Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Science and method.Henri Poincaré - 1914 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications. Edited by Francis Maitland.
    " Vivid . . . immense clarity . . . the product of a brilliant and extremely forceful intellect." — Journal of the Royal Naval Scientific Service "Still a sheer joy to read." — Mathematical Gazette "Should be read by any student, teacher or researcher in mathematics." — Mathematics Teacher The originator of algebraic topology and of the theory of analytic functions of several complex variables, Henri Poincare (1854–1912) excelled at explaining the complexities of scientific and mathematical ideas to lay (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • The value of science.Henri Poincaré - 1907 - New York,: Dover Publications. Edited by George Bruce Halsted.
    THE VALUE OF SCIENCE INTRODUCTION The search for truth should be the goal of our activities; it is the sole end worthy of them. Doubtless we should first bend our efforts to assuage human suffering, but why ? Not to suffer is a negative ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Science and method.Henri Poincaré - 1914 - New York]: Dover Publications. Edited by Francis Maitland.
    " Vivid . . . immense clarity . . . the product of a brilliant and extremely forceful intellect." — Journal of the Royal Naval Scientific Service "Still a sheer joy to read." — Mathematical Gazette "Should be read by any student, teacher or researcher in mathematics." — Mathematics Teacher The originator of algebraic topology and of the theory of analytic functions of several complex variables, Henri Poincare (1854–1912) excelled at explaining the complexities of scientific and mathematical ideas to lay (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • The Unseen Universe: Physical Speculations on a Future State.Balfour Stewart - 1875 - Cambridge University Press.
    In 1875, the geophysicist Balfour Stewart and the mathematician P. G. Tait published the second edition of The Unseen Universe. The book's aim had been 'to overthrow materialism by a purely scientific argument', and its initial success, and the controversy it aroused, prompted this revised edition. The treatise suggests that science and religion could be reconciled, and that by using science, it could be proved that the soul survives after death. The book begins with a historical account of the beliefs (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Essays in the History and Philosophy of Science.Pierre Maurice Marie Duhem - 1996 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    "This volume assembles twelve texts published between 1892 and 1915.... The editors allow one to see the genesis of the ideas of Duhem, philosopher and historian, of the variety of his styles, and sometimes also the limits of his work.... A useful index, probably unique in the field of Duhemian studies, completes the book.... The English-language public may be assured an exemplary translation and a reliable critical apparatus." --Jean Gayon, _Revue d'Histoire des Sciences_.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Wandering Significance: An Essay on Conceptual Behaviour.Chris Daly - 2007 - Philosophical Quarterly 57 (228):498-501.
  • When Realism Made a Difference: The Constitution of Matter and its Conceptual Enigmas in Late 19th Century Physics.Torsten Wilholt - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (1):1-16.
    The late 19th century debate among German-speaking physicists about theoretical entities is often regarded as foreshadowing the scientific realism debate. This paper brings out differences between them by concentrating on the part of the earlier debate that was concerned with the conceptual consistency of the competing conceptions of matter—mainly, but not exclusively, of atomism. Philosophical antinomies of atomism were taken up by Emil Du Bois-Reymond in an influential lecture in 1872. Such challenges to the consistency of atomism had repercussions within (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • When realism made a difference: The constitution of matter and its conceptual enigmas in late 19th century physics.Torsten Wilholt - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (1):1-16.
    The late 19th century debate among German-speaking physicists about theoretical entities is often regarded as foreshadowing the scientific realism debate. This paper brings out differences between them by concentrating on the part of the earlier debate that was concerned with the conceptual consistency of the competing conceptions of matter---{}mainly, but not exclusively, of atomism. Philosophical antinomies of atomism were taken up by Emil Du Bois-Reymond in an influential lecture in 1872. Such challenges to the consistency of atomism had repercussions within (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wandering Significance: An Essay on Conceptual Behavior.Mark Wilson - 2006 - Oxford, GB: Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    Mark Wilson presents a highly original and broad-ranging investigation of the way we get to grips with the world conceptually, and the way that philosophical problems commonly arise from this. He combines traditional philosophical concerns about human conceptual thinking with illuminating data derived from a large variety of fields including physics and applied mathematics, cognitive psychology, and linguistics. Wandering Significance offers abundant new insights and perspectives for philosophers of language, mind, and science, and will also reward the interest of psychologists, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Ludwig Boltzmann's Mathematical Argument for Atomism.Torsten Wilholt - 2001 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 9:199-211.
