Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The "Hart-Dworkin" debate : a short guide for the perplexed.Scott J. Shapiro - 2007 - In Arthur Ripstein (ed.), Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge University Press. pp. 22--49.
    For the past four decades, Anglo-American legal philosophy has been preoccupied – some might say obsessed – with something called the “Hart-Dworkin” debate. Since the appearance in 1967 of “The Model of Rules I,” Ronald Dworkin’s seminal critique of H.L.A. Hart’s theory of legal positivism, countless books and articles have been written either defending Hart against Dworkin’s objections or defending Dworkin against Hart’s defenders. My purpose in this essay is not to declare an ultimate victor; rather it is to identify (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Dworkin's Theoretical Disagreement Argument.Barbara Baum Levenbook - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (1):1-9.
    Dworkin's theoretical disagreement argument, developed in Law's Empire, is presented in that work as the motivator for his interpretive account of law. Like Dworkin's earlier arguments critical of legal positivism, the argument from theoretical disagreement has generated a lively exchange with legal positivists. It has motivated three of them to develop innovative positivist positions. In its original guise, the argument from theoretical disagreement is presented as ‘the semantic sting argument’. However, the argument from theoretical disagreement has more than one version. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Jurisprudential Theories and First‐Order Legal Judgments.Kevin Toh - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (5):457-471.
    The nature of the relation between jurisprudential theories and first-order legal judgments is a strangely uncontroversial matter in contemporary legal philosophy. There is one dominant conception of the relation according to which jurisprudential theories are second-order or meta-legal theories that specify the ultimate grounds of first-order legal judgments. According to this conception, difficult first-order legal disputes are to be resolved by jurisprudential theorizing. According to an alternative conception that Ronald Dworkin has influentially advocated, jurisprudential theories are not second-order theories about (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics.Henry Shue - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):453.
    Raz's method is as unusual, and as admirable, as the substance of his sometimes rather unfortunately labeled "perfectionist liberalism"—unfortunate because "it is not perfectionist in the more ordinary sense of the term" in that it recognizes that "imperfect ways of life may be the best which is possible for people" and "is strongly pluralistic", while understanding its fundamental value of well-being as the active and autonomous making of a life of one's own. Raz's approach is simultaneously alert to the complexity (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • “Protestant” interpretation and social practices.Gerald Postema - 1987 - Law and Philosophy 6 (3):283 - 319.
    In general, offers a good discussion of Dworkin's theory of interpretation. Postema is critically concerned with whether Dworkin commits himself to individualistic and privatistic sense of interpretation and how Dworkin articulates the logical independency of pre-interpretive paradigm instances or social facts which form the object of interpretation and the end which is interpretively posited in the act of interpretation. Criticisms, for the most part, appear to be compatible with Dworkin's overall theory and may simply be additional explication of the character (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Dworkin on the Semantics of Legal and Political Concepts.Dennis M. Patterson - 2006 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 (3):545-557.
    In a recent comment on H.L.A. Hart’s ‘Postscript’ to The Concept of Law, Ronald Dworkin claims that the meaning of legal and political concepts may be understood by analogy to the meaning of natural kind concepts like ‘tiger’, ‘gold’ and ‘water’. This article questions the efficacy of Dworkin’s claims by challenging the use of natural kinds as the basis for a semantic theory of legal and political concepts. Additionally, in matters of value there is no methodological equivalent to the scientific (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Interpretive Turn. [REVIEW]Ken Kress - 1987 - Ethics 97 (4):834-860.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   254 citations  
  • Hart's Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy.Ronald Dworkin - 2004 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24 (1):1-37.
    Several years ago I prepared a point-by-point response to this postscript as a working paper for the NYU Colloquium in Legal, Moral and Political Philosophy. I have not yet published that paper, but I understand that copies of it are in circulation. I do not intend to recapitulate the arguments of that working paper, but instead to concentrate on one aspect of Hart's Postscript, which is his defence of Archimedean jurisprudence. I shall have something to say about his own legal (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Is the Rule of Recognition Really a Conventional Rule?Julie Dickson - 2007 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (3):373-402.
    In this article I examine the view, common amongst several contemporary legal positivists, that rules of recognition are to be understood as conventional rules of some kind. The article opens with a discussion of H.L.A. Hart's original account of the rule of recognition in the 1st edn of The Concept of Law and argues that Hart did not view the rule of recognition as a conventional rule in that account. I then discuss Hart's apparent turn towards a conventionalist understanding of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Concept of Law.Stuart M. Brown - 1963 - Philosophical Review 72 (2):250.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   366 citations  
  • Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity.Gilbert Harman & Judith Jarvis Thomson - 1996 - Philosophy 71 (278):622-624.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  • Taking Rights Seriously.Ronald Dworkin - 1979 - Ethics 90 (1):121-130.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   456 citations  
  • Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity.Gilbert Harman & Judith Jarvis Thomson - 1996 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 50 (4):654-658.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2231 citations  
  • On Certainty.Ludwig Wittgenstein, G. E. M. Anscombe, G. H. Von Wright & Denis Paul - 1972 - Mind 81 (323):453-457.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Taking Rights Seriously.Ronald Dworkin - 1979 - Mind 88 (350):305-309.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   503 citations  
  • In Defense of Legal Positivism: Law without Trimmings.Matthew Kramer - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (200):422-425.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations