Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The struggle against dogmatism: Wittgenstein and the concept of philosophy.Oskari Kuusela - 2008 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Wittgenstein on philosophical problems : from one fundamental problem to particular problems -- The Tractatus on philosophical problems -- Wittgenstein's later conception of philosophical problems -- Examples of philosophical problems as based on misunderstandings -- Tendencies and inclinations of thinking : philosophy as therapy -- Wittgenstein's notion of peace in philosophy : the contrast with the Tractatus -- Two conceptions of clarification -- The Tractatus's conception of philosophy as logical analysis -- Wittgenstein's later critique of the Tractatus's notion of logical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Scepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties.P. F. Strawson - 1985 - New York: Routledge.
    By the time of his death in 2006, Sir Peter Strawson was regarded as one of the world's most distinguished philosophers. Unavailable for many years,_ Scepticism and Naturalism_ is a profound reflection on two classic philosophical problems by a philosopher at the pinnacle of his career. Based on his acclaimed Woodbridge lectures delivered at Columbia University in 1983, Strawson begins with a discussion of scepticism, which he defines as questioning the adequacy of our grounds for holding various beliefs. He then (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Editor’s Introduction.[author unknown] - 2011 - Editor's Introduction 4 (30).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conclusion.[author unknown] - 1926 - Archives de Philosophie 4 (3):112.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Hume on free will.Paul Russell - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    David Hume is widely recognized as providing the most influential statement of the “compatibilist” position in the free will debate — the view that freedom and moral responsibility can be reconciled with (causal) determinism. The arguments that Hume advances on this subject are found primarily in the sections titled “Of liberty and necessity”, as first presented in A Treatise of Human Nature (2.3.1-2) and, later, in a slightly amended form, in the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding (sec. 8). Although there is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Empiricism about Meanings.Jonathan Bennett - 2001 - In Peter Millican (ed.), Reading Hume on Human Understanding: Essays on the First Enquiry. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Hume's Intentions.John Arthur Passmore - 1952 - London: Cambridge University Press. Edited by David Hume.
    John Passmore was a renowned Australian empirical philosopher and historian of ideas. In this book, which was originally published in 1952, Passmore's intention was to disentangle certain main themes in Hume's philosophy and to show how they relate to Hume's main philosophic purpose. Rather than offering a detailed commentary, the text provides an account based on specificity and critical scholarship, seeking to complement the other more comprehensive works on Hume's philosophy that had become available around the same time. This book (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Preliminary studies for the 'Philosophical investigations'.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1958 - Oxford,: Blackwell. Edited by Ludwig Wittgenstein.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations," generally known as the Blue and Brown books.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1958 - Oxford,: Blackwell. Edited by Ludwig Wittgenstein.
    These works, as the sub-title makes clear, are unfinished sketches for Philosophical Investigations, possibly the most important and influential philosophical ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar.Michael N. Forster - 2005 - Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.
    What is the nature of a conceptual scheme? Are there alternative conceptual schemes? If so, are some more justifiable or correct than others? The later Wittgenstein already addresses these fundamental philosophical questions under the general rubric of "grammar" and the question of its "arbitrariness"--and does so with great subtlety. This book explores Wittgenstein's views on these questions. Part I interprets his conception of grammar as a generalized version of Kant's transcendental idealist solution to a puzzle about necessity. It also seeks (...)
    No categories
  • Rule-following without Reasons: Wittgenstein’s Quietism and the Constitutive Question.Crispin Wright - 2007 - Ratio 20 (4):481–502.
    This is a short, and therefore necessarily very incomplete discussion of one of the great questions of modern philosophy. I return to a station at which an interpretative train of thought of mine came to a halt in a paper written almost 20 years ago, about Wittgenstein and Chomsky,[1] hoping to advance a little bit further down the track. The rule-following passages in the Investigations and Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics in fact raise a number of distinct issues about (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and idealism.Bernard Williams - 1981 - In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980. Cambridge University Press. pp. 144-164.
  • Wittgenstein and Idealism.Bernard Williams - 1973 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 7:76-95.
    Tractatus, 5.62 famously says: ‘… what the solipsist means is quite correct; only it cannot be said but makes itself manifest. The world is my world: this is manifest in the fact that the limits of language mean the limits of my world.’ The later part of this repeats what was said in summary at 5.6: ‘the limits of my language mean the limits of my world’. And the key to the problem ‘how much truth there is in solipsism’ has (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The rhetoric of grammar: Understanding Wittgenstein's method.William E. Barnett - 1990 - Metaphilosophy 21 (1-2):43-66.
  • Is Hume's shade of blue a red Herring?William H. Williams - 1992 - Synthese 92 (1):83 - 99.
    The existence of an idea of a missing shade of blue contradicts Hume's first principle that simple ideas all derive from corresponding simple impressions. Hume dismisses the exception to his principle as unimportant. Why does he do so? His later account of distinctions of reason suggests a systematic way of dealing with simple ideas not derived from simple impressions. Why does he not return to the problem of the missing shade, having offered that account? Several suggestions as to Hume's solution (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hume's Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature.Michael Williams & Robert J. Fogelin - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (2):263.
  • Moore and Wittgenstein on certainty.Avrum Stroll - 1994 - New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Hume.Barry Stroud - 2016 - Philosophical Review 125 (4):597-601.
  • The naturalism of Hume (II.).Norman Smith - 1905 - Mind 14 (55):335-347.
  • Hume's two definitions of "cause".J. A. Robinson - 1962 - Philosophical Quarterly 12 (47):162-171.
  • Hume's Intentions.Kingsley Price - 1954 - Philosophical Review 63 (1):113.
  • Hume on Knowledge, by Harold Noonan. [REVIEW]P. J. E. Kail - 2001 - Mind 110 (440):1102-1105.
  • Hume's Missing Shade of Blue Re-viewed.John O. Nelson - 1989 - Hume Studies 15 (2):353-363.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume's Missing Shade of Blue Re-viewed John 0. Nelson It is obviously important for Hume's purposes in the Treatise to maintain that simple ideas are always founded in precedent, resembling impressions;1 andhe explicitly, overandover, doesso, evensometimes being so carried away by this first principle ofhis science of man (T 7) or so careless as to say that not just all simple ideas but all ideas are founded in precedent, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The rational warrant for Hume's general rules.Marie Martin - 1993 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 31 (2):245-257.
  • Naturalism and Scepticism.Martin Bell & Marie McGinn - 1990 - Philosophy 65 (254):399 - 418.
    In this paper we argue that a dominant view of Humean naturalism involves a fundamental misconception of Hume's naturalist project. We shall show that the naturalist project as Hume conceives it is philosophically much more interesting than the form of naturalism commonly attributed to him. We shall also argue, however, that Hume's commitment to principles of empiricist epistemology prevented him from bringing his naturalist project to a satisfactory conclusion. Finally, we shall suggest that Wittgenstein shares Hume's conception of a philosophically (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • General Rules and the Justification of Probable Belief in Hume’s Treatise.Jack C. Lyons - 2001 - Hume Studies 27 (2):247-278.
    An examination of the role played by general rules in Hume's positive (nonskeptical) epistemology. General rules for Hume are roughly just general beliefs. The difference between justified and unjustified belief is a matter of the influence of good versus bad general rules, the good general rules being the "extensive" and "constant" ones.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hume's philosophy of common life.Donald W. Livingston - 1984 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Review of Donald W. Livingston: Hume's Philosophy of Common Life[REVIEW]John Deigh - 1985 - Ethics 95 (4):959-960.
  • Mark Norris Lance and John O'Leary-Hawthorne, The Grammar of Meaning.Mark Norris Lance & John O'leary-Hawthorne - 1998 - Erkenntnis 49 (3):403-409.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on rules and private language: an elementary exposition.Saul A. Kripke - 1982 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In this book Saul Kripke brings his powerful philosophical intelligence to bear on Wittgenstein's analysis of the notion of following a rule.
  • Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language.Paul Horwich - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (1):163-171.
    Discussion of Wittgenstein's philosophy has suffered from a scarcity of commentators who understand his work well enough to explain it in their own words. Apart from certain notable exceptions, all too many advocates and critics alike have tended merely to repeat slogans, with approval or ridicule as the case may be. The result has been an unusual degree of polarization and acrimony—some philosophers abandoning normal critical standards, falling under the spell and becoming fanatical supporters; and others taking an equally extreme (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   377 citations  
  • Gewissheit Als Norm: Wittgensteins Erkenntnistheoretische Untersuchungen in "Über Gewissheit".Michael Kober - 1993 - New York: De Gruyter.
  • Kritik der reinen Vernunft.Immanuel Kant - 2020 - Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG.
    überall einen richtigen Gebrauch der reinen Vernunft giebt, in welchem Fall es auch einen Canon derselben geben muß, so wird dieser nicht den speculativen, sondernden pr.ntischen Vernunftgebrauch betreffen, den wir also iezt ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   632 citations  
  • Hume's Sentiments.Peter Jones - 1986 - Noûs 20 (2):274-281.
  • What's the Point of Elucidation?Phil Hutchinson - 2007 - Metaphilosophy 38 (5):691-713.
    In this article I examine three ways in which one might interpret Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations (PI). In a partial response to Hans‐Johann Glock's article in this journal, I suggest that since publication PI has, broadly speaking, been interpreted in three ways: doctrinal; elucidatory; or therapeutic. The doctrinal interpretation is shown to be, at best, difficult to sustain textually. The elucidatory (standard) interpretation, though seemingly closer to the text, is shown both to implicate Wittgenstein in some unfortunate philosophical commitments and to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Toward a perspicuous presentation of "perspicuous presentation".Phil Hutchinson & Rupert Read - 2008 - Philosophical Investigations 31 (2):141–160.
    Gordon Baker in his last decade published a series of papers (now collected in Baker 2004), which are revolutionary in their proposals for understanding of later Wittgenstein. Taking our lead from the first of those papers, on "perspicuous presentations," we offer new criticisms of 'elucidatory' readers of later Wittgenstein, such as Peter Hacker: we argue that their readings fail to connect with the radically therapeutic intent of the 'perspicuous presentation' concept, as an achievement-term, rather than a kind of 'objective' mapping (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Hume and the Problem of Causation.Terence Horgan - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (2):278.
  • Investigating Wittgenstein. [REVIEW]Robert J. Fogelin - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (1):93-97.
  • Wittgenstein and Behaviourism.S. Stephen Hilmy - 1989 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 33 (1):335-352.
    Many have interpreted Wittgenstein as advocating a form of behaviourism. Through an examination of Wittgenstein's own remarks about behaviourism, and further textual evidence from his notebooks, it is shown that categorizing Wittgenstein as a 'behaviourist', of whatever ilk, serves not merely to obstruct an appreciation of his thinking, but perversely to distort Wittgenstein's views by flying in the face of the central critical thrusts of his later philosophy.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hume and Wittgenstein.Oswald Hanfling - 1975 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 9:47-65.
    It is well known that Wittgenstein's reading of the philosophical classics was patchy. He left unread a large part of the literature which most philosophers would regard as essential to a knowledge of their subject. Wittgenstein gave an interesting reason for his non-reading of Hume. He said that he could not sit down and read Hume, because he knew far too much about the subject of Hume's writings to find this anything but a torture. In a recent commentary, Peter Hacker (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Was Wittgenstein an Analytic Philosopher?Hans-Johann Glock - 2004 - Metaphilosophy 35 (4):419-444.
    This article first surveys the established views on Wittgenstein's relation to analytic philosophy. Next it distinguishes among different ways of defining analytic philosophy—topical, doctrinal, methodological, stylistic, historical, and the idea that it is a family‐resemblance concept. It argues that while certain stylistic features are important, the historical and the family‐resemblance conceptions are the most auspicious, especially in combination. The answer to the title question is given in section 3. Contrary to currently popular “irrationalist” interpretations, Wittgenstein was an analytic philosopher in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar.Michael N. Forster - 2004 - Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.
    What is the nature of a conceptual scheme? Are there alternative conceptual schemes? If so, are some more justifiable or correct than others? The later Wittgenstein already addresses these fundamental philosophical questions under the general rubric of "grammar" and the question of its "arbitrariness"--and does so with great subtlety. This book explores Wittgenstein's views on these questions. Part I interprets his conception of grammar as a generalized version of Kant's transcendental idealist solution to a puzzle about necessity. It also seeks (...)
  • Michael N. Forster, Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar. [REVIEW]John Hyman - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (3):471-473.
  • Hume's Interest in Newton and Science.James E. Force - 1987 - Hume Studies 13 (2):166-216.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:166 HUME'S INTEREST IN NEWTON AND SCIENCE Many writers have been forced to examine — in their treatments of Hume's knowledge of and acquaintance with scientific theories of his day — the related questions of Hume's knowledge of and acquaintance with Isaac Newton and of the nature and extent of Newtonian influences upon Hume's thinking. Most have concluded that — in some sense — Hume was acquainted with and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Hume's skepticism in the Treatise of human nature.Robert J. Fogelin - 1985 - Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
    Examines the skeptical arguments in David Hume's major work and analyzes the place of skepticism in his philosophy.
  • Hume’s Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature.Robert J. Fogelin - 1985 - Mind 95 (379):392-396.
  • Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind.Jerry A. Fodor - 1987 - MIT Press. Edited by Margaret A. Boden.
    Preface 1 Introduction: The Persistence of the Attitudes 2 Individualism and Supervenience 3 Meaning Holism 4 Meaning and the World Order Epilogue Creation Myth Appendix Why There Still Has to be a Language of Thought Notes References Author Index.
  • Review of P sychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning In the Philosophy of Mind. [REVIEW]Jay L. Garfield - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1):235-240.
  • Hume's Philosophy of Belief.Jack Kaminsky - 1962 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 23 (2):295-296.
  • David Hume's theory of mind.Daniel E. Flage - 1990 - New York: Routledge.
    INTRODUCTION Anyone who reads David Hume's Treatise of Human Nature cannot but be struck by the diversity of philosophical issues Hume addresses, ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations