Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A theory of justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4021 citations  
  • Plato's Unnatural Teleology.James Lennox - 1985 - In Dominic J. O'Meara (ed.), Platonic Investigations. Catholic University of Amer Press. pp. 195-218.
  • Identity and Essence.Baruch A. Brody - 1980 - Princeton University Press.
    Baruch Brody contends that the fundamental assumption on which the tradition is based is erroneous and that once this assumption is shown to be in error, all philosophical problems in this area have to be rethought. Originally published in 1980. The Princeton Legacy Library uses the latest print-on-demand technology to again make available previously out-of-print books from the distinguished backlist of Princeton University Press. These editions preserve the original texts of these important books while presenting them in durable paperback and (...)
    No categories
  • Teleological Explanations.Andrew Woodfield & Larry Wright - 1978 - Philosophical Quarterly 28 (110):86.
  • Teleology.Anthony Manser - 1977 - Philosophical Quarterly 27 (108):275-277.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Teleology and the logical structure of function statements.William C. Wimsatt - 1972 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 3 (1):1-80.
  • The good man and the good for man in Aristotle's ethics.Kathleen V. Wilkes - 1978 - Mind 87 (348):553-571.
    It is notorious that Aristotle gives two distinct and seemingly irreconcilable versions of man's eudaimonia in the Nicomachean Ethics. These offer conflicting accounts not only of what the good man should do, but also of what it is good for a man to do. This paper discusses the incompatibility of these two pictures of eudaimonia, and explores the extent to which the notions of 'the life of a good man' and 'the life good for a man' can be successfully united (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Function Argument.Jennifer Whiting - 1988 - Ancient Philosophy 8 (1):33-48.
  • Aristotle’s Function Argument.Jennifer Whiting - 1988 - Ancient Philosophy 8 (1):33-48.
  • Modern Ethics, Teleology, and the Love of Self.Henry B. Veatch - 1992 - The Monist 75 (1):52-70.
    “Modern ethics,” so-called, has only in the most recent years come under some very sharp and telling, not to say even devastating, criticism. And what is it that one should understand by this term, “modern ethics”? Well, it is a term used largely by very recent critics to designate that whole tradition in ethics, in part utilitarian and in part Kantian in character, that has quite dominated the study of ethics, at least in Anglo-American philosophy, for upwards of three-quarters of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Explanation of Behavior.W. D. Joske - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 27 (1):135-137.
  • Aristotle on loving another for his own sake.Kelly Rogers - 1994 - Phronesis 39 (3):291-302.
  • The Significance for Cognitive Realism of the Thought of John Poinsot.Douglas B. Rasmussen - 1994 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 68 (3):409-424.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Quine and Aristotelian Essentialism.Douglas B. Rasmussen - 1984 - New Scholasticism 58 (3):316-335.
  • Radical Realism. [REVIEW]Jude P. Dougherty - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (3):723-725.
    Edward Pols long ago established himself as a philosopher of first rank. His carefully wrought studies have succeeded each other with regularity, The Recognition of Reason, Whitehead’s Metaphysics, Meditation on a Prisoner: Towards Understanding Action and Mind, and The Acts of Our Being: A Reflection on Agency and Responsibility. While clearly within a tradition that can be traced through modernity to the middle ages and to classical philosophy, Pols is no slave to the past. He recognizes the perennial character of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on Eudaimonia1.Thomas Nagel - 1972 - Phronesis 17 (3):252-259.
  • Ultimate ends in practical reasoning: Aquinas's aristotelian moral psychology and Anscombe's fallacy.Scott MacDonald - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (1):31-66.
  • Moral individualism: Agent-relativity and deontic restraints*: Eric Mack.Eric Mack - 1989 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1):81-111.
    My goal in this essay is to say something helpful about the philosophical foundations of deontic restraints, i.e., moral restraints on actions that are, roughly speaking, grounded in the wrongful character of the actions themselves and not merely in the disvalue of their results. An account of deontic restraints will be formulated and offered against the backdrop of three related, but broader, contrasts or puzzles within moral theory. The plausibility of this account of deontic restraints rests in part on how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • James Rachels on Kant’s Basic Idea.Joseph L. Lombardi - 1997 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 71 (1):53-58.
  • Tradition and Reason in the History of Ethics: T. H. IRWIN.T. H. Irwin - 1989 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1):45-68.
    Students of the history of ethics sometimes find themselves tempted by moderate or extreme versions of an approach that might roughly be called ‘historicist’. This temptation may result from the difficulties of approaching historical texts from a ‘narrowly philosophical’ point of view. We may begin, for instance, by wanting to know what Aristotle has to say about ‘the problems of ethics’, so that we can compare his views with those of Aquinas, Hume, Kant, Sidgwick, and Rawls, and then decide what (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Freedom of Mind.Stuart Hampshire - unknown
    This is the text of The Lindley Lecture for 1961, given by Stuart Hampshire, a British philosopher.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A fallacy in aristotle’s argument about the good.P. Glassen - 1957 - Philosophical Quarterly 7 (29):319-322.
  • Reason and Human Good in Aristotle.Michael Woods - 1978 - Philosophical Quarterly 28 (110):75-77.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Biological Teleology: Questions and Explanations.Robert N. Brandon - 1981 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 12 (2):91.
    This paper gives an account of evolutionary explanations in biology. Briefly, the explanations I am primarily concerned with are explanations of adaptations. These explanations are contrasted with other nonteleological evolutionary explanations. The distinction is made by distinguishing the different kinds of questions these different explanations serve to answer. The sense in which explanations of adaptations are teleological is spelled out.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • The Crooked Timber of Humanity: Chapters in the History of Ideas.Leon Pompa - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (165):500-502.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology.Francisco J. Ayala - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (1):1-15.
    The ultimate source of explanation in biology is the principle of natural selection. Natural selection means differential reproduction of genes and gene combinations. It is a mechanistic process which accounts for the existence in living organisms of end-directed structures and processes. It is argued that teleological explanations in biology are not only acceptable but indeed indispensable. There are at least three categories of biological phenomena where teleological explanations are appropriate.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • Swimming Against the Current in Contemporary Philosophy: Occasional Essays and Papers.Henry Babcock Veatch - 1990 - Catholic University of Amer Press.
  • After Virtue.A. MacIntyre - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46 (1):169-171.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1570 citations  
  • Human Rights. Fact or Fancy?Henry B. Veatch - 1985 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 25 (2):123-125.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Epistemology and Moral Knowledge.Tibor R. Machan - 1982 - Review of Metaphysics 36 (1):23 - 49.
    It is argued that a wrongheaded model of what a theory of knowledge must satisfy has engendered unjustified skepticism about knowledge and moral knowledge in particular. A contextualist conception of knowledge is sketched and defended and it is then argued that in terms of such an idea of what it is to know something the prospects for moral and political knowledge are significantly improved.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Aristotle on Rationality in Action.Fred D. Miller - 1984 - Review of Metaphysics 37 (3):499 - 520.
    WHEN Aristotle takes up the task of establishing the foundations of ethics in the Nicomachean Ethics, he understands this task in a quite different way from many modern moral philosophers. For one thing, he explicitly distinguishes inquiries such as ethics and politics from more precise disciplines such as mathematics, and emphasizes that their end is action rather than knowledge. Moreover, he differs from many modern ethicists in the importance which he assigns to knowledge of what to do in a concrete (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Human Good.Richard KRAUT - 1989 - Ethics 101 (2):382-391.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Whose Justice? Which Rationality?Alasdair Macintyre - 1988 - Journal of Religious Ethics 16 (2):363-363.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   388 citations