequate understanding of perception is important more widely, especially for metaphysics and the philosophy of mind. For this reason Barry Maund provides an account (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  32.  61
    Irony, metaphor, and the problem of intention.Daniel Nathan - 1992 - In Gary Iseminger (ed.), Intention and Interpretation. Temple University Press. pp. 183--202.
    This essay considers the reliability and proper role of authorial intention in the interpretation of figurative language and argues that, even in cases of metaphor and irony, the meaning of a text must remain logically independent of the intent of its historical author. Irony and metaphor have been broadly considered to be the most problematic cases for the anti-intentionalist approach to interpretation. The arguments in this essay address standard intentionalist arguments and, in the end, defend a sort of hypothetical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  33. Зарождение дискуссии об авторской интенции в американской критике и философии.Александр Юдин - 2015 - Sententiae 32 (1):60-71.
    The article deals with the origin and formation of debating positions in American criticism and philosophy. It analyzes “Intentional Fallacy” by W. Wimsatt and M. Beardsley. as well as E.D. Hirsch’s texts concerning the idea of objective interpretation which initiated this discussion. In fact, both positions are limited because of their normative and ahistorical character. Both sides try to regulate interpretation. Wimsatt and Beardsley lose the historical place of a text, whereas Hirsch reduces the historical place of an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  19
    Intrinsic Moral Evils in the Middle Ages: Augustine as a Source of the Theological Doctrine.Matthew R. McWhorter - 2016 - Studies in Christian Ethics 29 (4):409-423.
    Contemporary historians examining moral theology in the Middle Ages question whether the practice of proscribing certain kinds of human acts as intrinsic moral evils has a legitimate basis in the Christian ethical tradition. John Dedek argues that this proscription does not fully emerge until the work of the fourteenth-century thinker Durandus of St. Pourçain. Dedek’s historical focus, however, is upon theological discussions which consider God’s absolute power and his ability to dispense from or command any human act whatsoever. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  22
    Is There A Language-game That Even the Deconstructionist Can Play?Steven Fuller - 1985 - Philosophy and Literature 9 (1):104-109.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:IS THERE A LANGUAGE-GAME THAT EVEN THE DECONSTRUCTIONIST CAN PLAY? by Steven Fuller After reading A. J. Cascardi's fascinating "Skepticism and Deconstruction," I am led to ask the question that "entitles" this response.1 The answer I want to give is "yes," but Cascardi has made the task more difficult than I would have liked. In brief, he has dissociated deconstruction from all philosophical pursuits, including skepticism, which it superficially (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  9
    Derrida At Yale: The "Deconstructive Moment" in Modernist Poetics.Christopher Norris - 1980 - Philosophy and Literature 4 (2):242-256.
    Christopher Norris DERRIDA AT YALE: THE "DECONSTRUCTIVE MOMENT" IN MODERNIST POETICS IN seven types of ambiguity, William Empson breezily remarked of his critical method that it was "either all nonsense or all very startling and new." The reactions went very much as Empson predicted, with a whole new school of criticism eagerly latching on to the idea of multiple meanings in poetry, while the sober-sided scholars indignantly attacked his wayward "misreadings" and flagrant anachronisms. At present, there is a similar controversy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  68
    Vagueness, counterfactual intentions, and legal interpretation.Natalie Stoljar - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (4):447-465.
    "My argument is as follows. In the first section, I sketch briefly the ways in which intentionalism might provide a solution to the problem of vagueness. The second section describes the different areas in which counterfactuals must be invoked by intentionalism. In the third section I point out that on a classic analysis of counterfactuals - that of David Lewis and Robert Stalnaker - the truth conditions of counterfactuals depend on relations of similarity among possible worlds. Since similarity (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38.  84
    Composers and Performers.Junyeol Kim - 2020 - Philosophia 48 (4):1469-1481.
    We take performers of classical music as producers of creative performances. We sometimes criticize a performer’s performance by saying ‘That is not what the composer wants’. The literature takes this kind of criticism, which I call ‘intentionalist criticism’, to be in tension with performers’ creativity—taking the criticism to be an attempt to restrict performers’ creativity by historical authenticity. This paper aims to construct a possible understanding of intentionalist criticisms according to which those criticisms are grounded in our respect of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. La teoria critica ha bisogno di un'ontologia sociale (e viceversa)?Italo Testa - 2016 - Politica E Società 1:47-72.
    In this article I argue that contemporary critical theory needs the conceptual tools of social ontology in order to make its own ontological commitments explicit and strengthen its interdisciplinary approach. On the other hand, contemporary analytic social ontology needs critical theory in order to be able to focus on the role that social change, power, and historicity play in the constitution of social facts, and to see the shortcomings of an agential and intentionalist approach to social facts. My thesis is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Die Fallstricke einer intentionalistischen Engführung der Geschichtsdeutung.Eckhart Arnold - 2015 - Erwã¤Gen Wissen Ethik 26:60-65.
    In this commentary I criticise Doris Gerber's intentionalistic reading of history. While an intentionalistic philosophy of history has some plausibility, a *purely* intentionalistic view is often irreconcilable with the most elementary common sense. For example, that history ought to be considered exclusively as the history of human action and not of things that simply happen to humans as well - like the outbreak of the volcano Vesuv in the year 79 which lead to the destructions of Pompeii. Or that (...) value judgments should always be judgments about the reasons for human action, which raises the questions if and how the unintended consequences of human action are to be judged. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  5
    Sailing the Seas of Cheese.Erik Anderson - 2023 - In Max Ryynänen & Paco Barragán (eds.), The Changing Meaning of Kitsch: From Rejection to Acceptance. Palgrave / MacMillan (Springer Verlag). pp. 87-117.
