Switch to: Citations

References in:

Reformulating Mill’s Harm Principle

Mind 125 (500):1005-1032 (2016)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Harm, Rights, and Liberty: Towards a Non-Normative Reading of Mill's Liberty Principle. Mulnix - 2009 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (2):196-217.
    Many commentators have argued that Mill's Liberty Principle is most reasonably construed as limiting social interference to cases where an individual's action either harms or increases the probability of harm to others. The convention when it comes to understanding harm seems to be to build into the concept a normative component such that what it means to harm someone is that we have wronged them in some important respect. But such an understanding of harm will vary depending upon which particular (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Subjection of Women.Susan M. Okin (ed.) - 1988 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    "Reasonably priced and beautifully produced. A clear and helpful introduction by Susan Okin, one of the leading feminist scholars of our generation, as well as a useful bibliography and chronology of Mill's life.... Invaluable for teaching and scholarship alike." --Ian Shapiro, Yale University.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • .Dermot Hodson - 2016
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • John Stuart mill and pornography: Beyond the harm principle.Richard Vernon - 1996 - Ethics 106 (3):621-632.
  • “Harm” and Mill’s Harm Principle.Piers Norris Turner - 2014 - Ethics 124 (2):299-326.
    This article addresses the long-standing problem of how to understand Mill’s famous harm principle in light of his failure to specify what counts as “harm” in On Liberty. I argue that standard accounts restricting “harm” to only certain negative consequences fail to do justice to the text, and that this fact forces us to rethink Mill’s defense of individual liberty. I then offer a new account of that defense in which “harm” is understood in an expansive sense, despite apparent problems (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Incest and Liberal Neutrality.Johan Tralau - 2012 - Journal of Political Philosophy 21 (1):87-105.
  • Retributivists! The Harm Principle Is Not for You!Patrick Tomlin - 2014 - Ethics 124 (2):272-298.
    Retributivism is often explicitly or implicitly assumed to be compatible with the harm principle, since the harm principle (in some guises) concerns the content of the criminal law, while retributivism concerns the punishment of those that break the law. In this essay I show that retributivism should not be endorsed alongside any version of the harm principle. In fact, retributivists should reject all attempts to see the criminal law only through (other) person-affecting concepts or “grievance” morality, since they should endorse (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Review of C. L. Ten: Mill on Liberty[REVIEW]Richard J. Arneson - 1983 - Ethics 93 (2):399-401.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mill and pornography.Robert Skipper - 1993 - Ethics 103 (4):726-730.
  • J. S. mill's conception of utility.Ben Saunders - 2010 - Utilitas 22 (1):52-69.
    Mill's most famous departure from Bentham is his distinction between higher and lower pleasures. This article argues that quality and quantity are independent and irreducible properties of pleasures that may be traded off against each other higher pleasures’ lexically dominate lower ones, and that the distinction is compatible with hedonism. I show how this interpretation not only makes sense of Mill but allows him to respond to famous problems, such as Crisp's Haydn and the oyster and Nozick's experience machine.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • J. S. Mill's Conception of Utility.Ben Saunders - 2010 - Utilitas 22 (1):52-69.
    Mill's most famous departure from Bentham is his distinction between higher and lower pleasures. This article argues that quality and quantity are independent and irreducible properties of pleasures that may be traded off against each other – as in the case of quality and quantity of wine. I argue that Mill is not committed to thinking that there are two distinct kinds of pleasure, or that ‘higher pleasures’ lexically dominate lower ones, and that the distinction is compatible with hedonism. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Defining the demos.Ben Saunders - 2012 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 11 (3):280-301.
    Until relatively recently, few democrats had much to say about the constitution of the ‘demos' that ought to rule. A number of recent writers have, however, argued that all those whose interests are affected must be enfranchised if decision-making is to be fully democratic. This article criticizes this approach, arguing that it misunderstands democracy. Democratic procedures are about the agency of the people so only agents can be enfranchised, yet not all bearers of interests are also agents. If we focus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • On Social Facts.Michael Root - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (3):675.
  • Beyond the Harm Principle.Arthur Ripstein - 2006 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (3):215-245.
  • Trans Fat Bans and Human Freedom.David Resnik - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (3):27-32.
    A growing body of evidence has linked consumption of trans fatty acids to cardiovascular disease. To promote public health, numerous state and local governments in the United States have banned the use of artificial trans fats in restaurant foods, and additional bans may follow. Although these policies may have a positive impact on human health, they open the door to excessive government control over food, which could restrict dietary choices, interfere with cultural, ethnic, and religious traditions, and exacerbate socioeconomic inequalities. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Political Liberalism.Stephen Mulhall - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (177):542-545.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • Political Liberalism.John Rawls - 1993 - Columbia University Press.
    This book continues and revises the ideas of justice as fairness that John Rawls presented in _A Theory of Justice_ but changes its philosophical interpretation in a fundamental way. That previous work assumed what Rawls calls a "well-ordered society," one that is stable and relatively homogenous in its basic moral beliefs and in which there is broad agreement about what constitutes the good life. Yet in modern democratic society a plurality of incompatible and irreconcilable doctrines--religious, philosophical, and moral--coexist within the (...)
  • Political Liberalism by John Rawls. [REVIEW]Philip Pettit - 1994 - Journal of Philosophy 91 (4):215-220.
  • Some limits of informed consent.O. O'Neill - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (1):4-7.
    Many accounts of informed consent in medical ethics claim that it is valuable because it supports individual autonomy. Unfortunately there are many distinct conceptions of individual autonomy, and their ethical importance varies. A better reason for taking informed consent seriously is that it provides assurance that patients and others are neither deceived nor coerced. Present debates about the relative importance of generic and specific consent do not address this issue squarely. Consent is a propositional attitude, so intransitive: complete, wholly specific (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Principles of Political Economy with some of their Applications to Social Philosophy. [REVIEW]H. R. Mussey - 1911 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 8 (1):26-26.
  • Egalitarianism and the levelling down objection.Andrew Mason - 2001 - Analysis 61 (3):246–254.
    In an important piece of work Derek Parfit distinguishes two different forms of egalitarianism, ‘Deontic’ and ‘Telic’. He contrasts these with what he calls the Priority View, which is not strictly a form of egalitarianism at all, since it is not essentially concerned with how well off people are relative to each other. His main aim is to generate an adequate taxonomy of the positions available, but in the process he draws attention to some of the different problems they face. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The nature and disvalue of injury.Seth Lazar - 2009 - Res Publica 15 (3):289-304.
    This paper explicates a conception of injury as right-violation, which allows us to distinguish between setbacks to interests that should, and should not, be the concern of theories of justice. It begins by introducing a hybrid theory of rights, grounded in (a) the mobilisation of our moral equality to (b) protect our most important interests, and shows how violations of rights are the concern of justice, while setbacks where one of the twin grounds of rights is defeated are not. It (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Lipids, Liberty, and the Integrity of Free Actions.Kenneth Kirkwood - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (3):45-46.
  • One Very Simple Principle.Jonathan Riley - 1991 - Utilitas 3 (1):1.
    John Gray, much influenced by Isaiah Berlin and building on work by the late John Rees and the late Fred Berger, has recently stated three ‘fatal’ objections which virtually all analysts seem to find persuasive against John Stuart Mill's classic doctrine of liberty. First, Gray thinks it ‘an obvious objection to Mill's project that conceptions of harm vary with competing moral outlooks, so that no Principle of Liberty whose application turns on judgements about harm can expect to resolve disputes between (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The harm principle.Nils Holtug - 2002 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5 (4):357-389.
    According to the Harm Principle, roughly, the state may coerce a person only if it can thereby prevent harm to others. Clearly, this principle depends crucially on what we understand by harm. Thus, if any sort of negative effect on a person may count as a harm, the Harm Principle will fail to sufficiently protect individual liberty. Therefore, a more subtle concept of harm is needed. I consider various possible conceptions and argue that none gives rise to a plausible version (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The harm principle and genetically modified food.Nils Holtug - 2001 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 14 (2):168-178.
    It is suggested that the Harm Principle can be viewedas the moral basis on which genetically modified (GM) food iscurrently regulated. It is then argued (a) that the concept ofharm cannot be specified in such a manner as to render the HarmPrinciple a plausible political principle, so this principlecannot be used to justify existing regulation; and (b) that evenif the Harm Principle were a plausible political principle, itcould not be used alone in the regulation of GM food, since itdoes not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mill, Paternalism, and Slavery.John D. Hodson - 1980 - Analysis 41 (1):60 - 62.
  • Paternalism and the Ill-Informed Agent.Jason Hanna - 2012 - The Journal of Ethics 16 (4):421-439.
    Most anti-paternalists claim that informed and competent self-regarding choices are protected by autonomy, while ill-informed or impaired self-regarding choices are not. Joel Feinberg, among many others, argues that we can in this way distinguish impermissible “hard” paternalism from permissible “soft” paternalism. I argue that this view confronts two related problems in its treatment of ill-informed decision-makers. First, it faces a dilemma when applied to decision-makers who are responsible for their ignorance: it either permits too much, or else too little, intervention (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Trans Fat Bans and the Human Freedom: A Refutation.Lawrence O. Gostin - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (3):33-34.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On Social Facts.Roger Fellows - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (162):100-104.
  • On Social Facts.Margaret Gilbert - 1989 - Routledge.
    This book offers original accounts of a number of central social phenomena, many of which have received little if any prior philosophical attention. These phenomena include social groups, group languages, acting together, collective belief, mutual recognition, and social convention. In the course of developing her analyses Gilbert discusses the work of Emile Durkheim, Georg Simmel, Max Weber, David Lewis, among others.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   456 citations  
  • Legal Paternalism.Joel Feinberg - 1971 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):105 - 124.
    The principle of legal paternalism justifies state coercion to protect individuals from self-inflicted harm, or in its extreme version, to guide them, whether they like it or not, toward their own good. Parents can be expected to justify their interference in the lives of their children on the ground that “daddy knows best.” legal paternalism seems to imply that since the state often can know the interests of individual citizens better than the citizens know them themselves, it stands as a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • John Stuart mill and the harm of pornography.David Dyzenhaus - 1992 - Ethics 102 (3):534-551.
  • The limits of informed consent.K. Davison - 1975 - Journal of Medical Ethics 1 (3):146.
  • Paternalism, part II.David J. Garren - 2007 - Philosophical Books 48 (1):50-59.
  • Paternalism, part I.David J. Garren - 2006 - Philosophical Books 47 (4):334-341.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Coercive Paternalism in Health Care: Against Freedom of Choice.Sarah Conly - 2013 - Public Health Ethics 6 (3):pht025.
    I argue that it can be morally permissible to coerce people into doing what is good for their own health. I discuss recent initiatives in New York City that are designed to take away certain unhealthy options from local citizens, and argue that this does not impose on them in unjustifiable ways. Good paternalistic measures are designed to promote people's long-term goals, and to prevent them from making short-term decisions that interfere with reaching those, and New York's attempts to ban (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Human Life, Action and Ethics: Essays by G.E.M. Anscombe Edited by Mary Geach and Luke Gormally.David Carr - 2006 - Philosophical Books 47 (3):284-287.
  • More on Self-Enslavement and Paternalism in Mill: D. G. Brown.D. G. Brown - 1989 - Utilitas 1 (1):144-150.
  • Mill’s moral theory: Ongoing revisionism.D. G. Brown - 2010 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 9 (1):5-45.
    Revisionist interpretation of Mill needs to be extended to deal with a residue of puzzles about his moral theory and its connection with his theory of liberty. The upshot shows his reinterpretation of his Benthamite tradition as a form of ‘philosophical utilitarianism’; his definition of the art of morality as collective self-defence; his ignoring of maximization in favour of ad hoc dealing in utilities; the central role of his account of the justice of punishment; the marginal role of the internal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Doing Away with Harm.Ben Bradley - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (2):390-412.
  • Harm versus sovereignty: A reply to Ripstein.Colin Bird - 2007 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 35 (2):179–194.
  • Paternalism and Public Policy.Bill New - 1999 - Economics and Philosophy 15 (1):63.
    Wherever a government or state is concerned with the welfare of its citizens, there will probably also exist policies which compel the individual citizen to undertake or abstain from activities which affect that citizen alone. The set of theories behind such policies is collectively known as ‘paternalism’. It is not hard to understand why this term has developed strong pejorative overtones. Policies of this type appear to offend a fundamental tenet of liberal societies: namely, that the individual is best placed (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The role of consent in sado-masochistic practices.Nafsika Athanassoulis - 2002 - Res Publica 8 (2):141-155.
    In 1993 the Law Lords upheld the original conviction of five men under the 1861 Offences Against the Person Act for participating in sado-masochistic practices. Although the five men were fully consenting adults, the Law Lords held that consent did not constitute a defence to acts of violence within a sado-masochistic context. This paper examines the judgements in this case and argues that sado-masochistic practices are no different from the known exceptions cited by the court to the idea that consent (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mill versus paternalism.Richard J. Arneson - 1980 - Ethics 90 (4):470-489.
  • Mill Versus Paternalism.Richard J. Arneson - 1979 - Philosophy Research Archives 5:89-119.
    This paper attempts a defense of John Stuart Mill’s absolute ban against paternalistic restrictions on liberty. Mill’s principle looks more credible once we recognize that some instances of what are thought to be justified instances of paternalism are not instances of paternalism at all—e.g. anti-duelling laws. An interpretation of Mill’s argument is advanced which stresses his commitment to autonomy and his suggestion that exactly the same reasons which favor absolute freedom of speech also favor an absolute prohibition of paternalism. Alternative (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Freedom not to be free: The case of the slavery contract in J. S. mill's on liberty.David Archard - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161):453-465.
  • Freedom not to be free.David Archard - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161):453.
  • J.S. Mill's on Liberty in Focus.John Gray & G. W. Smith (eds.) - 1991 - Routledge.
    This volume brings together J.S. Mills _On Liberty_ and a selection of important essays by such eminent scholars as Isaiah Berlin, Alan Ryan, John Rees, C.L. Ten and Richard Wollheim. As well as providing authoritative commentary upon _On Liberty_, the essays reflect a broader debate about the philosophical foundations of Mill's liberalism, particularly the question of the connection betweenMill's professed utilitarianism and his commitment to individual liberty. Introduced and edited by John Gray and G.W. Smith, the book will be of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mill’s Progressive Principles.David O. Brink - 2013 - Oxford: Oxford University Press UK.
    David O. Brink offers a reconstruction and assessment of John Stuart Mill's contributions to the utilitarian and liberal traditions. Brink defends interpretations of key elements in Mill's moral and political thought, and shows how a perfectionist reading of his conception of happiness has a significant impact on other aspects of his philosophy.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations