Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Review. [REVIEW]John Worrall - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (4):279-295.
  • Reconsidering Feyerabend’s “Anarchism‘.Jonathan Y. Tsou - 2003 - Perspectives on Science 11 (2):208-235.
    This paper explores Paul Feyerabend's (1924-1994) skeptical arguments for "anarchism" in his early writings between 1960 to 1975. Feyerabend's position is encapsulated by his well-known suggestion that the only principle for scientific method that can be defended under all circumstances is: "anything goes." I present Feyerabend's anarchism as a recommendation for pluralism that assumes a realist view of scientific theories. The aims of this paper are threefold: (1) to present a defensible view of Feyerabend's anarchism and its motivations, (2) to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Unconceived alternatives and conservatism in science: the impact of professionalization, peer-review, and Big Science.P. Kyle Stanford - 2015 - Synthese:1-18.
    Scientific realists have suggested that changes in our scientific communities over the course of their history have rendered those communities progressively less vulnerable to the problem of unconcieved alternatives over time. I argue in response not only that the most fundamental historical transformations of the scientific enterprise have generated steadily mounting obstacles to revolutionary, transformative, or unorthodox scientific theorizing, but also that we have substantial independent evidence that the institutional apparatus of contemporary scientific inquiry fosters an exceedingly and increasingly theoretically (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • The Attenuated Ramblings of a Madman.Sarah M. Roe - 2009 - Polish Journal of Philosophy 3 (2):67-85.
    The slogan ‘anything goes’ first appears in Paul Feyerabend’s book Against Method at the end of the first chapter. Since that time, philosophical literature has been peppered with criticism and cries of outrage towards Feyerabend’s call for anarchy. Many have speculated on what exactly was meant by the slogan and even more philosophers and scientists have quickly discarded Feyerabend’s antidote as the obvious ramblings of a madman.In this essay, I will argue that Paul Feyerabend does not promote complete anarchy, contrary (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What is General Philosophy of Science?Stathis Psillos - 2012 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 43 (1):93-103.
    The very idea of a general philosophy of science relies on the assumption that there is this thing called science —as opposed to the various individual sciences. In this programmatic piece I make a case for the claim that general philosophy of science is the philosophy of science in general or science as such. Part of my narrative makes use of history, for two reasons. First, general philosophy of science is itself characterised by an intellectual tradition which aimed to develop (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On the historical origins of the contemporary notion of incommensurability: Paul Feyerabend's assault on conceptual conservatism.Eric Oberheim - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 36 (2):363-90.
    This paper investigates the historical origins of the notion of incommensurability in contemporary philosophy of science. The aim is not to establish claims of priority, but to enhance our understanding of the notion by illuminating the various issues that contributed to its development. Kuhn developed his notion of incommensurability primarily under the influence of Fleck, Polanyi, and Köhler. Feyerabend, who had developed his notion more than a decade earlier, drew directly from Duhem, who had developed a notion of incommensurability in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • On the historical origins of the contemporary notion of incommensurability: Paul Feyerabend’s assault on conceptual conservativism.Eric Oberheim - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (2):363-390.
    This paper investigates the historical origins of the notion of incommensurability in contemporary philosophy of science. The aim is not to establish claims of priority, but to enhance our understanding of the notion by illuminating the various issues that contributed to its development. Kuhn developed his notion of incommensurability primarily under the influence of Fleck, Polanyi, and Köhler. Feyerabend, who had developed his notion more than a decade earlier, drew directly from Duhem, who had developed a notion of incommensurability in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Feyerabend and Galileo: The interaction of theories, and the reinterpretation of experience.Peter K. Machamer - 1973 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 4 (1):1-46.
  • Feyerabend's Rationalism.Andrew Lugg - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (4):755 - 775.
    I like to say there is no scientific method as such, but rather only the free and utmost use of intelligence.P.W. BridgmanIt is generally believed—see, for example, Lakatos, Dorling, Koertge, Gellner, and Finnocchiaro—that Feyerabend is committed to the view that science is an essentially irrational enterprise. In this paper, I argue initially that this is so only if Feyerabend is saddled with an unreasonable notion of rationality. Next, I point out, first, that there is a reasonable notion of rationality which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Feyerabend, mill, and pluralism.Elisabeth A. Lloyd - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):407.
    I suggest following Paul Feyerabend's own advice, and interpreting Feyerabend's work in light of the principles laid out by John Stuart Mill. A review of Mill's essay, On Liberty, emphasizes the importance Mill placed on open and critical discussion for the vitality and progress of various aspects of human life, including the pursuit of scientific knowledge. Many of Feyerabend's more unusual stances, I suggest, are best interpreted as attempts to play certain roles--especially the role of "defender of unpopular minority opinion"--that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Criticism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.Imre Lakatos - 1969 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 69 (1):149 - 186.
    Imre Lakatos; II—Criticism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 69, Issue 1, 1 June 1969, Page.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • II—Criticism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.Imre Lakatos - 1969 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 69 (1):149-186.
    Imre Lakatos; II—Criticism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 69, Issue 1, 1 June 1969, Page.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Relativism in Feyerabend's later writings.Martin Kusch - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:106-113.
  • Ii how far does anything go? Comments on Feyerabend's epistemological anarchism.Tomas Kulka - 1977 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 7 (3):277-287.
  • The division of cognitive labor.Philip Kitcher - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy 87 (1):5-22.
  • Two letters of Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kühn on a draft of the structure of scientific revolutions.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (3):353-387.
  • More letters by Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on Proto-Structure.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (4):610-632.
    The paper contains two yet unknown letters that Feyerabend wrote to Kuhn in 1960 or 1961 on a draft of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. In these letters, Feyerabend criticises both details of Kuhn's book and its general direction. The letters anticipate many of the arguments that were put forward in the public controversy against Kuhn's position, including some of the (numerous) misunderstandings. Feyerabend's assertions and arguments are very characteristic of his position in the early sixties.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Rom Harré - 1977 - Mind 86 (342):294-298.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Review: Beyond Truth and Falsehood. [REVIEW]Ernest Gellner - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (4):331 - 342.
  • Beyond truth and falsehood. [REVIEW]Ernest Gellner - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (4):331-342.
  • Beyond Truth and Falsehood. [REVIEW]Ernest Gellner - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (4):331-342.
  • The concept of intelligibility in modern physics.Paul K. Feyerabend - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:64-66.
  • VIII.—An Attempt at a Realistic Interpretation of Experience.P. K. Feyerabend - 1958 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 58 (1):143-170.
  • The structure of science.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1966 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17 (3):237-249.
  • The theatre as an instrument of the criticism of ideologies.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1967 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 10 (1-4):298 – 312.
    It is the thesis of the paper that the arts of the twentieth century have gone much further in the criticism of customary modes of thought than have both the sciences and the various critical philosophies which exist today. Moreover, they have not only developed an abstract principle of criticism, they have also studied the psychological conditions under which criticism can be expected to become effective. Some plays and the theoretical essays of Ionesco are analysed as an example. It is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Reply to Hellman's review.P. K. Feyerabend - 1979 - Metaphilosophy 10 (2):202–206.
  • Review: The Structure of Science. [REVIEW]Paul K. Feyerabend - 1966 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17 (3):237 - 249.
  • Review: Changing Patterns of Reconstruction. [REVIEW]Paul Feyerabend - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (4):351 - 369.
  • On a recent critique of complementarity: Part II.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1969 - Philosophy of Science 36 (1):82-105.
    “Bohr was primarily a philosopher, not a physicist, but he understood that natural philosophy... carries weight only if its every detail can be subjected to the... test of experiment”. As a result his approach differed from that of the school-philosophers whom he regarded with a somewhat “sceptical attitude, to say the least” and whose lack of interest in “the important viewpoint which had emerged during the development of atomic physics” he noticed with regret. But it also differed, and to a (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Reviews. [REVIEW]Paul K. Feyerabend - 1964 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 15 (59):244-254.
  • Marxist fairytales from australia.Paul Feyerabend - 1977 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 20 (1-4):372 – 397.
  • Machamer on Galileo.Paul Feyerabend - 1974 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 5 (3):297-304.
  • Changing patterns of reconstruction.Paul Feyerabend - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (4):351-369.
  • Eliminative pluralism.Marc Ereshefsky - 1992 - Philosophy of Science 59 (4):671-690.
    This paper takes up the cause of species pluralism. An argument for species pluralism is provided and standard monist objections to pluralism are answered. A new form of species pluralism is developed and shown to be an improvement over previous forms. This paper also offers a general foundation on which to base a pluralistic approach to biological classification.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Two Millian Arguments: Using Helen Longino’s Approach to Solve the Problems Philip Kitcher Targeted with His Argument on Freedom of Inquiry.Jaana Eigi - 2012 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 5 (1):44-63.
    Philip Kitcher argued that the freedom to pursue one's version of the good life is the main aim of Mill's argument for freedom of expression. According to Kitcher, in certain scientific fields, political and epistemological asymmetries bias research toward conclusions that threaten this most important freedom of underprivileged groups. Accordingly, Kitcher claimed that there are Millian grounds for limiting freedom of inquiry in these fields to protect the freedom of the underprivileged. -/- I explore Kitcher's argument in light of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Was Feyerabend a Popperian? Methodological issues in the History of the Philosophy of Science.Matteo Collodel - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:27-56.
  • Feyerabend and Popper on Theory Proliferation and Anomaly Import: On the Compatibility of Theoretical Pluralism and Critical Rationalism.Karim Bschir - 2015 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 5 (1):24-55.
    A fundamental tenet of Paul Feyerabend’s pluralistic view of science has it that theory proliferation, that is, the availability of theoretical alternatives, is of crucial importance for the detection of anomalies in established theories. Paul Hoyningen-Huene calls this the Anomaly Importation Thesis, according to which anomalies are imported, as it were, into well-established theories from competing alternatives. This article pursues two major objectives: (a) to work out the systematic details of Feyerabend’s ideas on theory proliferation and anomaly import as they (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Against method: Outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge.Joseph Agassi - 1976 - Philosophia 6 (1):165-177.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Science in a Democratic Society.Philip Kitcher - 2011 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 101:95-112.
    Claims that science should be more democratic than it is frequently arouse opposition. In this essay, I distinguish my own views about the democratization of science from the more ambitious theses defended by Paul Feyerabend. I argue that it is unlikely that the complexity of some scientific debates will allow for resolution according to the methodological principles of any formal confirmation theory, suggesting instead that major revolutions rest on conflicts of values. Yet these conflicts should not be dismissed as irresoluble.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   198 citations