    Memphis Elvis is cool; Vegas Elvis is cheesy. How come? To call something cheesy is, ostensibly, to disparage it, and yet cheesy acts are some of the most popular in popular culture today. How is this possible? The concepts of cheese, cheesy, and cheesiness play an important and increasingly ubiquitous role in popular culture today. I offer an analysis of these concepts, distinguishing them from nearby concepts like kitschy and campy. Along the way I draw attention to the important roles (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  26
    Rationalism in History.Steven Galt Crowell - 2003 - Diacritics 33 (1):3-22.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Diacritics 33.1 (2003) 3-22 [Access article in PDF] Rationalism in History Steven Crowell Mark Bevir. The Logic of the History of Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1999. [L] When Hegel spoke of history as the "slaughter-bench at which the happiness of peoples, the wisdom of states, and the virtue of individuals have been sacrificed" [27], he wished his hearers to find satisfaction in the contemplation of a "reason" in history (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  54
    Artist-Audience Communication: Tolstoy Reclaimed.Saam Trivedi - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (2):38.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Journal of Aesthetic Education 38.2 (2004) 38-52 [Access article in PDF] Artist-Audience Communication: Tolstoy Reclaimed Saam Trivedi Whoever is really conversant with art recognizes in [Tolstoy's What is Art?] the voice of the master.1There has to be some presumption that, as one of the greatest artists who ever lived, Tolstoy might actually have known what he was talking about.2It is widely accepted in contemporary Anglo-American aesthetics that, despite (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Art and pornography.Hans Maes - 2009 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 43 (3):pp. 107-116.
    This paper provides an in-depth review of Jerrold Levinson’s most recent work in aesthetics, focusing especially on his account of the incompatibility of art and pornography. The author argues that this account does not fit well with Levinson’s own intentional-historical definition of art and his Wollheimian account of depiction.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  13
    Logic, Language and Legitimation in the History of Ideas: A Brief View and Survey of Bevir and Skinner.Timothy Stanton - 2011 - Intellectual History Review 21 (1):71-84.
    Bevir's doctrine of ?weak intentionalism?, developed in the course of his criticism of the work of Quentin Skinner, at once modifies and qualifies Skinner's approach by specifying the beliefs of individuals rather than their utterances as the loci of their intentions and the things that fix the meaning of their utterances. This has the effect of broadening the scope of meaning, by disengaging the meaning of utterances from their status as speech acts, of narrowing the relevance of linguistic contexts, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  34
    A pragmatic critique of pluralism in text interpretation.Pol Vandevelde - 2005 - Metaphilosophy 36 (4):501-521.
    I take a pragmatic approach to what interpreters do when they interpret and argue that critical pluralists have focused almost exclusively on one aspect of interpretation: the fact that it is an event taking place in a historical and cultural milieu that influences the many ways interpreters approach a given text. However, there is also in interpretation a pragmatic aspect: the fact that it is an act performed by individuals who, through the utterance of their statements, implicitly make claims, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  2
    Emotion and Object.John R. S. Wilson - 1972 - Cambridge,: Cambridge University Press.
    A study in the philosophy of mind, centred on the problem of 'intentionality' the sense in which emotions can be said to have objects, their relation to these objects, and the implications of this relation for our understanding of human action and behaviour. Dr Wilson sets his enquiry against a broad historical background on what distinguishes man from inanimate objects by describing both Cartesian view of man is matter plus mind and the neo-Wittgensteinian view that there is a dynamic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Pure Intentionalism About Moods and Emotions.Angela Mendelovici - 2013 - In Uriah Kriegel (ed.), Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. Routledge. pp. 135-157.
    Moods and emotions are sometimes thought to be counterexamples to intentionalism, the view that a mental state's phenomenal features are exhausted by its representational features. The problem is that moods and emotions are accompanied by phenomenal experiences that do not seem to be adequately accounted for by any of their plausibly represented contents. This paper develops and defends an intentionalist view of the phenomenal character of moods and emotions on which emotions and some moods represent intentional objects as having (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  49. Intentionalism and pain.D. T. Bain - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (213):502-523.
    Pain may appear to undermine the radically intentionalist view that the phenomenal character of any experience is entirely constituted by its representational content. That appearance is illusory. After categorizing versions of pain intentionalism along two dimensions, I argue that an 'objectivist' and 'non-mentalist' version is the most promising, if it can withstand two objections concerning what we say when in pain, and the distinctiveness of pain. I rebut these objections, in a way available to both opponents of and adherents (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  50. Literary Intentionalism.Robbie Kubala - 2019 - Metaphilosophy 50 (4):503-515.
    In the philosophical debate about literary interpretation, the actual intentionalist claims, and the anti-intentionalist denies, that an acceptable interpretation of fictional literature must be constrained by the author’s intentions. I argue that a close examination of the two most influential recent strands in this debate reveals a surprising convergence. Insofar as both sides (a) focus on literary works as they are, where work identity is determined in part by certain (successfully realized) categorial intentions concerning, e.g., title, genre, and large-scale instances (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 990