Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Teleology without regrets. The transformation of physiology in Germany: 1790–1847.Timothy Lenoir - 1981 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 12 (4):293-354.
  • C.F. Wolff on Variability and Heredity.A. E. Gaissinovitch - 1990 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 12 (2):179 - 201.
    Based on his published works and on manuscripts that were unpublished during his lifetime, C. F. Wolff's views on variability and heredity are analyzed. Attention is focused on his treatise Objecta meditationum pro theoria monstrorum published in 1973. The findings do not completely coincide with B. E. Rajkov's conclusions as to Wolff's anticipation of some theses of modern genetics and the theory of evolution. In addition, the case for the transformism elements in Wolff's work is argued. Lastly, Wolff's misunderstanding of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • ‘This inscrutable principle of an original organization’: epigenesis and ‘looseness of fit’ in Kant’s philosophy of science.John H. Zammito - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):73-109.
    Kant’s philosophy of science takes on sharp contour in terms of his interaction with the practicing life scientists of his day, particularly Johann Blumenbach and the latter’s student, Christoph Girtanner, who in 1796 attempted to synthesize the ideas of Kant and Blumenbach. Indeed, Kant’s engagement with the life sciences played a far more substantial role in his transcendental philosophy than has been recognized hitherto. The theory of epigenesis, especially in light of Kant’s famous analogy in the first Critique, posed crucial (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The epigenesis of pure reason. A note on the critique of pure reason, b, sec. 27,165—168.J. Wubnig - 1969 - Kant Studien 60 (2):147-152.
  • „naturmechanismus" Und „naturzweck": Bemerkungen zu Kants Organismus-Begriff.Camilla Warnke - 1992 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 40 (1-2):42-52.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The system of transcendental idealism: Questions raised and left open in the kritik der urteilskraft.Burkhard Tuschling - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (S1):109-127.
  • Buffon, German Biology, and the Historical Interpretation of Biological Species.Phillip R. Sloan - 1979 - British Journal for the History of Science 12 (2):109-153.
    The entry of time and history into biological systems of classification is perhaps the single most significant development in the history of biological systematics in the modern era. Darwin's claiming that descent is ‘… the hidden bond of connexion which naturalists have been seeking under the term of the natural system’, rather than seeing the answer in the multitude of previous attempts to resolve the problem in terms of morphological affinities, analogies, and complex relations of resemblance, marked the turning point (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Rationalism and embryology: Caspar Friedrich Wolff's theory of epigenesis.Shirley A. Roe - 1979 - Journal of the History of Biology 12 (1):1-43.
  • Historizismus und Kritizismus. Kants Streit mit G. Forster und J. G. Herder.Manfred Riedel - 1981 - Kant Studien 72 (1-4):41-57.
  • Kant and Blumenbach on the Bildungstrieb: A Historical Misunderstanding.Robert J. Richards - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 31 (1):11-32.
  • Kant on the history of nature: The ambiguous heritage of the critical philosophy for natural history.Phillip R. Sloan - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):627-648.
    This paper seeks to show Kant’s importance for the formal distinction between descriptive natural history and a developmental history of nature that entered natural history discussions in the late eighteenth century. It is argued that he developed this distinction initially upon Buffon’s distinctions of ‘abstract’ and ‘physical’ truths, and applied these initially in his distinction of ‘varieties’ from ‘races’ in anthropology. In the 1770s, Kant appears to have given theoretical preference to the ‘history’ of nature [Naturgeschichte] over ‘description’ of nature (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Kant's Philosophy of Science.Philip Kitcher - 1983 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 8 (1):387-407.
    This paper attempts to understand kant's obscure remarks that certain parts of natural science are a priori or have something akin to an a priori status. i argue that kant does not claim that propositions of physics are fully a priori, that the notion of a proposition's being a priori "given an empirical concept" can be explicated, that kant's attempted defense of the status of parts of dynamics is deeply flawed because of his commitments about a priority, but that his (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Kant on biological teleology: Towards a two-level interpretation.Marcel Quarfood - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):735-747.
    Kant stresses the regulative status of teleological attributions, but sometimes he seems to treat teleology as a constitutive condition for biology. To clarify this issue, the concept of natural purpose and its role for biology are examined. I suggest that the concept serves an identificatory function: it singles out objects as natural purposes, whereby the special science of biology is constituted. This relative constitutivity of teleology is explicated by means of a distinction of levels: on the object level of biological (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Methodological Rules in Kant’s Philosophy of Science.Margaret Morrison - 1989 - Kant Studien 80 (1-4):155-172.
  • Kant, Blumenbach, and Vital Materialism in German Biology.Timothy Lenoir - 1980 - Isis 71:77-108.
  • Generational Factors in the Origin of "Romantische Naturphilosophie".Timothy Lenoir - 1978 - Journal of the History of Biology 11 (1):57 - 100.
  • Vital Forces: Regulative Principles or Constitutive Agents? A Strategy in German Physiology, 1786-1802.James L. Larson - 1979 - Isis 70:235-249.
  • Kant, teleology, and evolution.Daniel Kolb - 1992 - Synthese 91 (1-2):9 - 28.
    This essay examines Kant's idea of organic teleology. The first two sections are devoted to Kant's analysis and justification of teleological conceptions in biology. Both the idea of teleology and Kant's anti-reductionism are derived from basic elements of his critical treatment of the human intellect. The third section discusses the limitations Kant places on accounts of origins in the life world. It is argued that the limitations Kant places on accounts of the origins of species do not follow from his (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Teleology then and now: The question of Kant's relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology.John Zammito - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):748-770.
    Kant -- drawing on his eighteenth-century predecessors -- provided a discerning and powerful characterization of what biologists had to explain in organic form. His difference from the rest is that he opined that was impossible to explain it. Its ’inscrutability’ was intrinsic. The third ’Critique’ essentially proposed the reduction of biology to a kind of prescientific descriptivism, doomed never to attain authentic scientificity. By contrast, for Locke, and ’a fortiori’ for Buffon and his followers, ’intrinsic purposiveness’ was a fact of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Kant's concept of natural purpose and the reflecting power of judgement.Joan Steigerwald - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):712-734.
    This paper examines how in the ‘Critique of teleological judgment’ Kant characterized the concept of natural purpose in relation to and in distinction from the concepts of nature and the concept of purpose he had developed in his other critical writings. Kant maintained that neither the principles of mechanical science nor the pure concepts of the understanding through which we determine experience in general provide adequate conceptualizations of the unique capacities of organisms. He also held that although the concept of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Naturalising purpose: From comparative anatomy to the 'adventure of reason'.Philippe Huneman - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (4):649-674.
    Kant’s analysis of the concept of natural purpose in the Critique of judgment captured several features of organisms that he argued warranted making them the objects of a special field of study, in need of a special regulative teleological principle. By showing that organisms have to be conceived as self-organizing wholes, epigenetically built according to the idea of a whole that we must presuppose, Kant accounted for three features of organisms conflated in the biological sciences of the period: adaptation, functionality (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • From the critique of judgment to the hermeneutics of nature: Sketching the fate of philosophy of nature after Kant. [REVIEW]Philippe Huneman - 2006 - Continental Philosophy Review 39 (1):1-34.
    This paper proposes an interpretative framework for some developments of the philosophy of nature after Kant. I emphasize the critique of the economy of nature in the Critique of judgement. I argue that it resulted in a split of a previous structure of knowledge; such a structure articulated natural theology and natural philosophy on the basis of the consideration of the order displayed by living beings, both in their internal organisation and their ecological distribution. The possibility of a philosophical discourse (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • From enlightenment to Naturphilosophie: Marcus Herz, Johann Christian Reil, and the problem of border crossings.Leeann Hansen - 1993 - Journal of the History of Biology 26 (1):39-64.
  • Two kinds of mechanical inexplicability in Kant and Aristotle.Hannah Ginsborg - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (1):33-65.
    I distinguish two senses in which organisms are mechanically inexplicable for Kant. Mechanical inexplicability in the first sense is shared with artefacts, and consists in their exhibiting regularities irreducible to the regularities of matter. Mechanical inexplicability in the second sense is peculiar to organisms, consisting in the reciprocal causal dependence of an organism's parts. This distinction corresponds to two strands of thought in Aristotle, one supporting a teleological conception of organisms, the other supporting a conception of organisms as natural. Recognizing (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Kant’s Epigenesis of Pure Reason.A. C. Genova - 1974 - Kant Studien 65 (1-4):259-273.
  • Is there "a gap" in Kant's critical system?Eckart Förster - 1987 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (4):533-555.
  • Regulative and constitutive.Michael Friedman - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (S1):73-102.
  • Explaining the inexplicable. The hypotheses of the faculty of reflective judgement in Kant's third critique.Christel Fricke - 1990 - Noûs 24 (1):45-62.
  • Limits of the Recapitulation Theory: Carl Friedrich Kielmeyer's Critique of the Presumed Parallelism of Earth History, Ontogeny, and the Present Order of Organisms.William Coleman - 1973 - Isis 64:341-350.
  • Teleology and scientific method in Kant's critique of judgment.Robert E. Butts - 1990 - Noûs 24 (1):1-16.
  • XIV—The Relation Between ‘Understanding’ and ‘Reason’ in the Architectonic of Kant's Philosophy1.Gerd Buchdahl - 1967 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 67 (1):209-226.
    Gerd Buchdahl; XIV—The Relation Between ‘Understanding’ and ‘Reason’ in the Architectonic of Kant's Philosophy1, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The conception of lawlikeness in Kant's philosophy of science.Gerd Buchdahl - 1972 - Synthese 23 (1-2):24 - 46.
    A demarcation between kant's general metaphysics (transcendental principles) and his special metaphysics is attempted, through a discussion of kant's three accounts of lawlikeness, 'transcendental', 'empirical' and 'metaphysical'. the distinctions are defended via a number of 'indicators' in kant's writings, and the 'looseness of fit' between the different types of lawlikeness is discussed.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Causality, causal laws and scientific theory in the philosophy of Kant.Gerd Buchdahl - 1965 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 16 (63):187-208.
  • Teleology in Biology: A Kantian Perspective.Angela Breitenbach - 2009 - Kant Yearbook 1 (1):31-56.
  • Der vierfache Sinn der inneren Zweckmäßigkeit in Kants Philosophie des Organischen.Paul Bommersheim - 1927 - Kant Studien 32 (1-3):290-309.
  • Der Begriff der organischen Selbstregulation in Kants Kritik der Urteilskraft.Paul Bommersheim - 1919 - Kant Studien 23 (1-3):209-220.
  • Kant’s Antinomy of Teleological Judgment.Henry E. Allison - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (S1):25-42.
  • Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft.Immanuel Kant - 1997 - Meiner, F.
    Kants Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft von 1786 stehen ihrem Anspruch nach zwischen einer transzendentalen Kritik der Vernunft - Kant bereitete zur selben Zeit die in wesentlichen Stücken umgearbeitete zweite Auflage der KrV vor - und der Physik als empirischer Wissenschaft. Die Notwendigkeit einer Reflexion über die Naturwissenschaft verhilft dieser Schrift heute wieder zu systematischer Relevanz, nachdem sie lange Zeit nur aus dem Blickwinkel ihrer Bedeutsamkeit für die empirische Naturwissenschaft betrachtet und infolgedessen allenfalls aus wissenschaftshistorischem Interesse rezipiert wurde.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht.Immanuel Kant - 2003 - Meiner, F.
    Kants Anthropologie (1798) galt lange als eine bloß popularphilosophische Schrift von allenfalls propädeutischem Wert. Dabei erfüllt sich die Leistung der Anthropologie keineswegs nur in einer vorphilosophischen Verständigung über das theoretische und praktische Vermögen des Menschen. Nur die anthropologische Reflexion verleiht Gewißheit, daß der Mensch "sein eigener letzter Zweck ist". Dies gibt dem Leben seinen Sinn.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Kritik Der Urteilskraft.Immanuel Kant & Karl Vorlander - 1924 - Andesite Press.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important, and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work was reproduced from the original artifact, and remains as true to the original work as possible. Therefore, you will see the original copyright references, library stamps (as most of these works have been housed in our most important libraries around the world), and other notations in the work. This work is in the public domain (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   171 citations  
  • Kant's early views on epigenesis : The role of maupertuis.John Zammito - 2006 - In Justin E. H. Smith (ed.), The Problem of Animal Generation in Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
  • Kant on understanding organisms as natural purposes.Hannah Ginsborg - 2001 - In Eric Watkins (ed.), Kant and the Sciences. Oxford University Press. pp. 231--58.
  • Organisms and the Unity of Science.Paul Guyer - 2001 - In Eric Watkins (ed.), Kant and the Sciences. Oxford University Press. pp. 259--281.
  • Causal laws and the foundations of natural science.Michael Friedman - 1992 - In Paul Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant. Cambridge University Press. pp. 3--161.
  • Kant, Naturphilosophie, and Scientific Method.L. Pearce Williams - 1973 - In Ronald N. Giere & Richard S. Westfall (eds.), Foundations of Scientific Method: The Nineteenth Century. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. pp. 3--22.
  • Haller et Les théories de Buffon et C. F. Wolff sur l'épigenèse.François Duchesneau - 1979 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 1 (1):65 - 100.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aspekte des Bedeutungswandels im Begriff organismischer Ähnlichkeit vom 18. zum 19. Jahrhundert.Hans-Jörg Rheinberger - 1986 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 8 (2):237 - 250.
    The concept of similarity plays a crucial role in biology, especially in natural history. Despite its apparent familiarity it has been subject again and again to reinterpretations — it may even be stated that the main streams of theoretical thinking in the life sciences are reflected and condensed in its ever changing meaning. The changing content of the concept is analyzed from Linnaean systematics through classical morphology and comparative anatomy to Darwinian evolutionary thinking. It appears that the meaning of similarity (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kant on the Systematicity of Nature: Two Puzzles.Paul Guyer - 2003 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 20 (3):277 - 295.
  • Kants Philosophie des Organischen und die Biologie seiner Zeit.Hans-Joachim Lieber - 1950 - Philosophia Naturalis 1:553.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Zweckmässigkeit, Zweckursächlichkeit und Ganzheitlichkeit in der organischen Natur: zum Problem einer teleologischen Naturauffassung in Kants «Kritik der Urteilskraft».Bernhard Rang - 1993 - Philosophisches Jahrbuch 100 (1):39-71.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations