Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Punishment: Nonconsequentialism.David Wood - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (6):470-482.
    A companion to ‘Punishment: Consequentialism’, and also ‘Punishment: The Future’, this paper examines various nonconsequentialist attempts to justify punishment, that is, attempts that appeal to claims concerning the innate worth or intrinsic character of punishment, quite apart from any consequential good or benefit punishment may be thought to produce. The paper starts with retributive theories, and turns then to the denunciation and expressive theories, before considering combined communicative–retributive theories.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Punishment: Consequentialism.David Wood - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (6):455-469.
    Punishment involves deliberating harming individuals. How, then, if at all, is it to be justified? This, the first of three papers on the philosophy of punishment (see also 'Punishment: Nonconsequentialism' and 'Punishment: The Future'), examines attempts to justify the practice or institution according to its consequences. One claim is that punishment reduces crime, and hence the resulting harms. Another is that punishment functions to rehabilitate offenders. A third claim is that punishment (or some forms of punishment) can serve to make (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the Relevance of Neuroscience to Criminal Responsibility.Nicole A. Vincent - 2010 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (1):77-98.
    Various authors debate the question of whether neuroscience is relevant to criminal responsibility. However, a plethora of different techniques and technologies, each with their own abilities and drawbacks, lurks beneath the label “neuroscience”; and in criminal law responsibility is not a single, unitary and generic concept, but it is rather a syndrome of at least six different concepts. Consequently, there are at least six different responsibility questions that the criminal law asks—at least one for each responsibility concept—and, I will suggest, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Punishment and repentance.John Tasioulas - 2006 - Philosophy 81 (2):279-322.
    In philosophical writings, the practice of punishment standardly features as a terrain over which comprehensive moral theories—in the main, versions of ‘consequentialism’ and ‘deontology’—have fought a prolonged and inconclusive battle. The grip of this top-down model of the relationship between philosophical theory and punitive practice is so tenacious that even the most seemingly innocent concern with the ‘consequences’ of punishment is often read, if not as an endorsement of consequentialism, then at least as the registering of a consequentialist point. But (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium.Peter Singer - 1974 - The Monist 58 (3):490-517.
    In his book A Theory of Justice, John Rawls introduces and employs the concept of “reflective equilibrium” as a method of testing which of rival moral theories is to be preferred. The introduction of this concept is plainly a significant event for moral philosophy. The criterion by which we decide to reject, say, utilitarianism in favour of a contractual theory of justice is, if anything, even more fundamental than the choice of theory itself, since our choice of moral theory may (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • The failure of retributivism.Russ Shafer-Landau - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 82 (3):289 - 316.
  • Retributivism and desert.Russ Shafer-Landau - 2000 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 81 (2):189–214.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Giving Desert its Due: Social Justice and Legal Theory.Wojciech Sadurski - 1985 - D. Reidel Publishing Company.
    During the last half of the twentieth century, legal philosophy (or legal theory or jurisprudence) has grown significantly. It is no longer the domain of a few isolated scholars in law and philosophy. Hundreds of scholars from diverse fields attend international meetings on the subject. In some universities, large lecture courses of five hundred students or more study it. The primary aim of the Law and Philosophy Library is to present some of the best original work on legal philosophy from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • The claims of reflective equilibrium.Joseph Raz - 1982 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 25 (3):307 – 330.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Without guilt and justice: from decidophobia to autonomy.Walter Arnold Kaufmann - 1973 - New York,: P. H. Wyden.
  • Without Guilt and Justice, From Decidophobia To Autonomy.Walter Kaufmann - 1973 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 34 (2):294-296.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An Eye for an Eye: Proportionality as a Moral Principle of Punishment.Morris J. Fish - 2008 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 28 (1):57-71.
    The lex talionis of the Old Testament has been widely perceived—understandably, but mistakenly—as a barbaric law of retribution in kind. It is better understood as a seminal expression of restraint and proportionality as moral principles of punishment. This has been recognized from the earliest times. Over the intervening centuries, the lex talionis has lost neither its moral significance nor its penal relevance. This is reflected in H.L.A. Hart's synthesis of modern retributivist and utilitarian theories of punishment and, again, in contemporary (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Expressive Function of Punishment.Joel Feinberg - 1965 - The Monist 49 (3):397-423.
  • Social Principles and the Democratic State.Kurt Baier - 1959 - Philosophy 36 (137):251-254.
  • Proportionate Sentencing: Exploring the Principles.Andrew Von Hirsch & Andrew Ashworth - 2005 - Oxford University Press UK.
    The principle that a sentence should be proportionate to the seriousness of the offence remains at the centre of penal practice and scholarly debate. This volume explores highly topical aspects of proportionality theory that require examination and further analysis. von Hirsch and Ashworth explore the relevance of the principle of proportionality to the sentencing of young offenders, the possible reasons for departing from the principle when sentencing dangerous offenders, and the application of the principle to socially deprived offenders. They examine (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Censure and Sanctions.Andrew Von Hirsch - 1996 - Oxford University Press UK.
    A number of jurisdictions, including England and Wales after their adoption of the 1991 Criminal Justice Act, require that sentences be `proportionate' to the severity of the crime. This book, written by the leading architect of `just deserts' sentencing theory, discusses how sentences may be scaled proportionately to the gravity of the crime. Topics dealt with include how the idea of a penal censure justifies proportionate sentences; how a penalty scale should be `anchored' to reduce overall punishment levels; how non-custodial (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Punishment, communication and community.Antony Duff - 2002 - In Derek Matravers & Jonathan E. Pike (eds.), Debates in Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology. Routledge, in Association with the Open University.
    The question "What can justify criminal punishment ?" becomes especially insistent at times, like our own, of penal crisis, when serious doubts are raised not only about the justice or efficacy of particular modes of punishment, but about the very legitimacy of the whole penal system. Recent theorizing about punishment offers a variety of answers to that question-answers that try to make plausible sense of the idea that punishment is justified as being deserved for past crimes; answers that try to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • The Subjective Experience of Punishment.Adam J. Kolber - 2009 - Columbia Law Review 109:182.
    Suppose two people commit the same crime and are sentenced to equal terms in the same prison facility. I argue that they have identical punishments in name only. One may experience incarceration as challenging but tolerable while the other is thoroughly tormented by it. Even though people vary substantially in their experiences of punishment, our sentencing laws pay little attention to such differences. I make two central claims: First, a successful justification of punishment must take account of offenders' subjective experiences (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Censure and Sanctions.Andrew Von Hirsch - 1996 - Law and Philosophy 15 (4):407-415.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Intuition and Moral Philosophy.William H. Shaw - 1980 - American Philosophical Quarterly 17 (2):127 - 134.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations