Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Is Descartes a Temporal Atomist?Ken Levy - 2005 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13 (4):627 – 674.
    I argue that Descartes' Second Causal Proof of God in the Third Meditation evidences, and commits him to, the belief that time is "strongly discontinuous" -- that is, that there is actually a gap between each consecutive moment of time. Much of my article attempts to reconcile this interpretation, the "received view," with Descartes' statements about time, space, and matter in his other writings, including his correspondence with various philosophers.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Structure of Leibnizian Simple Substances.John Whipple - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (3):379-410.
  • Leibniz on Divine Concurrence.John Whipple - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (10):865-879.
    In this paper I examine G. W. Leibniz’s view on the debate between occasionalists, mere conservationists, and concurrentists. Although commentators agree that Leibniz wants to reject occasionalism and mere conservationism, there is considerable disagreement about whether Leibniz is committed to a theory of divine concurrence that differs from occasionalism and mere conservationism in principled ways. I critically assess three interpretations of Leibniz’s theory in this paper. The first two (those of Robert Adams and Sukjae Lee) differ with respect to important (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Leibniz on divine concurrence with secondary causes.Ezio Vailati - 2002 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 10 (2):209 – 230.
  • Leibnizian Chronadology.Andrew Pessin - 2006 - Journal of Philosophical Research 31:185-218.
    I argue that we can learn quite a lot about Leibniz’s metaphysics, in particular about monads and their relationship to time, by viewing Leibniz through a McTaggartian lens. After presenting McTaggart’s highly influential two basic conceptions of time, the A- (or tensed) and B- (or tenseless) conceptions, I distinguish four possible models of the relationship between monads and time: the fi rst two invoke tenses, differing in whether they treat non-present states as “real,” while the latter two are tenseless, differing (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Louis de la Forge and the development of occasionalism: Continuous creation and the activity of the soul.Steven M. Nadler - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (2):215-231.
    Louis de La Forge and the Development of Occasionalism: Continuous Creation and the Activity of the Soul STEVEN NADLER THE DOCTRINE OF DIVINE CONSERVATION is a dangerous one. It is not theologi- cally dangerous, at least not in itself. From the thirteenth century onwards, and particularly with the Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas, the notion of the continuous divine sustenance of the world of created things was, if not univer- sally accepted, a nonetheless common feature of theological orthodoxy, Chris- tian (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Leibniz: Creation and Conservation and Concurrence.Jeffrey K. McDonough - 2007 - The Leibniz Review 17:31-60.
    In this paper I argue that the hoary theological doctrine of divine concurrence poses no deep threat to Leibniz’s views on theodicy and creaturely activity even as those views have been traditionally understood. The first three sections examine respectively Leibniz’s views on creation, conservation and concurrence, with an eye towards showing their sys­tematic compatibility with Leibniz’s theodicy and metaphysics. The fourth section takes up remaining worries arising from the bridging principle that conservation is a continued or continuous creation, and argues (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The interval of motion in Leibniz's pacidius philalethi.Samuel Levey - 2003 - Noûs 37 (3):371–416.
  • Matter and two concepts of continuity in Leibniz.Samuel Levey - 1999 - Philosophical Studies 94 (1-2):81-118.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Leibniz on divine concurrence.Sukjae Lee - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (2):203-248.
    Leibniz was a divine concurrentist. That is to say, when it came to the question of how God’s causal power relates to the natural causal activity of creatures, Leibniz held that both God and the creature are directly involved in the occurrence of these effects.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Causality and Creation in Leibnitz.Nicholas Jolley - 1998 - The Monist 81 (4):591-611.
    Leibniz is famously committed to the following three metaphysical claims concerning causality.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Space and time in the Leibnizian metaphysic.Glenn A. Hartz & J. A. Cover - 1988 - Noûs 22 (4):493-519.
  • Leibniz's phenomenalisms.Glenn A. Hartz - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (3):511-549.
  • Unpacking the Monad.Marc Bobro & Kenneth Clatterbaugh - 1996 - The Monist 79 (3):408-425.