Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. On Axiomatizing Shramko-Wansing’s Logic.Sergei P. Odintsov - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (3):407-428.
    This work treats the problem of axiomatizing the truth and falsity consequence relations, ⊨ t and ⊨ f, determined via truth and falsity orderings on the trilattice SIXTEEN 3 (Shramko and Wansing, 2005). The approach is based on a representation of SIXTEEN 3 as a twist-structure over the two-element Boolean algebra.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Bilattices and the Semantics of Logic Programming.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    Bilattices, due to M. Ginsberg, are a family of truth value spaces that allow elegantly for missing or conflicting information. The simplest example is Belnap’s four-valued logic, based on classical two-valued logic. Among other examples are those based on finite many-valued logics, and on probabilistic valued logic. A fixed point semantics is developed for logic programming, allowing any bilattice as the space of truth values. The mathematics is little more complex than in the classical two-valued setting, but the result provides (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Generalized truth values.: A reply to Dubois.Heinrich Wansing & Nuel Belnap - 2010 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 18 (6):921-935.
  • Notes on N-lattices and constructive logic with strong negation.D. Vakarelov - 1977 - Studia Logica 36 (1-2):109-125.
  • Some Useful 16-Valued Logics: How a Computer Network Should Think.Yaroslav Shramko & Heinrich Wansing - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (2):121-153.
    In Belnap's useful 4-valued logic, the set 2 = {T, F} of classical truth values is generalized to the set 4 = ������(2) = {Ø, {T}, {F}, {T, F}}. In the present paper, we argue in favor of extending this process to the set 16 = ᵍ (4) (and beyond). It turns out that this generalization is well-motivated and leads from the bilattice FOUR₂ with an information and a truth-and-falsity ordering to another algebraic structure, namely the trilattice SIXTEEN₃ with an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Hyper-contradictions, generalized truth values and logics of truth and falsehood.Yaroslav Shramko & Heinrich Wansing - 2006 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 15 (4):403-424.
    In Philosophical Logic, the Liar Paradox has been used to motivate the introduction of both truth value gaps and truth value gluts. Moreover, in the light of “revenge Liar” arguments, also higher-order combinations of generalized truth values have been suggested to account for so-called hyper-contradictions. In the present paper, Graham Priest's treatment of generalized truth values is scrutinized and compared with another strategy of generalizing the set of classical truth values and defining an entailment relation on the resulting sets of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Representation of interlaced trilattices.Umberto Rivieccio - 2013 - Journal of Applied Logic 11 (2):174-189.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On Axiomatizing Shramko-Wansing’s Logic.Sergei P. Odintsov - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (3):407 - 428.
    This work treats the problem of axiomatizing the truth and falsity consequence relations, $ \vDash _t $ and $ \vDash _f $, determined via truth and falsity orderings on the trilattice SIXTEEN₃. The approach is based on a representation of SIXTEEN₃ as a twist-structure over the two-element Boolean algebra.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • On extensions of intermediate logics by strong negation.Marcus Kracht - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (1):49-73.
    In this paper we will study the properties of the least extension n(Λ) of a given intermediate logic Λ by a strong negation. It is shown that the mapping from Λ to n(Λ) is a homomorphism of complete lattices, preserving and reflecting finite model property, frame-completeness, interpolation and decidability. A general characterization of those constructive logics is given which are of the form n(Λ). This summarizes results that can be found already in [13, 14] and [4]. Furthermore, we determine the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Knowledge, Uncertainty and Ignorance in Logic: Bilattices and beyond.George Gargov - 1999 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 9 (2-3):195-283.
    ABSTRACT In the paper we present a survey of some approaches to the semantics of many-valued propositional systems. These approaches are inspired on one hand by classical problems in the investigations of logical aspects of epistemic activity: knowledge and truth, contradictions, beliefs, reliability of data, etc. On the other hand they reflect contemporary concerns of researchers in Artificial Intelligence (and Cognitive Science in general) with inferences drawn from imperfect information, even from total ignorance. We treat the mathematical apparatus that has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • A theory of truth that prefers falsehood.Melvin Fitting - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (5):477-500.
    We introduce a subclass of Kripke's fixed points in which falsehood is the preferred truth value. In all of these the truthteller evaluates to false, while the liar evaluates to undefined (or overdefined). The mathematical structure of this family of fixed points is investigated and is shown to have many nice features. It is noted that a similar class of fixed points, preferring truth, can also be studied. The notion of intrinsic is shown to relativize to these two subclasses. The (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Reasoning with logical bilattices.Ofer Arieli & Arnon Avron - 1996 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5 (1):25--63.
    The notion of bilattice was introduced by Ginsberg, and further examined by Fitting, as a general framework for many applications. In the present paper we develop proof systems, which correspond to bilattices in an essential way. For this goal we introduce the notion of logical bilattices. We also show how they can be used for efficient inferences from possibly inconsistent data. For this we incorporate certain ideas of Kifer and Lozinskii, which happen to suit well the context of our work. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • Fixpoint Semantics for Logic Programming A Survey.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    The variety of semantical approaches that have been invented for logic programs is quite broad, drawing on classical and many-valued logic, lattice theory, game theory, and topology. One source of this richness is the inherent non-monotonicity of its negation, something that does not have close parallels with the machinery of other programming paradigms. Nonetheless, much of the work on logic programming semantics seems to exist side by side with similar work done for imperative and functional programming, with relatively minimal contact (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Multivalued logics: a uniform approach to reasoning in AI.Matthew Ginsberg - 1988 - Computer Intelligence 4 (1):256--316.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • A useful four-valued logic.N. D. Belnap - 1977 - In J. M. Dunn & G. Epstein (eds.), Modern Uses of Multiple-Valued Logic. D. Reidel.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   259 citations  
  • The Family of Stable Models.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    The family of all stable models for a logic program has a surprisingly simple overall structure, once two naturally occurring orderings are made explicit. In a so-called knowledge ordering based on degree of definedness, every logic program P has a smallest stable model, sk P — it is the well-founded model. There is also a dual largest stable model, S k P, which has not been considered before. There is another ordering based on degree of truth. Taking the meet and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations