Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Self-defense, pacifism, and the possibility of killing.Cheyney C. Ryan - 1982 - Ethics 93 (3):508-524.
  • War and self-defense.David Rodin - 2004 - Ethics and International Affairs 18 (1):63–68.
    When is it right to go to war? The most persuasive answer to this question has always been 'in self-defense'. In a penetrating new analysis, bringing together moral philosophy, political science, and law, David Rodin shows what's wrong with this answer. He proposes a comprehensive new theory of the right of self-defense which resolves many of the perplexing questions that have dogged both jurists and moral philosophers. By applying the theory of self-defense to international relations, Rodin produces a far-reaching critique (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations.Barrie Paskins & Michael Walzer - 1981 - Philosophical Quarterly 31 (124):285.
  • Innocence and Responsibility in War.Lionel K. McPherson - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (4):485-506.
    Innocence is a notion that can prove controversial. Claims of innocence typically support not imposing burdens on the innocent when their conduct is relevantly unobjectionable. This paper examines innocence in the context of violent conflict between states or groups. Many thinkers about the morality of such violence want to establish a principle that would protect innocent civilians. Yet the common view in just war theory does not affirm the moral innocence of civilians. Similarly, the common view that soldiers have an (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Self-defense and the problem of the innocent attacker.Jeff McMahan - 1994 - Ethics 104 (2):252-290.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Innocence, self-defense and killing in war.Jeff McMahan - 1994 - Journal of Political Philosophy 2 (3):193–221.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Debate: Justification and Liability in War.Jeff McMahan - 2008 - Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (2):227-244.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Coerced moral agents? Individual responsibility for military service.David R. Mapel - 1998 - Journal of Political Philosophy 6 (2):171–189.
  • Responsibility and Culpability in War.Helene Ingierd & Henrik Syse - 2005 - Journal of Military Ethics 4 (2):85-99.
    This article furnishes a philosophical background for the current debate about responsibility and culpability for war crimes by referring to ideas from three important just war thinkers: Augustine, Francisco de Vitoria, and Michael Walzer. It combines lessons from these three thinkers with perspectives on current problems in the ethics of war, distinguishes between legal culpability, moral culpability, and moral responsibility, and stresses that even lower-ranking soldiers must in many cases assume moral responsibility for their acts, even though they are part (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Child soldiers and international law: Patchwork gains and conceptual debates.Mary-Jane Fox - 2005 - Human Rights Review 7 (1):27-48.
    This article reviews and also compares developments within international humanitarian law and human rights law in regard to matters relating to child soldiers. Beginning with the Geneva Conventions and early twentieth century legal developments for children in general, this article identifies the legal and conceptual discrepancies in the child soldiers issue and how they relate to and affect each other. It also includes an overview of the child soldiers issue, followed by summary discussions of the respective strengths and weaknesses of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • When is a child not a child? Child soldiers in international law.Claire Breen - 2007 - Human Rights Review 8 (2):71-103.
    International humanitarian law and international human rights law both prohibit the use of child soldiers in armed conflict. The protection afforded to children is problematic because the age a child may become a soldier and what constitutes child “soldiering” fluctuates between States and cultures. Differing levels of children soldiers’ protection leave them vulnerable to particular abuses. This paper examines some different attitudes and approaches towards the use of child soldiers and concludes that international human rights law and international humanitarian law (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Becoming versus being: A critical analysis of the child in liberal theory.Barbara Arneil - 2002 - In David Archard & Colin M. Macleod (eds.), The Moral and Political Status of Children. Oxford University Press. pp. 70--96.
    The excessive faith liberal theorists have had in the power of rights and rights discourse can have deleterious consequences for children. As vulnerable and dependent beings, children need to be nurtured with love and affection in a setting in which intimate relationships between parents and children can flourish. A rights‐based discourse is conceptually ill‐equipped to accommodate the importance of establishing and supporting caring relationships. An ethic of care, emphasizing responsibilities over rights, provides a better way of conceptualizing and responding to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers.David Rodin & Henry Shue (eds.) - 2008 - Oxford University Press.
    Can a soldier be held responsible for fighting in a war that is illegal or unjust? The chapters in the book both challenge and defend many deeply held assumptions: about the liability of soldiers for crimes of aggression, about the nature and justifiability of terrorism, about the relationship between law and morality.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Self-defense.Judith Jarvis Thomson - 1991 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (4):283-310.
    But what if in order to save 0nc’s life one has to ki]1 another person? In some cases that is obviously permissible. In a case I will call Villainous Aggrcssor, you are standing in :1 meadow, innocently minding your own business, and 21 truck suddenly heads toward you. You try to sidestep the truck, but it tums as you tum. Now you can sec the driver: he is a mam you know has long hated you. What to do? You cannot (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • The moral inequality of soldiers: Why jus in Bello asymmetry is half right.David Rodin - 2008 - In David Rodin & Henry Shue (eds.), Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers. Oxford University Press. pp. 44--68.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Childhood and Personhood.Tamar Schapiro - 2003 - Arizona Law Review 575 45:575-594.