    In recent years, the philosophy of Ludwig Boltzmann has become a point of interest within the field of history of philosophy of science. Attention has centred around Boltzmann’s philosophical considerations connected to his defense of atomism in physics. In analysing these considerations, several scholars have attributed a pragmatist stance to Boltzmann. In this paper, I want to argue that, whatever pragmatist traits may be found in Boltzmann’s diverse writings, his defense of atomism in physics can not be analysed this way. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Determinism and the mystery of the missing physics.Mark Wilson - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (1):173-193.
    This article surveys the difficulties in establishing determinism for classical physics within the context of several distinct foundational approaches to the discipline. It explains that such problems commonly emerge due to a deeper problem of ‘missing physics'. The Problems of Formalism Norton's Example Three Species of Classical Mechanics 3.1 Mass point physics 3.2 The physics of perfect constraints 3.3 Continuum mechanics Conclusion CiteULike Connotea Del.icio.us What's this?
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • On the origins and foundations of Laplacian determinism.Marij van Strien - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 45:24-31.
    In this paper I examine the foundations of Laplace's famous statement of determinism in 1814, and argue that rather than derived from his mechanics, this statement is based on general philosophical principles, namely the principle of sufficient reason and the law of continuity. It is usually supposed that Laplace's statement is based on the fact that each system in classical mechanics has an equation of motion which has a unique solution. But Laplace never proved this result, and in fact he (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Bluff Your Way in the Second Law of Thermodynamics.Jos Uffink - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32 (3):305-394.
    The aim of this article is to analyse the relation between the second law of thermodynamics and the so-called arrow of time. For this purpose, a number of different aspects in this arrow of time are distinguished, in particular those of time-reversal (non-)invariance and of (ir)reversibility. Next I review versions of the second law in the work of Carnot, Clausius, Kelvin, Planck, Gibbs, Caratheodory and Lieb and Yngvason, and investigate their connection with these aspects of the arrow of time. It (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • The problem of time's arrow historico-critically reexamined.Roberto Torretti - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (4):732-756.
  • The Problem of Time’s Arrow Historico-critically Reexamined.Roberto Torretti - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (4):732-756.
    Responding to Hasok Chang’s vision of the history and philosophy of science as the continuation of science by other means, I illustrate the methods of HPS and their utility through a historico-critical examination of the problem of “time’s arrow‘, that is to say, the problem posed by the claim by Boltzmann and others that the temporal asymmetry of many physical processes and indeed the very possibility of identifying each of the two directions we distinguish in time must have a ground (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Norton Dome and the Nineteenth Century Foundations of Determinism.Marij van Strien - 2014 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 45 (1):167-185.
    The recent discovery of an indeterministic system in classical mechanics, the Norton dome, has shown that answering the question whether classical mechanics is deterministic can be a complicated matter. In this paper I show that indeterministic systems similar to the Norton dome were already known in the nineteenth century: I discuss four nineteenth century authors who wrote about such systems, namely Poisson, Duhamel, Boussinesq and Bertrand. However, I argue that their discussion of such systems was very different from the contemporary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Princess Elizabeth and Descartes: The union of soul and body and the practice of philosophy.Lisa Shapiro - 1999 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (3):503 – 520.
    (1999). Princess Elizabeth and Descartes: The union of soul and body and the practice of philosophy. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 7, No. 3, pp. 503-520. doi: 10.1080/09608789908571042.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • From Axioms to Conventions and Hypotheses: The Foundations of Mechanics and the Roots of Carl Neumann’s “Principles of the Galilean–Newtonian Theory”.Helmut Pulte - 2009 - In Michael Heidelberger & Gregor Schiemann (eds.), The Significance of the Hypothetical in Natural Science. De Gruyter. pp. 77-98.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Philosophical objections to the kinetic theory.John Nyhof - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (1):81-109.
    Towards the end of the 19th century there were those who wished to see the kinetic theory abandoned. This paper attempts to show that this reaction was primarily due to philosophical objections rather than the result of scientific difficulties encountered by the kinetic theory. First the relevant philosophical background is examined as well as the relation between the kinetic theory and thermodynamics. Next the scientific difficulty known as the specific heats ratio anomaly is discussed and finally Boltzmann's philosophy of science (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Moral Freedom of Man and the Determinism of Nature: The Catholic Synthesis of Science and History in the Revue des Questions Scientifiques.Mary Nye - 1976 - British Journal for the History of Science 9 (3):274-292.
    In 1877 the first issue of the Revue des questions scientifiques, published by the Scientific Society of Brussels, appeared in France and Belgium. The new journal was greeted with disdain and hostility by Emile Littrè and George Wyrouboff, the disciples of Auguste Comte and editors of La philosophie positive. The Scientific Society of Brussels was a Catholic organization, and the positivists' opinion was that ‘If science is spoken of in this assembly, it is in order to organize a veritable crusade (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Dome: An Unexpectedly Simple Failure of Determinism.John D. Norton - 2008 - Philosophy of Science 75 (5):786-798.
    Newton’s equations of motion tell us that a mass at rest at the apex of a dome with the shape specified here can spontaneously move. It has been suggested that this indeterminism should be discounted since it draws on an incomplete rendering of Newtonian physics, or it is “unphysical,” or it employs illicit idealizations. I analyze and reject each of these reasons. †To contact the author, please write to: Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Descartes on mind-body interaction and the conservation of motion.Peter McLaughlin - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (2):155-182.
    The traditional (Leibnizian) reading of Descartes on mind-body interaction is given a more rigorous reformulation, explaining how Descartes could assert that the mind while not affecting the quantity of motion in the world could change its direction. It is shown, contrary to the trend in recent literature, that this reading has a reliable textual base, and it is argued that it attributes to Descartes a philosophical position of more substance and interest. The kind of interpretation favored depends on the status (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Pointsman: Maxwell’s Demon, Victorian Free Will, and the Boundaries of Science.Matthew Stanley - 2008 - Journal of the History of Ideas 69 (3):467-491.
    This article discusses the writings of the devout Christian physicist James Clerk Maxwell (best known for his epochal work in electromagnetism and statistical mechanics) on the concept of conscious free-will. To Maxwell a correct understanding of free will, as personified in the example of the railway pointsman, was essential to clear conceptions of both man as a religious creature and of the limits of science. Understanding human volition, then, was not an end unto itself. It was a foundation on which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Norton’s Slippery Slope.David B. Malament - 2008 - Philosophy of Science 75 (5):799-816.
    In my contribution to the Symposium ("On the Vagaries of Determinism and Indeterminism"), I will identify several issues that arise in trying to decide whether Newtonian particle mechanics qualifies as a deterministic theory. I'll also give a mini-tutorial on the geometry and dynamical properties of Norton's dome surface. The goal is to better understand how his example works, and better appreciate just how wonderfully strange it is.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Indeterminism, asymptotic reasoning, and time irreversibility in classical physics.Alexandre Korolev - 2007 - Philosophy of Science 74 (5):943-956.
    A recent proposal by Norton (2003) to show that a simple Newtonian system can exhibit stochastic acausal behavior by giving rise to spontaneous movements of a mass on the dome of a certain shape is examined. We discuss the physical significance of an often overlooked and yet important Lipschitz condition the violation of which leads to the existence of anomalous nontrivial solutions in this and similar cases. We show that the Lipschitz condition is closely linked with the time reversibility of (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Mechanical Explanation at the End of the Nineteenth Century.Martin J. Klein - 1973 - Centaurus 17 (1):58-82.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Traité de l'enchaînement des idées fondamentales dans les sciences et dans l'histoire.Antoine Augustin Cournot - 1968 - Roma,: Bizzarri.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Concepts of Force.Max Jammer - 1959 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 20 (1):132-132.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Is classical mechanics really time-reversible and deterministic?Keith Hutchison - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):307-323.
  • Helmholtz and Kant: The Metaphysical Foundations of "Über die Erhaltung der Kraft".P. M. Heimann - 1974 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 5 (3):205.
  • Of liberty and necessity: the free will debate in eighteenth-century British philosophy.James A. Harris - 2005 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The eighteenth century was a time of brilliant philosophical innovation in Britain. In Of Liberty and Necessity James A. Harris presents the first comprehensive account of the period's discussion of what remains a central problem of philosophy, the question of the freedom of the will. He offers new interpretations of contributions to the free will debate made by canonical figures such as Locke, Hume, Edwards, and Reid, and also discusses in detail the arguments of some less familiar writers. Harris puts (...)
  • Nineteenth Century Cracks in the Concept of Determinism.Ian Hacking - 1983 - Journal of the History of Ideas 44 (3):455.
  • Poincaré and the philosophy of mathematics.Janet Folina - 1996 - New York: St. Martin's Press.
  • Poincaré and the Philosophy of Mathematics.Mark Steiner - 1996 - Philosophical Quarterly 46 (183):251-255.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philosophy and the kinetic theory of gases.Henk W. de Regt - 1996 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (1):31-62.
    This article examines the role of philosophy in the development of the kinetic theory of gases. Two opposing accounts of this role, by Peter Clark and John Nyhof, are discussed and criticized. Contrary to both accounts, it is argued that philosophical views of scientists can fundamentally influence the results of their scientific work. This claim is supported by a detailed analysis of the philosophical views of Maxwell and Boltzmann, and of their work on the kinetic theory, especially concerning the so-called (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Ludwig Boltzmann's Bildtheorie and Scientific Understanding.Henk W. de Regt - 1999 - Synthese 119 (1-2):113-134.
    Boltzmann’s Bildtheorie, which asserts that scientific theories are ‘mental pictures’ having at best a partial similarity to reality, was a core element of his philosophy of science. The aim of this article is to draw attention to a neglected aspect of it, namely its significance for the issue of scientific explanation and understanding, regarded by Boltzmann as central goals of science. I argue that, in addition to being an epistemological view of the interpretation of scientific theories Boltzmann’s Bildtheorie has implications (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Wilhelm Ostwald’s Energetics 1: Origins and Motivations. [REVIEW]R. J. Deltete - 2006 - Foundations of Chemistry 9 (1):3-56.
  • Wilhelm Ostwald’s energetics 2: energetic theory and applications, part I. [REVIEW]R. J. Deltete - 2007 - Foundations of Chemistry 9 (3):265-316.
    This is the second of a series of essays on the development and reception of Wilhelm Ostwald’s energetics. The first essay described the chemical origins of Ostwald’s interest in the energy concept and his motivations for seeking a comprehensive science of energy. The present essay and the next discuss his various attempts, beginning in 1891 and extending over almost 3 years, to develop a consistent and coherent energetic theory. A final essay will consider reactions to this work and Ostwald’s replies, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Helm and Boltzmann: Energetics at the lübeck naturforscherversammlung.Robert Deltete - 1999 - Synthese 119 (1-2):45-68.
    The energetics controversy is understood variously as energy vs. atoms, thermodynamics vs. statistical mechanics, phenomenalism vs. realism, equations vs. pictures, and especially Ostwald vs. Boltzmann. It is generally thought that at Lübeck in 1895 Boltzmann and Planck demolished energetics, but while its momentum was slowed, energetics in one or more of the above senses still retained supporters as late as the great physics conference at the St. Louis World’s Fair in 1904. Indeed, after Ostwald himself abandoned it in 1908, Ernst (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Number and measure: Hermann von Helmholtz at the crossroads of mathematics, physics, and psychology.Olivier Darrigol - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (3):515-573.
    In 1887 Helmholtz discussed the foundations of measurement in science as a last contribution to his philosophy of knowledge. This essay borrowed from earlier debates on the foundations of mathematics, on the possibility of quantitative psychology, and on the meaning of temperature measurement. Late nineteenth-century scrutinisers of the foundations of mathematics made little of Helmholtz’s essay. Yet it inspired two mathematicians with an eye on physics, and a few philosopher-physicists. The aim of the present paper is to situate Helmholtz’s contribution (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The Great Chain of Being. A Study of the History of an Idea. [REVIEW]H. T. C. - 1936 - Journal of Philosophy 33 (21):580.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Into the ‘regions of physical and metaphysical chaos’: Maxwell’s scientific metaphysics and natural philosophy of action.Jordi Cat - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (1):91-104.
  • The metaphysics of time reversal: Hutchison on classical mechanics.Craig Callender - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (3):331-340.
    What grounds the standard claim that classical mechanics is time-reversal invariant? Hutchison (1993, 1995) challenges the conventional reasoning underlying the belief that classical mechanics is time reversal invariant and argues that it is not in any well-defined sense. I find a defensible criterion that will exclude his cases, thereby rescuing a sense in which we can say that classical mechanics is time reversal invariant.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Origins of Time-Asymmetry in Thermodynamics: The Minus First Law.Harvey R. Brown & Jos Uffink - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32 (4):525-538.
    This paper investigates what the source of time-asymmetry is in thermodynamics, and comments on the question whether a time-symmetric formulation of the Second Law is possible.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Boltzmann's H-theorem, its discontents, and the birth of statistical mechanics.Harvey R. Brown, Wayne Myrvold & Jos Uffink - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 40 (2):174-191.
  • The Rise of Statistical Thinking, 1820-1900.Theodore M. Porter - 1986 - Princeton University Press: Princeton.
    Emphasizing the debt of science to nonspecialist intellectuals, Theodore Porter describes in detail the nineteenth-century background that produced the burst of modern statistical innovation of the early 1900s. Statistics arose as a study of society--the science of the statist--and the pioneering statistical physicists and biologists, Maxwell, Boltzmann, and Galton, each introduced statistical models by pointing to analogies between his discipline and social science.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Ludwig Boltzmann: The Man Who Trusted Atoms.Carlo Cercignani - 1998 - Oxford University Press UK.
    This book presents the life and personality, the scientific and philosophical work of Ludwig Boltzmann, one of the great scientists who marked the passage from 19th- to 20th-Century physics. His rich and tragic life, ending by suicide at the age of 62, is described in detail. A substantial part of the book is devoted to discussing his scientific and philosophical ideas and placing them in the context of the second half of the 19th century. The fact that Boltzmann was the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Ludwig Boltzmann: The Man Who Trusted Atoms.Carlo Cercignani - 1998 - Oxford University Press UK.
    The book presents the life and personality, the scientific and philosophical work of Ludwig Boltzmann, one of the great scientists who marked the passage from 19th to 20th century physics. His rich and tragic life, ending by suicide at the age of 62, is described in detail. A substantial part of the book is devoted to discussing his scientific and philosophical ideas and placing them in the context of the second half of the 19th century. The fact that Boltzmann was (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Erkenntnis und Irrtum: Skizzen zur Psychologie der Forschung.Ernst Mach (ed.) - 2011 - Zenodot.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Die Principien der Wärmelehre Historisch-Kritisch Entwickelt.Ernst Mach - 1896 - J.A. Barth.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations