Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Books received. [REVIEW][author unknown] - 2011 - Philosophical Investigations 34 (4):410-411.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Utopia is Intelligible and Game-Playing is What Makes Utopia Intelligible.Deborah P. Vossen - 2016 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 43 (2):251-265.
    Via the existential questioning outlook supplied by the Grasshopper’s three visions as relevant to the fate of humankind – oblivion, delusion, and really magnificent games – this article seeks to alleviate some of the ambiguity surrounding Bernard Suits’ provocative claim that Utopian existence is fundamentally concerned with game-playing. Specifically, after proposing an interpretation of Suits’ parable designed to enrich the logical intelligibility of his Utopian thesis, I advance the suggestion that the Grasshopper’s picture of people playing really magnificent games is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Good Grasshopping and the Avoidance of Game-Spoiling.Deborah P. Vossen - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 35 (2):175-192.
    Traditionally, acts of sportsmanship have been upheld as worthy of praise. The purpose of this paper is to discern whether Bernard Suits’ Grasshopper -- in "The Grasshopper: Games, Life and Utopia" -- would share this approval. The paper begins with a conceptual analysis of good sportspersonship. From this, four action categories are identified including good sportspersonship in the forms of game desertion, changing the game, not trying, and lusory self-handicapping. A strategy for evaluation is derived from the Grasshopper’s theory. Game-playing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A Grasshopperian Analysis of the Strategic Foul.Deborah P. Vossen - 2014 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 41 (3):325-346.
    The question of acceptability in respect to the strategic foul in sport has provoked a rich and seemingly irreconcilable dispute with normative theorists currently divided amongst three schools of thought including formalism, conventionalism and interpretivism. In this paper, I seek to transcend the three-way intellectual stalemate portrayed in the literature via a consideration as to whether or not the strategic foul qualifies as ‘Utopian’. More specifically, after demonstrating that Bernard Suits’ theory of game-playing is fully capable of embracing all three (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Sport and Utopia.Keith Thompson - 2004 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 31 (1):60-63.
  • II—John Tasioulas.John Tasioulas - 2006 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1):237-264.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • John Tasioulas.John Tasioulas - 2006 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1):237–264.
  • Tricky Triad: Games, Play, and Sport.Bernard Suits - 1988 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 15 (1):1-9.
  • The Trick of the Disappearing Goal.Bernard Suits - 1989 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 16 (1):1-12.
  • Venn and the Artof Category Maintenance.Bernard Suits - 2004 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 31 (1):1-14.
  • What is a game?Bernard Suits - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (2):148-156.
    By means of a critical examination of a number of theses as to the nature of game-playing, the following definition is advanced: To play a game is to engage in activity directed toward bringing about a specific state of affairs, using only means permitted by specific rules, where the means permitted by the rules are more limited in scope than they would be in the absence of the rules, and where the sole reason for accepting such limitation is to make (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Words On Play.Bernard Suits - 1977 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 4 (1):117-131.
  • Sticky Wickedness: Games and Morality.Bernard Suits - 1982 - Dialogue 21 (4):755-759.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Grasshopper: Games, Life and Utopia.Bernard Suits & Thomas Hurka - 1978 - Broadview Press.
    In the mid twentieth century the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein famously asserted that games are indefinable; there are no common threads that link them all. "Nonsense," says the sensible Bernard Suits: "playing a game is a voluntary attempt to overcome unnecessary obstacles." The short book Suits wrote demonstrating precisely that is as playful as it is insightful, as stimulating as it is delightful. Suits not only argues that games can be meaningfully defined; he also suggests that playing games is a central (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   331 citations  
  • Games and Their Institutions in The Grasshopper.Bernard Suits - 2006 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 33 (1):1-8.
  • Is life a game we are playing?Bernard Suits - 1967 - Ethics 77 (3):209-213.
  • McBride and Paddick on The Grasshopper.Bernard Suits - 1981 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 8 (1):69-78.
  • Pre-lusory Goals for Games: A Gambit Declined.Angela J. Schneider & Robert B. Butcher - 1997 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 24 (1):38-46.
  • Fruits, Apples, and Category Mistakes: On Sport, Games, and Play.Angela J. Schneider - 2001 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 28 (2):151-159.
    (2001). Fruits, Apples, and Category Mistakes: On Sport, Games, and Play. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport: Vol. 28, No. 2, pp. 151-159. doi: 10.1080/00948705.2001.9714610.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Game-players and game-playing: a response to kreider.Richard Royce - 2013 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 40 (2):225-239.
    This article is an examination of the recent contribution in this journal by Kreider. In that publication he argued against formalist and non-formalist positions concerning our understanding of game-player and game-playing, focusing his discussion around game rules and their relationship to the two key concepts. This led him to produce alternative conceptions of game-player and game-playing, and it is these conceptions tied closely to the idea of commitment, and Kreider’s arguments surrounding them, which are the subject of my article. Following (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Grasshopper: Games, Life and Utopia.By Bernard Suits. Toronto, University of Toronto Press 1978.Robert J. Paddick - 1979 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 6 (1):73-78.
  • Game as Paradox: A Rebuttal of Suits.David Myers - 2012 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39 (1):155-168.
    Here I examine Bernard Suits’s definition of games and explain why that definition is in need of reference to representation or, put more generally, to semiosis. And, once admitting the necessity of the representational in games, Suits’s definition must also then admit the essential paradoxy of games.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • “Some Further Words on Suits on Play”.William J. Morgan - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 35 (2):120-141.
  • Triad Trickery: Playing With Sport and Games.Klaus V. Meier - 1988 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 15 (1):11-30.
  • Performance Prestidigitation.Klaus V. Meier - 1989 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 16 (1):13-33.
  • A Critique of Mr. Suits' Definition of Game Playing.Frank McBride - 1979 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 6 (1):59-65.
  • The Intelligibility of Suits’s Utopia: The View From Anthropological Philosophy.R. Scott Kretchmar - 2006 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 33 (1):67-77.
  • On Beautiful Games.R. Scott Kretchmar - 1989 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 16 (1):34-43.
  • Gaming Up Life: Considerations for Game Expansions.Scott Kretchmar - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 35 (2):142-155.
  • Game-Playing Without Rule-Following.A. J. Kreider - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 38 (1):55-73.
  • X—Games and Aims.Aurel Kolnai - 1966 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 66 (1):103-128.
    Aurel Kolnai; X—Games and Aims, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 66, Issue 1, 1 June 1966, Pages 103–128, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/66.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Grasshopper’s Error: Or, On How Life is a Game.Avery Kolers - 2015 - Dialogue 54 (4):727-746.
    I here defend the thesis that the best life is the life that one plays as a game—specifically, a ‘Suitsian’ game that meets the definition proposed in The Grasshopper by Bernard Suits. Even more specifically, it is a nested, open, role-playing game where the life’s quality as a game partly depends on there being no more people than players. To defend this thesis I refute two powerful challenges to it, one from Thomas Hurka (2006) and another from within The Grasshopper (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Games and Aims.Aurel Kolnai - 1966 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 66:103 - 128.
    Aurel Kolnai; X—Games and Aims, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 66, Issue 1, 1 June 1966, Pages 103–128, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/66.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On Judged Sports.Thomas Hurka - 2015 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 42 (3):317-325.
    Whereas Bernard Suits argued that judged sports such as diving and figure skating are aesthetic performances rather than games, I argue that they’re simultaneously performances and games. Moreover, their two aspects are connected, since their prelusory goal is to dive or skate beautifully and the requirement to do somersaults or triple jumps makes achieving that goal more difficult. This analysis is similar to one given by Scott Kretchmar, but by locating these sports’ aesthetic side in their goals rather than in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Games and the good.Thomas Hurka - 2006 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (1):217-235.
    Using Bernard Suits’s brilliant analysis (contra Wittgenstein) of playing a game, this paper examines the intrinsic value of game-playing. It argues that two elements in Suits’s analysis make success in games difficult, which is one ground of value, while a third involves choosing a good activity for the property that makes it good, which is a further ground. The paper concludes by arguing that game-playing is the paradigm modern (Marx, Nietzsche) as against classical (Aristotle) value: since its goal is intrinsically (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Games as Pastimes in Suits’s Utopia: Meaningful Living and the “Metaphysics of Leisure”.M. Andrew Holowchak - 2007 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 34 (1):88-96.
  • A Kantian view of Suits’ Utopia: ‘a kingdom of autotelically-motivated game players’.Francisco Javier Lopez Frias - 2017 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 44 (1):138-151.
    In this paper, I engage the debate on Suits’ theory of games by providing a Kantian view of Utopia. I argue that although the Kantian aspects of Suits’ approach are often overlooked in comparison to its Socratic-Platonic aspects, Kant’s ideas play a fundamental role in Suits’ proposal. In particular, Kant’s concept of ‘regulative idea’ is the basis of Suits’ Utopia. I regard Utopia as Suits’ regulative idea on game playing. In doing so, I take Utopia to play a double role (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On the Concept of a Game.Jonathan Ellis - 2011 - Philosophical Investigations 34 (4):381-392.
    Thomas Hurka writes, “an anti-theoretical position is properly open only to those who have made a serious effort to theorize a given domain and found that it cannot succeed. Anti-theorists who do not make this effort are simply being lazy, like Wittgenstein himself. His central example of a concept that cannot be given a unifying analysis was that of a game, but in one of the great underappreciated books of the twentieth century Bernard Suits gives perfectly persuasive necessary and sufficient (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The “Playing” Field: Attitudes, Activities, and the Conflation of Play and Games.Chad Carlson - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 38 (1):74-87.
  • The Force of Truth 1.Alex Blum - 2011 - Philosophical Investigations 34 (4):393-395.
    The theme of the paper is that what is true cannot be false and conversely. This position was anticipated by Aristotle in De Interpretatione and by G. H. von Wright. The latter calls it “a truth of the logic of relative modalities.”Aristotle has been taken to task by Susan Haack and others for arguing fallaciously from the Principle of Bivalence, that every statement is either true or false, to fatalism. The implication holds, but we show that it is unreasonable to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sprints, Sports, and Suits.Mitchell N. Berman - 2013 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 40 (1):163-176.
    Philosophy of sport orthodoxy maintains the following three theses: (1) all sports (or all refereed sports) are games; (2) games are as Suits defined them; and (3) sprints are sports. This article argues that these three theses cannot be jointly maintained and offers exploratory thoughts regarding what might follow.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Paper World of Bernard Suits.Allan Bäck - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 35 (2):156-174.
  • Games as Pastimes in Suits’s Utopia: Meaningful Living and the “Metaphysics of Leisure”.M. Andrew Holowchak - 2007 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 34 (1):88-96.
  • Triad trickery: playing with sport and games.Klaus V. Meier - 2013 - In Jason Holt (ed.), Philosophy of Sport: Core Readings. Broadview Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The elements of sport.Bernard Suits - 2013 - In Jason Holt (ed.), Philosophy of Sport: Core Readings. Broadview Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The Elements of Sport.Bernard Suits - 2007 - In William John Morgan (ed.), Ethics in Sport. Human Kinetics. pp. 9--19.
  • Toward an "Action Plan" for Game Life in Utopia: A Conceptual Analysis of "Fair Play", "Cheating", "Good Gamespersonship" and "Bad Gamespersonship".Deborah Pearl Vossen - 2001 - Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario (Canada)
    If you were an all-powerful being possessing the ability to create a perfect world of game participation, what would your world look like? More specifically, what would count as ethical conduct therein? Many would readily agree that 'fair play' and/or 'good gamespersonship' represent concepts descriptive of actions that would likely be contained within any proposed "Utopia of ethical game participation." 'Cheating' and/or 'bad gamespersonship', on the other hand, represent concepts descriptive of actions signifying vision betrayal. Despite such commonsense assertions, it (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Chess is Not a Game.Deborah P. Vossen - 2008 - In Benjamin Hale (ed.), Philosophy Looks at Chess. Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court Press. pp. 191-208.
    As described in Benjamin Hale’s Introduction to “Philosophy Looks at Chess”: -/- “Deb Vossen asks whether chess can rightly be considered a game in the first place. She concludes, much to the surprise of many readers, that chess is not a game. Her evocative claim turns on a distinction between a game and the idea of a game, which evolved out of Bernard Suits’s phenomenally underappreciated work The Grasshopper: Games, Life and Utopia. She advances this position by way of a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Games as Pastimes in Suits's Utopia: Meaningful Living and the "Metaphysics of Leisure".M. Holowchak - 2007 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 34 (1).
  • A Deep Blue grasshopper. Playing games with artificial intelligence.Andy Miah - 2008 - In Benjamin Hale (ed.), Philosophy Looks at Chess. Open Court Press.