Switch to: Citations

References in:

Is it Better to Love Better Things?

In Tony Milligan, Christian Maurer & Kamila Pacovská (eds.), Love and Its Objects (2015)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Subtlety of Emotions.[author unknown] - 2001 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 63 (4):810-811.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Virtue, Vice and Value.Thomas Hurka - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (208):413-415.
  • A theory of justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4021 citations  
  • Love and history.Christopher Grau - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 48 (3):246-271.
    In this essay, I argue that a proper understanding of the historicity of love requires an appreciation of the irreplaceability of the beloved. I do this through a consideration of ideas that were first put forward by Robert Kraut in “Love De Re” (1986). I also evaluate Amelie Rorty's criticisms of Kraut's thesis in “The Historicity of Psychological Attitudes: Love is Not Love Which Alters Not When It Alteration Finds” (1986). I argue that Rorty fundamentally misunderstands Kraut's Kripkean analogy, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Nature of Love: Plato to Luther.Irving Singer - 1984 - Chicago: MIT Press.
    An analysis of concepts of bestowal, appraisal, imagination, and idealization followed by explorations into the writings of thinkers that include Plato, Ovid, ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • What we owe to each other.Thomas Scanlon - 1998 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    In this book, T. M. Scanlon offers new answers to these questions, as they apply to the central part of morality that concerns what we owe to each other.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2440 citations  
  • Love De Re.Robert Kraut - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):413-430.
  • Self-interpreting animals. 45-76 in: TAYLOR, Charles: Human agency and language.Charles Taylor - 1985 - Philosophical Papers 1.
  • Reply to Susan Wolf.Harry Frankfurt - 2002 - In Sarah Buss & Lee Overton (eds.), Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes From Harry Frankfurt. MIT Press, Bradford Books. pp. 248--249.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Caring and incapacity.Jeffrey Seidman - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 147 (2):301 - 322.
    This essay seeks to explain a morally important class of psychological incapacity—the class of what Bernard Williams has called “incapacities of character.” I argue for two main claims: (1) Caring is the underlying psychological disposition that gives rise to incapacities of character. (2) In competent, rational adults, caring is, in part, a cognitive and deliberative disposition. Caring is a mental state which disposes an agent to believe certain considerations to be good reasons for deliberation and action. And caring is a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Can Animals Be Moral?Mark Rowlands - 2012 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Can animals act morally? Philosophical tradition answers 'no,' and has apparently convincing arguments on its side. Cognitive ethology supplies a growing body of empirical evidence that suggests these arguments are wrong. This groundbreaking book assimilates both philosophical and ethological frameworks into a unified whole and argues for a qualified 'yes.'.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • The Speech of Alcibiades: A Reading of Plato's Symposium.Martha Nussbaum - 1979 - Philosophy and Literature 3 (2):131-172.
  • The Speech of Alcibiades: A Reading of Plato's Symposium.Martha Nussbaum - 1979 - Philosophy and Literature 3 (2):131-172.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • 3. The Importance of Free Will.Susan Wolf - 1993 - In John Martin Fischer & Mark Ravizza (eds.), Perspectives on Moral Responsibility. Cornell University Press. pp. 101-118.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The importance of free will.Susan Wolf - 1981 - Mind 90 (February):366-78.
  • Meaning in Life and Why It Matters.Susan Wolf - 2010 - Princeton University Press.
    Most people, including philosophers, tend to classify human motives as falling into one of two categories: the egoistic or the altruistic, the self-interested or the moral. According to Susan Wolf, however, much of what motivates us does not comfortably fit into this scheme. Often we act neither for our own sake nor out of duty or an impersonal concern for the world. Rather, we act out of love for objects that we rightly perceive as worthy of love--and it is these (...)
  • Morality and partiality.Susan Wolf - 1992 - Philosophical Perspectives 6:243-259.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Love as a moral emotion.J. David Velleman - 1999 - Ethics 109 (2):338-374.
  • Love.Gabriele Taylor - 1976 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76:147 - 164.
    Gabriele Taylor; VIII*—Love, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 76, Issue 1, 1 June 1976, Pages 147–164, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/76.1.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Justifying the emotions.G. Taylor - 1975 - Mind 84 (July):390-402.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Joke is the Thing: 'In the Company of Men' and the Ethics of Humor.Aaron Smuts - 2007 - Film and Philosophy 11:49-66.
    Any analysis of "In the Company of Men" is forced to answer three questions of central importance to the ethics of humor: What does it mean to find sexist humor funny? What are the various sources of humor? And, can moral flaws with attempts at humor increase their humorousness? I argued that although merely finding a joke funny in a neutral context cannot tell you anything reliable about a person's beliefs, in context, a joke may reveal a great deal about (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Nature of Love: Plato to Luther.Irving Singer - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (4):519-521.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Caring, identification, and agency.David W. Shoemaker - 2003 - Ethics 114 (1):88-118.
    This paper articulates and defends a noncognitive, care-based view of identification, of what privileged psychic subset provides the source of self-determination in actions and attitudes. The author provides an extended analysis of "caring," and then applies it to debates between Frankfurtians, on the one hand, and Watsonians, on the other, about the nature of identification, then defends the view against objections.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • The Foundations of Character.E. S. P. Haynes - 1915 - International Journal of Ethics 25 (2):268-270.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Foundations of Character. Being a Study of the Tendencies of the Emotions and Sentiments. [REVIEW]William K. Wright - 1914 - Philosophical Review 23 (5):561-565.
  • Valuing and caring.Jeffrey Seidman - 2009 - Theoria 75 (4):272-303.
    What is it to "value" something, in the semi-technical sense of the term that Gary Watson establishes? I argue that valuing something consists in caring about it. Caring involves not only emotional dispositions of the sort that Agnieszka Jaworska has elaborated, but also a distinctive cognitive disposition – namely, a (defeasible) disposition to believe the object cared about to be a source of agent-relative reasons for action and for emotion. Understood in this way, an agent's carings have a stronger claim (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Teleology, agent‐relative value, and 'good'.Mark Schroeder - 2007 - Ethics 117 (2):265-000.
    It is now generally understood that constraints play an important role in commonsense moral thinking and generally accepted that they cannot be accommodated by ordinary, traditional consequentialism. Some have seen this as the most conclusive evidence that consequentialism is hopelessly wrong,1 while others have seen it as the most conclusive evidence that moral common sense is hopelessly paradoxical.2 Fortunately, or so it is widely thought, in the last twenty-five years a new research program, that of Agent-Relative Teleology, has come to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Ought, Agents, and Actions.Mark Schroeder - 2010 - Philosophical Review 119 (3):1-41.
    According to a naive view sometimes apparent in the writings of moral philosophers, 'ought' often expresses a relation between agents and actions—the relation that obtains between an agent and an action when that action is what that agent ought to do. It is not part of this naive view that 'ought' always expresses this relation—adherents of the naive view are happy to allow that 'ought' also has an evaluative sense, on which it means, roughly, that were things ideal, some proposition (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Ought, Agents, and Actions.Mark Schroeder - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (1):1-41.
    According to a naïve view sometimes apparent in the writings of moral philosophers, ‘ought’ often expresses a relation between agents and actions – the relation that obtains between an agent and an action when that action is what that agent ought to do. It is not part of this naïve view that ‘ought’ always expresses this relation – on the contrary, adherents of the naïve view are happy to allow that ‘ought’ also has an epistemic sense, on which it means, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Explaining Emotions.Amélie Rorty (ed.) - 1980 - University of California Press.
    The philosopher must inform himself of the relevant empirical investigation to arrive at a definition, and the scientist cannot afford to be naive about the..
  • Explaining emotions.Amelie Oksenberg Rorty - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (March):139-161.
    The challenge of explaining the emotions has engaged the attention of the best minds in philosophy and science throughout history. Part of the fascination has been that the emotions resist classification. As adequate account therefore requires receptivity to knowledge from a variety of sources. The philosopher must inform himself of the relevant empirical investigation to arrive at a definition, and the scientist cannot afford to be naive about the assumptions built into his conceptual apparatus. The contributors to this volume have (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • What an emotion is: A sketch.Robert C. Roberts - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (April):183-209.
  • Deeper Than Reason: Emotion and its Role in Literature, Music, and Art.Jenefer Robinson - 2005 - Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press.
    Jenefer Robinson takes the insights of modern scientific research on the emotions and uses them to illuminate questions about our emotional involvement with the arts. Laying out a theory of emotion supported by the best evidence from current empirical work, she examines some of the ways in which the emotions function in the arts. Written in a clear and engaging style, her book will make fascinating reading for anyone interested in the emotions and how they work, as well as anyone (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • Emotion.George Pitcher - 1965 - Mind 74 (July):326-346.
  • Loyalties.Andrew Oldenquist - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (4):173-193.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • A Dispositional Theory of Love.Hichem Naar - 2013 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94 (3):342-357.
    On a naive reading of the major accounts of love, love is a kind of mental event. A recent trend in the philosophical literature on love is to reject these accounts on the basis that they do not do justice to the historical dimension of love, as love essentially involves a distinctive kind of temporally extended pattern. Although the historicist account has advantages over the positions that it opposes, its appeal to the notion of a pattern is problematic. I will (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The logic, intentionality, and phenomenology of emotion.Michelle Montague - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 145 (2):171-192.
    My concern in this paper is with the intentionality of emotions. Desires and cognitions are the traditional paradigm cases of intentional attitudes, and one very direct approach to the question of the intentionality of emotions is to treat it as sui generis—as on a par with the intentionality of desires and cognitions but in no way reducible to it. A more common approach seeks to reduce the intentionality of emotions to the intentionality of familiar intentional attitudes like desires and cognitions. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Against propositionalism.Michelle Montague - 2007 - Noûs 41 (3):503–518.
    'Propositionalism' is the widely held view that all intentional mental relations-all intentional attitudes-are relations to propositions or something proposition-like. Paradigmatically, to think about the mountain is ipso facto to think that it is F, for some predicate 'F'. It seems, however, many intentional attitudes are not relations to propositions at all: Mary contemplates Jonah, adores New York, misses Athens, mourns her brother. I argue, following Brentano, Husserl, Church and Montague among others, that the way things seem is the way they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Persons as Objects of Love.Ty Landrum - 2009 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (4):417-439.
    Recent attempts to view personal love as a response to value fail to capture the lover's distinctive compulsion to intimacy with the beloved. Their common mistake is to hold that the grounding value of love must be other than the beloved person herself. This view condemns theorists to describe an attachment comparatively impersonal and undiscerning. The present paper argues that the beloved person is the object of love, particularly when she is regarded in light of her virtues. Virtues are aspects (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Which relationships justify partiality? The case of parents and children.Niko Kolodny - 2010 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 38 (1):37-75.
  • Love as valuing a relationship.Niko Kolodny - 2003 - Philosophical Review 112 (2):135-189.
    At first glance, love seems to be a psychological state for which there are normative reasons: a state that, if all goes well, is an appropriate or fitting response to something independent of itself. Love for one’s parent, child, or friend is fitting, one wants to say, if anything is. On reflection, however, it is elusive what reasons for love might be. It is natural to assume that they would be nonrelational features of the person one loves, something about her (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   213 citations  
  • Love as a reactive emotion.Adam Leite Kate Abramson - 2011 - Philosophical Quarterly 61 (245):673-699.
    One variety of love is familiar in everyday life and qualifies in every reasonable sense as a reactive attitude. ‘Reactive love’ is paradigmatically an affectionate attachment to another person, appropriately felt as a non‐self‐interested response to particular kinds of morally laudable features of character expressed by the loved one in interaction with the lover, and paradigmatically manifested in certain kinds of acts of goodwill and characteristic affective, desiderative and other motivational responses . ‘Virtues of intimacy’ as expressed in interaction with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Love’s Vision.Troy Jollimore - 2011 - Princeton University Press.
    "Something in between : on the nature of love" -- Love's blindness (1) : love's closed heart -- Love's blindness (2) : love's friendly eye -- Beyond comparison -- Commitments, values, and frameworks -- Valuing persons -- Love and morality -- Afterword. Between the universal and the particular.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Friendship without partiality?Troy Jollimore - 2000 - Ratio 13 (1):69–82.
    Consequentialism involves a kind of strong impartiality which seems incompatible with the sort of partiality manifested in friendships. Consequentialists such as Kagan respond that friendship does not, in fact, require partiality. Against this, I argue that friendship cannot exist without expressions of personal feeling, and that such expressions necessarily involve a kind of partiality. Because her every action is determined by the goal of maximizing the impersonal good, a consequentialist cannot use her actions (including actions of speech) to express her (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Friendship, virtue, and impartiality.Diane Jeske - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1):51-72.
    The two dominant contemporary moral theories, Kantianism and utilitarianism, have difficulty accommodating our commonsense understanding of friendship as a relationship with significant moral implications. The difficulty seems to arise from their underlying commitment to impartiality, to the claim that all persons are equally worthy of concern. Aristotelian accounts of friendship are partialist in so far as they defend certain types of friendship by appeal to the claim that some persons, the virtuous, are in fact more worthy of concern than are (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Friendship, Virtue, and Impartiality.Diane Jeske - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1):51-72.
    The two dominant contemporary moral theories, Kantianism and utilitarianism, have difficulty accommodating our commonsense understanding of friendship as a relationship with significant moral implications. The difficulty seems to arise from their underlying commitment to impartiality, to the claim that all persons are equally worthy of concern. Aristotelian accounts of friendship are partialist in so far as they defend certain types of friendship by appeal to the claim that some persons, the virtuous, are in fact more worthy of concern than are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Caring and full moral standing.Agnieszka Jaworska - 2007 - Ethics 117 (3):460-497.
    A being has moral standing if it or its interests matter intrinsically, to at least some degree, in the moral assessment of actions and events. For instance, animals can be said to have moral standing if, other things being equal, it is morally bad to intentionally cause their suffering. This essay focuses on a special kind of moral standing, what I will call “full moral standing” (FMS), associated with persons. In contrast to the var- ious accounts of what ultimately grounds (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Caring and Internality.Agnieszka Jaworska - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (3):529-568.
    In his work on internality, identification, and caring, Harry Frankfurt attempts to delineate the organization of agency peculiar to human beings, while avoiding the traditional overintellectualized emphasis on the human capacity to reason about action. The focal point of Frankfurt’s alternative picture is our capacity to make our own motivation the object of reflection. Building upon the observation that marginal agents (such as young children and Alzheimer’s patients) are capable of caring, I show that neither caring nor internality need to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Value and friendship: A more subtle view.Thomas Hurka - 2006 - Utilitas 18 (3):232-242.
    T. M. Scanlon has cited the value of friendship in arguing against a ‘teleological’ view of value which says that value inheres only in states of affairs and demands only that we promote it. This article argues that, whatever the teleological view's final merits, the case against it cannot be made on the basis of friendship. The view can capture Scanlon's claims about friendship if it holds, as it can consistently with its basic ideas, that (i) friendship is a higher-level (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Character traits and desires.Stephen D. Hudson - 1980 - Ethics 90 (4):539-549.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations