Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Bestiary of the Manifest Image.Daniel C. Dennett - 2013 - In Don Ross, James Ladyman & Harold Kincaid (eds.), Scientific metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 96.
  • A case for extrinsic dispositions.Jennifer McKitrick - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2):155 – 174.
    Many philosophers think that dispositions are necessarily intrinsic. However, there are no good positive arguments for this view. Furthermore, many properties (such as weight, visibility, and vulnerability) are dispositional but are not necessarily shared by perfect duplicates. So, some dispositions are extrinsic. I consider three main objections to the possibility of extrinsic dispositions: the Objection from Relationally Specified Properties, the Objection from Underlying Intrinsic Properties, and the Objection from Natural Properties. These objections ultimately fail.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • The Metaphysics of Beauty.Nick Zangwill - 2001 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    In chapters ranging from "The Beautiful, the Dainty, and the Dumpy" to "Skin-deep or In the Eye of the Beholder?" Nick Zangwill investigates the nature of beauty as we conceive it, and as it is in itself. The notion of beauty is currently attracting increased interest, particularly in philosophical aesthetics and in discussions of our experiences and judgments about art. In The Metaphysics of Beauty, Zangwill argues that it is essential to beauty that it depends on the ordinary features of (...)
  • Response-dependence about aesthetic value.Michael Watkins & James Shelley - 2012 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93 (3):338-352.
    The dominant view about the nature of aesthetic value holds it to be response-dependent. We believe that the dominance of this view owes largely to some combination of the following prevalent beliefs: 1 The belief that challenges brought against response-dependent accounts in other areas of philosophy are less challenging when applied to response-dependent accounts of aesthetic value. 2 The belief that aesthetic value is instrumental and that response-dependence about aesthetic value alone accommodates this purported fact. 3 The belief that response-dependence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Dispositions without Conditionals.Barbara Vetter - 2014 - Mind 123 (489):129-156.
    Dispositions are modal properties. The standard conception of dispositions holds that each disposition is individuated by its stimulus condition(s) and its manifestation(s), and that their modality is best captured by some conditional construction that relates stimulus to manifestation as antecedent to consequent. I propose an alternative conception of dispositions: each disposition is individuated by its manifestation alone, and its modality is closest to that of possibility — a fragile vase, for instance, is one that can break easily. The view is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Perceptual Knowledge of Nonactual Possibilities.Margot Strohminger - 2015 - Philosophical Perspectives 29 (1):363-375.
    It is widely assumed that sense perception cannot deliver knowledge of nonactual (metaphysical) possibilities. We are not supposed to be able to know that a proposition p is necessary or that p is possible (if p is false) by sense perception. This paper aims to establish that the role of sense perception is not so limited. It argues that we can know lots of modal facts by perception. While the most straightforward examples concern possibility and contingency, others concern necessity and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • How can we discover the contents of experience?Susanna Siegel - 2007 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 45 (S1):127-42.
    In this paper I discuss several proposals for how to find out which contents visual experiences have, and I defend the method I.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • How Can We Discover the Contents of Experience?Susanna Siegel - 2007 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 45 (S1):127-142.
    How can we discover the contents of experience? I argue that neither introspection alone nor naturalistic theories of experience content are sufficient to discover these contents. I propose another method of discovery: the method of phenomenal contrast. I defend the method against skeptics who doubt that the contents of experience can be discovered, and I explain how the method may be employed even if one denies that experiences have contents.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Aesthetic Concepts.Frank Sibley - 1959 - Philosophical Review 68 (4):421-450.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   187 citations  
  • Art and Imagination: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind.B. R. Tilghman - 1975 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 34 (1):75-77.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Art and Imagination: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind.Reuben Abel - 1975 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (1):134-135.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • When Critics Disagree: Prospects for Realism in Aesthetics.S. Ross - 2014 - Philosophical Quarterly 64 (257):590-618.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Dispositions.Edward Craig - 1987 - Philosophical Quarterly 37 (146):109-111.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Only a Promise of Happiness: The Place of Beauty in a World of Art. [REVIEW]Monique Roelofs - 2007 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (4):399-401.
  • Jerrold Levinson.Derek Matravers & Jerrold Levinson - 2005 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1):211–227.
  • II—Jerrold Levinson.Derek Matravers - 2005 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79 (1):211-227.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Aesthetic Properties.Derek Matravers - 2005 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1):191-210.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Aesthetic Concepts.Derek Matravers - 2005 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79 (1):191-210.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Derek Matravers.Derek Matravers & Jerrold Levinson - 2005 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1):191–210.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Dispositions and conditionals.C. B. Martin - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (174):1-8.
  • On linking dispositions and conditionals.David Manley & Ryan Wasserman - 2008 - Mind 117 (465):59-84.
    Analyses of dispositional ascriptions in terms of conditional statements famously confront the problems of finks and masks. We argue that conditional analyses of dispositions, even those tailored to avoid finks and masks, face five further problems. These are the problems of: (i) Achilles' heels, (ii) accidental closeness, (iii) comparatives, (iv) explaining context sensitivity, and (v) absent stimulus conditions. We conclude by offering a proposal that avoids all seven of these problems.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • Finkish dispositions.David Kellogg Lewis - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (187):143-158.
    Many years ago, C.B. Martin drew our attention to the possibility of ‘finkish’ dispositions: dispositions which, if put to the test would not be manifested, but rather would disappear. Thus if x if finkishly disposed to give response r to stimulus s, it is not so that if x were subjected to stimulus r, x would give response z; so finkish dispositions afford a counter‐example to the simplest conditional analysis of dispositions. Martin went on to suggest that finkish dispositions required (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   410 citations  
  • II_— _Jerrold Levinson.Jerrold Levinson - 2005 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1):211-227.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hume's standard of taste: The real problem.Jerrold Levinson - 2002 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60 (3):227–238.
  • Belief, Truth and Knowledge.Peter D. Klein - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (2):225.
  • Hume's standard of taste: Breaking the circle.Peter Kivy - 1967 - British Journal of Aesthetics 7 (1):57-66.
  • How to speak of the colors.Mark Johnston - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 68 (3):221-263.
  • The Objective Eye: Color, Form, and Reality in the Theory of Art.Zed Adams - 2007 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65 (4):417-419.
  • How to Be a Pessimist about Aesthetic Testimony.Robert Hopkins - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy 108 (3):138-157.
    Is testimony a legitimate source of aesthetic belief? Can I, for instance, learn that a film is excellent on your say-so? Optimists say yes, pessimists no. But pessimism comes in two forms. One claims that testimony is not a legitimate source of aesthetic belief because it cannot yield aesthetic knowledge. The other accepts that testimony can be a source of aesthetic knowledge, yet insists that some further norm prohibits us from exploiting that resource. I argue that this second form of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Aesthetic Value. [REVIEW]David E. Cooper - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):490-492.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Aesthetic Value.B. R. Tilghman - 1999 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (1):81-82.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Participatory Imagining and the Explanation of Living-Presence Response.J. Gaiger - 2011 - British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (4):363-381.
    This paper has two aims. First, I seek to show that Kendall Walton's analysis of the participatory character of our imaginative engagement in games of make-believe provides a powerful explanatory framework that can be used to address some of the central problems that still remain unresolved in contemporary accounts of living-presence response, including those put forward by David Freedberg and Alfred Gell. Second, I argue that Walton's focus on the activities of ‘appreciators’ prevents him from considering the possible application of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Matters of Metaphysics.Alex Byrne & D. H. Mellor - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (2):285.
  • The acquaintance principle.Malcolm Budd - 2003 - British Journal of Aesthetics 43 (4):386-392.
    The Acquaintance Principle maintains that aesthetic knowledge must be acquired through first-hand experience of the object of knowledge and cannot be transmitted from person to person. This implies that aesthetic knowledge of an object cannot be acquired either from an accurate description of the non- aesthetic features of the object or from reliable testimony of its aesthetic character. The question I address is whether there is any sound argument in support of the Principle. I give scant consideration to the possibility (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Color as a secondary quality.Paul A. Boghossian & J. David Velleman - 1989 - Mind 98 (January):81-103.
    Should a principle of charity be applied to the interpretation of the colour concepts exercised in visual experience? We think not. We shall argue, for one thing, that the grounds for applying a principle of charity are lacking in the case of colour concepts. More importantly, we shall argue that attempts at giving the experience of colour a charitable interpretation either fail to respect obvious features of that experience or fail to interpret it charitably, after all. Charity to visual experience (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   267 citations  
  • Dispositions and antidotes.Alexander Bird - 1998 - Philosophical Quarterly 48 (191):227-234.
    In ‘Finkish Dispositions’1 David Lewis proposes an analysis of dispositions which improves on the simple conditional analysis. In this paper I show that Lewis’ analysis still fails. I also argue that repairs are of no avail, and suggest why this is so.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   253 citations  
  • Three theses about dispositions.Elizabeth W. Prior, Robert Pargetter & Frank Jackson - 1982 - American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (3):251-257.
    I. Causal Thesis: Dispositions have a causal basis. II. Distinctness Thesis: Dispositions are distinct from their causal basis. III. Impotence Thesis: Dispositions are not causally active.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Hume and the Paradox of Taste.Mary Mothersill - 1989 - In G. Dickie (ed.), Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology. St. Martin's.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • It's a Colorful World.Anna Marmodoro - 2006 - American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (1):71 - 80.
    Abstract: I defend the intuition that the phenomenology of our experience is right in attributing the colors we see to objects; but although colors are properties of objects, they are constitutively dependent on the perceiver’s experiences. I offer a metaphysical account for this primitivist intuition, in response to David Chalmers’ arguments against it, drawing inspiration from Aristotle’s theory of causation.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Color relationalism and color phenomenology.Jonathan Cohen - 2010 - In Bence Nanay (ed.), Perceiving the World. Oxford University Press. pp. 13.
    Color relationalism is the view that colors are constituted in terms of relations between subjects and objects. The most historically important form of color relationalism is the classic dispositionalist view according to which, for example red is the disposition to look red to standard observers in standard conditions (mutatis mutandis for other colors).1 However, it has become increasingly apparent in recent years that a commitment to the relationality of colors bears interest that goes beyond dispositionalism (Cohen, 2004; Matthen, 1999, 2001, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Powers: A Study in Metaphysics.George Molnar & Stephen Mumford - 2005 - Philosophical Quarterly 55 (221):674-677.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • Matters of Metaphysics.D. H. MELLOR - 1991 - Philosophy 67 (260):268-270.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Art and Imagination: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind.Roger Scruton - 1977 - Mind 86 (341):151-154.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Powers: A Study in Metaphysics.George Molnar & Stephen Mumford - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2):485-487.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   155 citations