Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Hundred Years Of Numbers. An Historical Introduction To Measurement Theory 1887–1990.JoséA Díez - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (2):237-265.
    Part II: Suppes and the mature theory. Representation and uniqueness.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Models and representation: why structures are not enough.Roman Frigg - 2002 - London School of Economics and Political Science.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Models and Analogies in Science.Mary B. Hesse - 1963 - [Notre Dame, Ind.]: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Painting as an Art.Richard Wollheim - 1987 - Princeton University Press.
    Explains the difference between pictorial and linguistic meaning, examines the works of Titian, Poussin, Ingres, Manet, Picasso, and de Kooning, and discusses art's psychological impact.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • The Emergence of Natural Representations.Andrew Woodfield - 1990 - Philosophical Topics 18 (2):187-213.
  • Painting as an Art.Joseph Margolis - 1989 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (3):281-284.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The Structure and Confirmation of Evolutionary Theory.Elisabeth Anne Lloyd - 1994 - Princeton University Press.
    Traditionally a scientific theory is viewed as based on universal laws of nature that serve as axioms for logical deduction. In analyzing the logical structure of evolutionary biology, Elisabeth Lloyd argues that the semantic account is more appropriate and powerful. This book will be of interest to biologists and philosophers alike.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Structural representation and surrogative reasoning.Chris Swoyer - 1991 - Synthese 87 (3):449 - 508.
    It is argued that a number of important, and seemingly disparate, types of representation are species of a single relation, here called structural representation, that can be described in detail and studied in a way that is of considerable philosophical interest. A structural representation depends on the existence of a common structure between a representation and that which it represents, and it is important because it allows us to reason directly about the representation in order to draw conclusions about the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • An inferential conception of scientific representation.Mauricio Suárez - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):767-779.
    This paper defends an inferential conception of scientific representation. It approaches the notion of representation in a deflationary spirit, and minimally characterizes the concept as it appears in science by means of two necessary conditions: its essential directionality and its capacity to allow surrogate reasoning and inference. The conception is defended by showing that it successfully meets the objections that make its competitors, such as isomorphism and similarity, untenable. In addition the inferential conception captures the objectivity of the cognitive representations (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   243 citations  
  • On the general theory of meaningful representation.Brent Mundy - 1986 - Synthese 67 (3):391 - 437.
    The numerical representations of measurement, geometry and kinematics are here subsumed under a general theory of representation. The standard theories of meaningfulness of representational propositions in these three areas are shown to be special cases of two theories of meaningfulness for arbitrary representational propositions: the theories based on unstructured and on structured representation respectively. The foundations of the standard theories of meaningfulness are critically analyzed and two basic assumptions are isolated which do not seem to have received adequate justification: the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Unifying Scientific Theories.Margaret Morrison - 2001 - Mind 110 (440):1097-1102.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • The Structure and Confirmation of Evolutionary Theory.Elisabeth A. Lloyd - 1992 - Noûs 26 (1):132-133.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   243 citations  
  • Science without Laws.Mauricio Suárez - 2002 - Mind 111 (441):111-114.
    1Department of Philosophy, University of Bristol, 9 Woodland Road, Bristol BS8 1TB, UKScience Without Laws Ronald Giere Chicago, IL University of Chicago Press 1999 x + 285 Hardback£17.50.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Science without laws.Ronald N. Giere - 1999 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    Debate over the nature of science has recently moved from the halls of academia into the public sphere, where it has taken shape as the "science wars." At issue is the question of whether scientific knowledge is objective and universal or socially mediated, whether scientific truths are independent of human values and beliefs. Ronald Giere is a philosopher of science who has been at the forefront of this debate from its inception, and Science without Laws offers a much-needed mediating perspective (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   253 citations  
  • How models are used to represent reality.Ronald N. Giere - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):742-752.
    Most recent philosophical thought about the scientific representation of the world has focused on dyadic relationships between language-like entities and the world, particularly the semantic relationships of reference and truth. Drawing inspiration from diverse sources, I argue that we should focus on the pragmatic activity of representing, so that the basic representational relationship has the form: Scientists use models to represent aspects of the world for specific purposes. Leaving aside the terms "law" and "theory," I distinguish principles, specific conditions, models, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   301 citations  
  • Explaining Science.Ronald Giere - 1991 - Noûs 25 (3):386-388.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   291 citations  
  • Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. [REVIEW]Jeffrey S. Poland - 1988 - Philosophical Review 100 (4):653-656.
  • Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach.Paul Teller - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (4):729-731.
  • The Scientific Image by Bas C. van Fraassen. [REVIEW]Michael Friedman - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (5):274-283.
  • Foundations of Space-Time Theories.Michael Friedman - 1987 - Noûs 21 (4):595-601.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   242 citations  
  • Foundations of Space-Time Theories.Robert Weingard - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (2):286-299.
    Foundations of Space-Time Theories, by Michael Friedman, falls naturally into two parts. In the first, he presents the general framework within which he will characterize and discuss space-time theories, and then he devotes a chapter each to Newtonian physics, special relativity, and general relativity. Although there is some rich philosophical discussion along the way, these chapters are, of necessity, somewhat technical expositions of the general framework in action. It is in the second part, consisting of two substantial chapters, one on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Reinflating the semantic approach.Steven French & James Ladyman - 1999 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (2):103 – 121.
    The semantic, or model-theoretic, approach to theories has recently come under criticism on two fronts: (i) it is claimed that it cannot account for the wide diversity of models employed in scientific practice—a claim which has led some to propose a “deflationary” account of models; (ii) it is further contended that the sense of “model” used by the approach differs from that given in model theory. Our aim in the present work is to articulate a possible response to these claims, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   140 citations  
  • A hundred years of numbers. An historical introduction to measurement theory 1887–1990.JoséA Díez - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (1):167-185.
    Part II: Suppes and the mature theory. Representation and uniqueness.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Meaning and Mental Representation.Peter Carruthers - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161):527-530.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   186 citations  
  • Critical Notices.Nancy Cartwright - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (1):244-249.
    The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. nancy cartwright. Plato's Reception of Parmenides. john a. palmer.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   315 citations  
  • Empirical adequacy: A partial structures approach.Otávio Bueno - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (4):585-610.
    Based on da Costa's and French's notions of partial structures and pragmatic truth, this paper examines two possible characterizations of the concept of empirical adequacy, one depending on the notion of partial isomorphism, the other on the hierarchy of partial models of phenomena, and both compatible with an empiricist view. These formulations can then be employed to illuminate certain aspects of scientific practice.An empirical theory must single out a specific part of the world, establish reference to that part, and say—by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • When scientific models represent.Daniela M. Bailer-Jones - 2003 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 17 (1):59 – 74.
    Scientific models represent aspects of the empirical world. I explore to what extent this representational relationship, given the specific properties of models, can be analysed in terms of propositions to which truth or falsity can be attributed. For example, models frequently entail false propositions despite the fact that they are intended to say something "truthful" about phenomena. I argue that the representational relationship is constituted by model users "agreeing" on the function of a model, on the fit with data and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Foundations of Measurement, Vol. I: Additive and Polynomial Representations.David Krantz, Duncan Luce, Patrick Suppes & Amos Tversky (eds.) - 1971 - New York Academic Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Foundations of Space-Time Theories.Micheal Friedman - 1983 - Princeton University Press.
  • The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    It is often supposed that the spectacular successes of our modern mathematical sciences support a lofty vision of a world completely ordered by one single elegant theory. In this book Nancy Cartwright argues to the contrary. When we draw our image of the world from the way modern science works - as empiricism teaches us we should - we end up with a world where some features are precisely ordered, others are given to rough regularity and still others behave in (...)
  • Theories, models, and representations.Mauricio Suárez - 1999 - In L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessian & P. Thagard (eds.), Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery. Kluwer/Plenum. pp. 75--83.
    I argue against an account of scientific representation suggested by the semantic, or structuralist, conception of scientific theories. Proponents of this conception often employ the term “model” to refer to bare “structures”, which naturally leads them to attempt to characterize the relation between models and reality as a purely structural one. I argue instead that scientific models are typically “representations”, in the pragmatist sense of the term: they are inherently intended for specific phenomena. Therefore in general scientific models are not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Using models to represent reality.Ronald N. Giere - 1999 - In L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessian & P. Thagard (eds.), Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery. Kluwer/Plenum. pp. 41--57.
  • Meaning and Mental Representation.Robert Cummins - 1990 - Mind 99 (396):637-642.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  • Hacia Una teoría general de la representación científica (tovvards a general theory of scientific represcntation).José A. Díez - 1998 - Theoria 13 (1):113-139.
    En la actividad científica se pueden distinguir tres tipos principales de representación científica: proyectiva, subsuntiva y reductiva. Tras unas breves considcraciones introductorias, se presentan las características más destacadas de cada uno de estos tres tipos principales de representación científica y se abstrae a partir de ellas el esquema al que toda Teoría General de la Representación Científica (TGRC) se debe adecuar. A continuación se exponen las lineas generales de la principal propuesta presente en la literatura para desarrollar TGRC y se (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Languages of Art.Nelson Goodman - 1970 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 3 (1):62-63.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   601 citations  
  • Models and Representation: Why Structures Are Not Enough.Roman Frigg - manuscript
    Models occupy a central role in the scientific endeavour. Among the many purposes they serve, representation is of great importance. Many models are representations of something else; they stand for, depict, or imitate a selected part of the external world (often referred to as target system, parent system, original, or prototype). Well-known examples include the model of the solar system, the billiard ball model of a gas, the Bohr model of the atom, the Gaussian-chain model of a polymer, the MIT (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Models and Analogies in Science.Mary B. Hesse - 1966 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 3 (3):190-191.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   411 citations  
  • From Vicious Circle to Infinite Regress, and Back Again.Bas C. van Fraassen - 1992 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992:6-29.
    The attempt to formulate a viable empiricist and non-foundationalist epistemology of science faces four problems here confronted. The first is an apparent loss of objectivity in science, in the conditions of use of models in applied science. The second derives from the theory-infection of scientific language, with an apparent loss of objective conditions of truth and reference. The third, often cited as objection to The Scientific Image, is the apparent theory-dependence of the distinction between what is and is not observable. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Models and Analogies in Science.Mary Hesse - 1965 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 16 (62):161-163.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - Philosophy 75 (294):613-616.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   574 citations  
  • Unifying Scientific Theories: Physical Concepts and Mathematical Structures.Margaret Morrison - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 51 (204):405-408.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • The semantic approach to scientific theories.Bas C. van Frassen - 1987 - In Nancy J. Nersessian (ed.), The Process of Science: Contemporary Philosophical Approaches to Understanding Scientific Practice. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations