Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Film as Art.Vernon Young - 1958 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 17 (2):260-262.
    In the fall of 1957 the University of California Press expanded Arnheim’s 1933 book _Film_ by four essays and brought that landmark work back into print as _Film as Art._ Now nearly fifty years after that re-edition, the book continues to occupy an important place in the literature of film. Arnheim’s method, provocative in this age of technological wizardry, was to focus on the way art in film was derived from that medium’s early limitations: no sound, no color, no three-dimensional (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics.[author unknown] - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203):280-282.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Attributability, Answerability, and Accountability: Toward a Wider Theory of Moral Responsibility.David Shoemaker - 2011 - Ethics 121 (3):602-632.
    Recently T. M. Scanlon and others have advanced an ostensibly comprehensive theory of moral responsibility—a theory of both being responsible and being held responsible—that best accounts for our moral practices. I argue that both aspects of the Scanlonian theory fail this test. A truly comprehensive theory must incorporate and explain three distinct conceptions of responsibility—attributability, answerability, and accountability—and the Scanlonian view conflates the first two and ignores the importance of the third. To illustrate what a truly comprehensive theory might look (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • Does Moral Virtue Constitute a Benefit to the Agent?Brad Hooker - 1996 - In Roger Crisp (ed.), How Should One Live?: Essays on the Virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Theories of individual well‐being fall into three main categories: hedonism, the desire‐fulfilment theory, and the list theory (which maintains that there are some things that can benefit a person without increasing the person's pleasure or desire‐fulfilment). The paper briefly explains the answers that hedonism and the desire‐fulfilment theory give to the question of whether being virtuous constitutes a benefit to the agent. Most of the paper is about the list theory's answer.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Virtue, Vice and Value.Thomas Hurka - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (208):413-415.
  • Self-interpreting animals. 45-76 in: TAYLOR, Charles: Human agency and language.Charles Taylor - 1985 - Philosophical Papers 1.
  • Death.John Martin Fischer - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Evaluating Emotional Responses to Fiction.Paisley Livingston & Alfred Mele - 1997 - In Mette Hjort & Sue Laver (eds.), Emotion and the Arts. Oup Usa.
    Philosophical discussion of emotional responses to fiction has been dominated by work on the paradox of fiction, which is often construed as asking whether and how we can experience genuine emotions in reaction to fiction. One may also ask more generally how we ought to respond to fictional works, a question that has to do both with what we should do when reacting to fiction and with what we should and should not let happen to us. It is possible to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The art of videogames.Grant Tavinor - 2009 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    The new art of videogames -- What are videogames anyway? -- On definition -- Theories of gaming -- A definition of videogames -- Videogames and fiction -- From tennis for two to worlds of warcraft -- Imaginary worlds and works of fiction -- Fictional or virtual? -- Interactive fiction -- Stepping into fictional worlds -- Welcome to rapture -- Meet niko bellic -- Experiencing game worlds -- Acting in game worlds -- Games through fiction -- The nature of gaming -- (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Just joking: The ethics and aesthetics of humor.Berys Nigel Gaut - 1998 - Philosophy and Literature 22 (1):51-68.
  • Film as Art, 50th Anniversary Printing.Rudolf Arnheim - 1957 - University of California Press.
    In the fall of 1957 the University of California Press expanded Arnheim’s 1933 book _Film_ by four essays and brought that landmark work back into print as _Film as Art._ Now nearly fifty years after that re-edition, the book continues to occupy an important place in the literature of film. Arnheim’s method, provocative in this age of technological wizardry, was to focus on the way art in film was derived from that medium’s early limitations: no sound, no color, no three-dimensional (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Harm to Others.Joel Feinberg - 1984 - Oxford University Press USA.
    This first volume in the four-volume series The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law focuses on the "harm principle," the commonsense view that prevention of harm to persons other than the perpetrator is a legitimate purpose of criminal legislation. Feinberg presents a detailed analysis of the concept and definition of harm and applies it to a host of practical and theoretical issues, showing how the harm principle must be interpreted if it is to be a plausible guide to the lawmaker.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Horror Films and the Argument from Reactive Attitudes.Scott Woodcock - 2013 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (2):309-324.
    Are horror films immoral? Gianluca Di Muzio argues that horror films of a certain kind are immoral because they undermine the reactive attitudes that are responsible for human agents being disposed to respond compassionately to instances of victimization. I begin with this argument as one instance of what I call the Argument from Reactive Attitudes (ARA), and I argue that Di Muzio’s attempt to identify what is morally suspect about horror films must be revised to provide the most persuasive interpretation (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Morals in Fiction and Fictional Morality (I).Kendall Lewis Walton - 2015 [1994] - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 68:27-50.
  • Morals in Fiction and Fictional Morality.Kendall L. Walton & Michael Tanner - 1994 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 68 (1):27-66.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Fearing fictions.Kendall L. Walton - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (1):5-27.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Horror, or Paradoxes of the Heart.Jerrold Levinson - 1991 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (3):253-258.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Friendship, Altruism, and Morality.Laurence Thomas - 1983 - Philosophical Review 92 (1):135.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Justifying the emotions.G. Taylor - 1975 - Mind 84 (July):390-402.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Regarding the pain of others.Susan Sontag - 2003 - Diogène 201 (1):127-.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art.Robert Stecker - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (3):379-381.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The feels good theory of pleasure.Aaron Smuts - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 155 (2):241-265.
    Most philosophers since Sidgwick have thought that the various forms of pleasure differ so radically that one cannot find a common, distinctive feeling among them. This is known as the heterogeneity problem. To get around this problem, the motivational theory of pleasure suggests that what makes an experience one of pleasure is our reaction to it, not something internal to the experience. I argue that the motivational theory is wrong, and not only wrong, but backwards. The heterogeneity problem is the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Art and negative affect.Aaron Smuts - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (1):39-55.
    Why do people seemingly want to be scared by movies and feel pity for fictional characters when they avoid situations in real life that arouse these same negative emotions? Although the domain of relevant artworks encompasses far more than just tragedy, the general problem is typically called the paradox of tragedy. The paradox boils down to a simple question: If people avoid pain then why do people want to experience art that is painful? I discuss six popular solutions to the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Caring, identification, and agency.David W. Shoemaker - 2003 - Ethics 114 (1):88-118.
    This paper articulates and defends a noncognitive, care-based view of identification, of what privileged psychic subset provides the source of self-determination in actions and attitudes. The author provides an extended analysis of "caring," and then applies it to debates between Frankfurtians, on the one hand, and Watsonians, on the other, about the nature of identification, then defends the view against objections.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • The Appeal of Utilitarianism.Robert Shaver - 2004 - Utilitas 16 (3):235-250.
    Utilitarianism continues to vex its critics even in the absence of generally respected arguments in its favour. I suggest that utilitarianism survives largely because of its welfarism. This explains why it survives without the backing of respected arguments. It survives without such arguments because justifying the value of welfare requires no such argument.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Why we are responsible for our emotions.Eugene Schlossberger - 1986 - Mind 95 (377):37-56.
    It is often said that one cannot be held responsible for something one cannot help. Indeed, Ted Honderich, Paul Edwards, and C. A. Campbell have suggested that it is obtuse, barbaric, or a solecism to think otherwise 1. Thus, if (contra Sartre and others) one cannot help feeling one's emotions, one is not responsible for one's emotions. In this paper I will argue otherwise; one is responsible for one's emotions, even if one cannot help feeling them. 2 In particular, I (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Responsibility and the problem of induced desires.Ferdinand Schoeman - 1978 - Philosophical Studies 34 (3):293 - 301.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Ought, Agents, and Actions.Mark Schroeder - 2010 - Philosophical Review 119 (3):1-41.
    According to a naive view sometimes apparent in the writings of moral philosophers, 'ought' often expresses a relation between agents and actions—the relation that obtains between an agent and an action when that action is what that agent ought to do. It is not part of this naive view that 'ought' always expresses this relation—adherents of the naive view are happy to allow that 'ought' also has an evaluative sense, on which it means, roughly, that were things ideal, some proposition (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Ought, Agents, and Actions.Mark Schroeder - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (1):1-41.
    According to a naïve view sometimes apparent in the writings of moral philosophers, ‘ought’ often expresses a relation between agents and actions – the relation that obtains between an agent and an action when that action is what that agent ought to do. It is not part of this naïve view that ‘ought’ always expresses this relation – on the contrary, adherents of the naïve view are happy to allow that ‘ought’ also has an epistemic sense, on which it means, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Fiction and the suspension of disbelief.Eva Schaper - 1978 - British Journal of Aesthetics 18 (1):31-44.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Responsibility of Persons for Their Emotions.Edward Sankowski - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (4):829 - 840.
    We sometimes blame persons, and we sometimes give them credit for the emotions they feel. We could, for example, speak of feeling hatred, resentment or envy as “reprehensible” in suitable circumstances, or say “He's to blame for feeling that way.” We could speak of feeling sympathy, affection or indignation as “commendable” in suitable circumstances, or say “He deserves credit for feeling that way.” And it is not just that we are assessing such emotion as somehow good or bad — in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Love and moral obligation.Edward Sankowski - 1978 - Journal of Value Inquiry 12 (2):100-110.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • What an emotion is: A sketch.Robert C. Roberts - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (April):183-209.
  • How Can We Be Moved by the Fate of Anna Karenina.Colin Radford & Michael Weston - 1975 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 49 (1):67 - 93.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Fiction, pity, fear, and jealousy.Colin Radford - 1995 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1):71-75.
  • Belief and Will.H. H. Price - 1954 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 28 (1):1-26.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Self-interest and the Concept of Self-sacrifice.Mark Carl Overvold - 1980 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):105-118.
    Owing to a genral dissatisfaction with hedonistic theories of value, a number of recent discussions have sought to identify an agent's selfinterest, individual utility, or personal welfare with what the agent most wants to do, all things considered. Two features of these accounts merit special attention for the argument in this paper. First, on such accounts any desire or aversion which persists in the face of complete information is logically relevant to the determination of an agent's self interest. This includes (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Morality and the emotions.Justin Oakley - 1992 - New York: Routledge.
    Introduction In recent years there has been a welcome reawakening of philosophical interest in the emotions. A significant number of contemporary ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Morality and the Emotions.Justin Oakley - 1992 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 56 (3):598-600.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Welfarism – The Very Idea.Nils Holtug - 2003 - Utilitas 15 (2):151.
    According to outcome welfarism, roughly, the value of an outcome is fundamentally a matterof the individual welfare it contains. I assess various suggestions as to how to spell out this idea more fully on the basis of some basic intuitions about the content and implications of welfarism. I point out that what are in fact different suggestions are often conflated and argue that none fully captures the basic intuitions. I then suggest that what this means is that different doctrines of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Death.Thomas Nagel - 1970 - Noûs 4 (1):73-80.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   246 citations  
  • The expression of feeling in imagination.Richard Moran - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (1):75-106.
  • Welfarism in moral theory.Andrew Moore & Roger Crisp - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (4):598 – 613.
    We take welfarism in moral theory to be the claim that the well-being of individuals matters and is the only consideration that fundamentally matters, from a moral point of view. We argue that criticisms of welfarism due to G.E. Moore, Donald Regan, Charles Taylor and Amartya Sen all fail. The final section of our paper is a critical survey of the problems which remain for welfarists in moral theory.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Principia Ethica.Evander Bradley McGilvary - 1904 - Philosophical Review 13 (3):351.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   575 citations  
  • On being immoral in a dream.Gareth B. Matthews - 1981 - Philosophy 56 (January):47-64.
    What is often called Descartes' dream problem should perhaps be called Plato's dream problem instead. Certainly it can be found in Plato's Theaetetus at 158b–c. It can also be found in Cicero and, through Cicero's influence, in much of the work of St Augustine.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The nature of pleasure: A critique of Feldman.Elinor Mason - 2007 - Utilitas 19 (3):379-387.
    In these remarks on Feldman's recent book, Pleasure and the Good Life, I concentrate on Feldman's account of pleasure as attitudinal. I argue that an account of pleasure according to which pleasure need not have any feel is implausible. I suggest that Feldman could avoid this problem but retain the advantages of his attitudinal hedonism by giving an account of the attitude such that the attitude has a feel.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Aesthetics of Photographic Transparency.Dominic McIver Lopes - 2003 - Mind 112 (447):434--48.
    When we look at photographs we literally see the objects that they are of. But seeing photographs as photographs engages aesthetic interests that are not engaged by seeing the objects that they are of. These claims appear incompatible. Sceptics about photography as an art form have endorsed the first claim in order to show that there is no photographic aesthetic. Proponents of photography as an art form have insisted that seeing things in photographs is quite unlike seeing things face-to-face. This (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Is violation pornography bad for your soul?Stephen Kershnar - 2004 - Journal of Social Philosophy 35 (3):349–366.
    Violation pornography is pornography where the depicted behavior includes unjust sexual acts, e.g., rape. In this paper I argue that it is unclear whether the enjoyment of violation pornography is bad for the viewer. My essay has three parts. First, I set out an account of flourishing. I adopt a composite account, whereby flourishing is a function of the degree to which an individual has pleasure and various objective-list elements. Objective-list elements are things (e.g., knowledge and meaningful relationships) that make (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Welfarism.Simon Keller - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (1):82-95.
    Welfarism is the view that morality is centrally concerned with the welfare or well-being of individuals. The division between welfarist and non-welfarist approaches underlies many important disagreements in ethics, but welfarism is neither consistently defined nor well understood. I survey the philosophical work on welfarism, and I offer a suggestion about how the view can be characterized and how it can be embedded in various kinds of moral theory. I also identify welfarism's major rivals, and its major attractions and weaknesses.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Rational fear of monsters.R. Joyce - 2000 - British Journal of Aesthetics 40 (2):209-224.
    Colin Radford must weary of defending his thesis that the emotional reactions we have towards fictional characters, events, and states of affairs are irrational.1 Yet, for all the discussion, the issue has not, to my mind, been properly settled—or at least not settled in the manner I should prefer—and so this paper attempts once more to debunk Radford’s defiance of common sense. For some, the question of whether our emotional responses to fiction are rational does not arise, for they are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations