Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Proper names.John R. Searle - 1958 - Mind 67 (266):166-173.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • On Denoting.Bertrand Russell - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):873 - 887.
    By a `denoting phrase' I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the center of mass of the solar system at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. Thus a phrase is denoting solely in virtue of its form. We may distinguish (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   667 citations  
  • Frege puzzles?Joseph Almog - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 37 (6):549 - 574.
    The first page of Frege’s classic “Uber Sinn und Bedeutung” sets for more than a hundred years now the agenda for much of semantics and the philosophy of mind. It presents a purported puzzle whose solution is said to call upon the “entities” of semantics (meanings) and psychological explanation (Psychological states, beliefs, concepts). The paper separates three separate alleged puzzles that can be read into Frege’s data. It then argues that none are genuine puzzles. In turn, much of the Frege-driven (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Frege’s Puzzle (2nd edition).Nathan U. Salmon - 1986 - Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
    This is the 1991 (2nd) edition of the 1986 book (MIT Press), considered to be the classic defense of Millianism. The nature of the information content of declarative sentences is a central topic in the philosophy of language. The natural view that a sentence like "John loves Mary" contains information in which two individuals occur as constituents is termed the naive theory, and is one that has been abandoned by most contemporary scholars. This theory was refuted originally by philosopher Gottlob (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   535 citations  
  • Types and tokens: on abstract objects.Linda Wetzel - 2009 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
    In this book, Linda Wetzel examines the distinction between types and tokens and argues that types exist (as abstract objects, since they lack a unique ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The Frege reader.Gottlob Frege & Michael Beaney (eds.) - 1997 - Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell.
    This is the first single-volume edition and translation of Frege's philosophical writings to include his seminal papers as well as substantial selections from ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   229 citations  
  • Themes From Kaplan.Joseph Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein (eds.) - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This anthology of essays on the work of David Kaplan, a leading contemporary philosopher of language, sprang from a conference, "Themes from Kaplan," organized by the Center for the Study of Language and Information at Stanford University.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   617 citations  
  • Afterthoughts.David Kaplan - 1989 - In J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein (eds.), Themes From Kaplan. Oxford University Press. pp. 565-614.
  • Can Frege pose Frege's puzzle?Stavroula Glezakos - 2009 - In Joseph Almog & Paolo Leonardi (eds.), The Philosophy of David Kaplan. Oxford University Press. pp. 202.
    Gottlob Frege maintained that two name-containing identity sentences, represented schematically as a=a and a=b,can both be true in virtue of the same object’s self-identity but nonetheless, puzzlingly, differ in their epistemic profiles. Frege eventually resolved his puzzlement by locating the source of the purported epistemic difference between the identity sentences in a difference in the Sinne, or senses, expressed by the names that the sentences contain. -/- Thus, Frege portrayed himself as describing a puzzle that can be posed prior to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Uber Sinn und Bedeutung.Gottlob Frege - 1892 - Zeitschrift für Philosophie Und Philosophische Kritik 100 (1):25-50.
  • A puzzle about belief.Saul A. Kripke - 1979 - In A. Margalit (ed.), Meaning and Use. Reidel. pp. 239--83.
  • Frege's Conception of Logic.Warren Goldfarb - 2001 - In Juliet Floyd (ed.), Future Pasts: The Analytic Tradition in Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 25-41.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Why is Frege's Puzzle Still Puzzling?Eros Corazza & Jerome Dokič - 1995 - In Petr Kotatko & John Biro (eds.), Frege: Sense and Reference One Hundred Years Later. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 151--168.