Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Carnap’s Early Semantics.Georg Schiemer - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (3):487-522.
    This paper concerns Carnap’s early contributions to formal semantics in his work on general axiomatics between 1928 and 1936. Its main focus is on whether he held a variable domain conception of models. I argue that interpreting Carnap’s account in terms of a fixed domain approach fails to describe his premodern understanding of formal models. By drawing attention to the second part of Carnap’s unpublished manuscript Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik, an alternative interpretation of the notions ‘model’, ‘model extension’ and ‘submodel’ (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Set theory, model theory, and computability theory.Wilfrid Hodges - 2011 - In Leila Haaparanta (ed.), The development of modern logic. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 471.
    This chapter surveys set theory, model theory, and computability theory: how they first emerged from the foundations of mathematics, and how they have developed since. There are any amounts of mathematical technicalities in the background, but the chapter highlights those themes that have some philosophical resonance.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The development of mathematical logic from Russell to Tarski, 1900-1935.Paolo Mancosu, Richard Zach & Calixto Badesa - 2011 - In Leila Haaparanta (ed.), The development of modern logic. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The period from 1900 to 1935 was particularly fruitful and important for the development of logic and logical metatheory. This survey is organized along eight "itineraries" concentrating on historically and conceptually linked strands in this development. Itinerary I deals with the evolution of conceptions of axiomatics. Itinerary II centers on the logical work of Bertrand Russell. Itinerary III presents the development of set theory from Zermelo onward. Itinerary IV discusses the contributions of the algebra of logic tradition, in particular, Löwenheim (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Frege, hilbert, and the conceptual structure of model theory.William Demopoulos - 1994 - History and Philosophy of Logic 15 (2):211-225.
    This paper attempts to confine the preconceptions that prevented Frege from appreciating Hilbert?s Grundlagen der Geometrie to two: (i) Frege?s reliance on what, following Wilfrid Hodges, I call a Frege?Peano language, and (ii) Frege?s view that the sense of an expression wholly determines its reference.I argue that these two preconceptions prevented Frege from achieving the conceptual structure of model theory, whereas Hilbert, at least in his practice, was quite close to the model?theoretic point of view.Moreover, the issues that divided Frege (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics.Atwell Turquette - 1958 - Philosophical Review 67 (1):113.
  • Completeness and Categoricity. Part I: Nineteenth-century Axiomatics to Twentieth-century Metalogic.Steve Awodey & Erich H. Reck - 2002 - History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (1):1-30.
    This paper is the first in a two-part series in which we discuss several notions of completeness for systems of mathematical axioms, with special focus on their interrelations and historical origins in the development of the axiomatic method. We argue that, both from historical and logical points of view, higher-order logic is an appropriate framework for considering such notions, and we consider some open questions in higher-order axiomatics. In addition, we indicate how one can fruitfully extend the usual set-theoretic semantics (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Mathematical Logic.J. Donald Monk - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):376-376.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Foundations without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-Order Logic.Gila Sher - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (1):150.
  • Carnap's Untersuchungen: Logicism, Formal Axiomatics, and Metatheory.Georg Schiemer - 2012 - In R. Creath (ed.), Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook. Springer Verlag. pp. 13--36.
    This paper discusses Carnap’s attempts in the late 1920s to provide a formal reconstruction of modern axiomatics.1 One interpretive theme addressed in recent scholarly literature concerns Carnap’s underlying logicism in his philosophy of mathematics from that time, more specifically, his attempt to “reconcile” the logicist approach of reducing mathematics to logic with the formal axiomatic method. For instance, Awodey & Carus characterize Carnap’s manuscript Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik from 1928 as a “large-scale project to reconcile axiomatic definitions with logicism, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Carnap’s Untersuchungen: Logicism, Formal Axiomatics, and Metatheory.Georg Schiemer - 2012 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 16:13-36.
    This paper discusses Carnap’s attempts in the late 1920s to provide a formal reconstruction of modern axiomatics.1 One interpretive theme addressed in recent scholarly literature concerns Carnap’s underlying logicism in his philosophy of mathematics from that time, more specifically, his attempt to “reconcile” the logicist approach of reducing mathematics to logic with the formal axiomatic method. For instance, Awodey & Carus characterize Carnap’s manuscript Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik from 1928 as a “large-scale project to reconcile axiomatic definitions with logicism, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Carnap on extremal axioms, "completeness of the models," and categoricity.Georg Schiemer - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (4):613-641.
    This paper provides a historically sensitive discussion of Carnaps theory will be assessed with respect to two interpretive issues. The first concerns his mathematical sources, that is, the mathematical axioms on which his extremal axioms were based. The second concerns Carnapcompleteness of the modelss different attempts to explicate the extremal properties of a theory and puts his results in context with related metamathematical research at the time.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On the Matter of Essential Richness.Greg Ray - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (4):433-457.
    Alfred Tarski (1944) wrote that "the condition of the 'essential richness' of the metalanguage proves to be, not only necessary, but also sufficient for the construction of a satisfactory definition of truth." But it has remained unclear what Tarski meant by an 'essentially richer' metalanguage. Moreover, DeVidi and Solomon (1999) have argued in this Journal that there is nothing that Tarski could have meant by that phrase which would make his pronouncement true. We develop an answer to the historical question (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Philosophy of Logic.Willard V. O. Quine - 1986 - Philosophy 17 (3):392-393.
    With his customary incisiveness, W. V. Quine presents logic as the product of two factors, truth and grammar-but argues against the doctrine that the logical truths are true because of grammar or language. Rather, in presenting a general theory of grammar and discussing the boundaries and possible extensions of logic, Quine argues that logic is not a mere matter of words.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • The Logical Syntax of Language. [REVIEW]E. N. - 1937 - Journal of Philosophy 34 (11):303.
  • Recursive Functions and Metamathematics: Problems of Completeness and Decidability, Gödel's Theorems.Rod J. L. Adams & Roman Murawski - 1999 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    Traces the development of recursive functions from their origins in the late nineteenth century to the mid-1930s, with particular emphasis on the work and influence of Kurt Gödel.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Tarski on Logical Consequence.Mario Gómez-Torrente - 1996 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 37 (1):125-151.
    This paper examines from a historical perspective Tarski's 1936 essay, "On the concept of logical consequence." I focus on two main aims. The primary aim is to show how Tarski's definition of logical consequence satisfies two desiderata he himself sets forth for it: (1) it must declare logically correct certain formalizations of the -rule and (2) it must allow for variation of the individual domain in the test for logical consequence. My arguments provide a refutation of some interpreters of Tarski, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Fixed- versus Variable-domain Interpretations of Tarski’s Account of Logical Consequence.Paolo Mancosu - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (9):745-759.
    In this article I describe and evaluate the debate that surrounds the proper interpretation of Tarski’s account of logical consequence given in his classic 1936 article ‘On the concept of logical consequence’. In the late 1980s Etchemendy argued that the familiar model theoretic account of logical consequence is not to be found in Tarski’s original article. Whereas the contemporary account of logical consequence is a variable‐domain conception – in that it calls for a reinterpretation of the domain of variation of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Carnap’s dream: Gödel, Wittgenstein, and Logical, Syntax.S. Awodey & A. W. Carus - 2007 - Synthese 159 (1):23-45.
    In Carnap’s autobiography, he tells the story how one night in January 1931, “the whole theory of language structure” in all its ramifications “came to [him] like a vision”. The shorthand manuscript he produced immediately thereafter, he says, “was the first version” of Logical Syntax of Language. This document, which has never been examined since Carnap’s death, turns out not to resemble Logical Syntax at all, at least on the surface. Wherein, then, did the momentous insight of 21 January 1931 (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • A new approach to semantics – Part II.John G. Kemeny - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (2):149-161.
  • A new approach to semantics – Part I.John G. Kemeny - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21:1.
  • Set Theory.Keith J. Devlin - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):876-877.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   163 citations  
  • Truth in a Structure.Wilfrid Hodges - 1986 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86:135 - 151.
    Wilfrid Hodges; VIII*—Truth in a Structure, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 86, Issue 1, 1 June 1986, Pages 135–152, https://doi.org/10.1093/ari.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • On the development of the model-theoretic viewpoint in logical theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 1988 - Synthese 77 (1):1 - 36.
  • Carnap's work in the foundations of logic and mathematics in a historical perspective.Jaakko Hintikka - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):167 - 189.
    Carnap's philosophy is examined from new viewpoints, including three important distinctions: (i) language as calculus vs language as universal medium; (ii) different senses of completeness: (iii) standard vs nonstandard interpretations of (higher-order) logic. (i) Carnap favored in 1930-34 the "formal mode of speech," a corollary to the universality assumption. He later gave it up partially but retained some of its ingredients, e.g., the one-domain assumption. (ii) Carnap's project of creating a universal self-referential language is encouraged by (ii) and by the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Logic in the twenties: The nature of the quantifier.Warren D. Goldfarb - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (3):351-368.
  • The indefinability of truth in the “Wahrheitsbegriff”.Mario Gómez-Torrente - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126 (1-3):27-37.
    Contrary to what often seems to be the implicit belief, Tarski's 1933 version of the theorem on the indefinability of truth did not mention semantic notions, either defined or intuitive. I state this version in a somewhat modernized form and explain briefly the self-imposed mathematico-philosophical constraints that led Tarski to formulate it as he did. I also point out that close attention to its content suggests a refined view of the exact contrast between Tarski's achievement and Gödel's achievement in his (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Rereading Tarski on logical consequence.Mario Gómez-Torrente - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):249-297.
    I argue that recent defenses of the view that in 1936 Tarski required all interpretations of a language to share one same domain of quantification are based on misinterpretations of Tarski’s texts. In particular, I rebut some criticisms of my earlier attack on the fixed-domain exegesis and I offer a more detailed report of the textual evidence on the issue than in my earlier work. I also offer new considerations on subsisting issues of interpretation concerning Tarski’s views on the logical (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Comparison of Russell's resolution of the semantical antinomies with that of Tarski.Alonzo Church - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (4):747-760.
  • Über Extremalaxiome.Rudolf Carnap & Friedrich Bachmann - 1936 - Erkenntnis 6 (1):166-188.
  • Bericht über untersuchungen zur allgemeinen axiomatik.Rudolf Carnap - 1930 - Erkenntnis 1 (1):303-307.
  • On Tarski on models.Timothy Bays - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1701-1726.
    This paper concerns Tarski’s use of the term “model” in his 1936 paper “On the Concept of Logical Consequence.” Against several of Tarski’s recent defenders, I argue that Tarski employed a non-standard conception of models in that paper. Against Tarski’s detractors, I argue that this non-standard conception is more philosophically plausible than it may appear. Finally, I make a few comments concerning the traditionally puzzling case of Tarski’s ω-rule example.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Carnap, completeness, and categoricity:The gabelbarkeitssatz OF 1928. [REVIEW]S. Awodey & A. W. Carus - 2001 - Erkenntnis 54 (2):145-172.
    In 1929 Carnap gave a paper in Prague on Investigations in General Axiomatics; a briefsummary was published soon after. Its subject lookssomething like early model theory, and the mainresult, called the Gabelbarkeitssatz, appears toclaim that a consistent set of axioms is complete justif it is categorical. This of course casts doubt onthe entire project. Though there is no furthermention of this theorem in Carnap''s publishedwritings, his Nachlass includes a largetypescript on the subject, Investigations inGeneral Axiomatics. We examine this work here,showing (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • ch. 17. Developments in logic : Carnap, Godel, and Tarski.Erich H. Reck - 2013 - In Michael Beaney (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  • Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik.D. Hilbert & W. Ackermann - 1928 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 7:157-157.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   202 citations  
  • Hierarchies Ontological and Ideological.Øystein Linnebo & Agustín Rayo - 2012 - Mind 121 (482):269 - 308.
    Gödel claimed that Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory is 'what becomes of the theory of types if certain superfluous restrictions are removed'. The aim of this paper is to develop a clearer understanding of Gödel's remark, and of the surrounding philosophical terrain. In connection with this, we discuss some technical issues concerning infinitary type theories and the programme of developing the semantics for higher-order languages in other higher-order languages.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Der wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten sprachen.Alfred Tarski - 1935 - Studia Philosophica 1:261--405.
  • From Wittgenstein's prison to the boundless ocean : Carnap's dream of logical syntax.Steve Awodey & A. W. Carus - 2009 - In Pierre Wagner (ed.), Carnap's Logical Syntax of Language. Palgrave-Macmillan.