Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Risk, fear, blame, shame and the regulation of public safety.Jonathan Wolff - 2006 - Economics and Philosophy 22 (3):409-427.
    The question of when people may impose risks on each other is of fundamental moral importance. Forms of “quantified risk assessment,” especially risk cost-benefit analysis, provide one powerful approach to providing a systematic answer. It is also well known that such techniques can show that existing resources could be used more effectively to reduce risk overall. Thus it is often argued that some current practices are irrational. On the other hand critics of quantified risk assessment argue that it cannot adequately (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Preference, rationality, and risk taking.Eric Von Magnus - 1984 - Ethics 94 (4):637-648.
  • Cost‐benefit analysis and the environment.Cass R. Sunstein - 2005 - Ethics 115 (2):351-385.
  • Consulting scientist and engineer liability: A survey of relevant law.Margaret N. Strand - 1997 - Science and Engineering Ethics 3 (4):357-394.
    This paper is a survey of the law in the United States which is applicable to consulting scientists and engineers. Based on the body of law which has developed for the construction industry and professional “advice-givers” such as attorneys, medical doctors and accountants, the paper reviews professional responsibilities in the areas of Common Law Torts. Common Law Contracts, certain U.S. Federal and State Statutes and the protection of sensitive information.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Technological risk and small probabilities.Kristin Shrader-Frechette - 1985 - Journal of Business Ethics 4 (6):431 - 445.
    Many scientists, businessmen, and government regulators believe that the criteria for acceptable societal risk are too stringent. Those who subscribe to this belief often accept the view which I call the probability-threshold position. Proponents of this stance maintain that society ought to ignore very small risks, i.e., those causing an average annual probability of fatality of less than 10–6.After examining the three major views in the risk-evaluation debate, viz., the probability-threshold position, the zero-risk position, and the weighted-risk position, I focus (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Trading jobs for health: Ionizing radiation, occupational ethics, and the welfare argument.Kristin Shrader-Frechette - 2002 - Science and Engineering Ethics 8 (2):139-154.
    Blue-collar workers throughout the world generally face higher levels of pollution than the public and are unable to control many health risks that employers impose on them. Economists tend to justify these risky workplaces on the grounds of the compensating wage differential (CWD). The CWD, or hazard-pay premium, is the alleged increment in wages, all things being equal, that workers in hazardous environments receive. According to this theory, employees trade safety for money on the job market, even though they realize (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mortgaging the future: Dumping ethics with nuclear waste.Kristin Shrader-Frechette - 2005 - Science and Engineering Ethics 11 (4):518-520.
    On August 22, 2005 the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency issued proposed new regulations for radiation releases from the planned permanent U.S. nuclear-waste repository in Yucca Mountain, Nevada. The goal of the new standards is to provide public-health protection for the next million years — even though everyone admits that the radioactive wastes will leak. Regulations now guarantee individual and equal protection against all radiation exposures above the legal limit. Instead E.P.A. recommended different radiation exposure-limits for different time periods. It also (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Data trimming, nuclear emissions, and climate change.Kristin Sharon Shrader-Frechette - 2009 - Science and Engineering Ethics 15 (1):19-23.
    Ethics requires good science. Many scientists, government leaders, and industry representatives support tripling of global-nuclear-energy capacity on the grounds that nuclear fission is “carbon free” and “releases no greenhouse gases.” However, such claims are scientifically questionable (and thus likely to lead to ethically questionable energy choices) for at least 3 reasons. (i) They rely on trimming the data on nuclear greenhouse-gas emissions (GHGE), perhaps in part because flawed Kyoto Protocol conventions require no full nuclear-fuel-cycle assessment of carbon content. (ii) They (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Distribution and emergency.Jennifer Rubenstein - 2007 - Journal of Political Philosophy 15 (3):296–320.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Towards a right against risking.John Oberdiek - 2009 - Law and Philosophy 28 (4):367 - 392.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The acceptability and the tolerability of societal risks: A capabilities-based approach.Colleen Murphy & Paolo Gardoni - 2008 - Science and Engineering Ethics 14 (1):77-92.
    In this paper, we present a Capabilities -based Approach to the acceptability and the tolerability of risks posed by natural and man-made hazards. We argue that judgments about the acceptability and/or tolerability of such risks should be based on an evaluation of the likely societal impact of potential hazards, defined in terms of the expected changes in the capabilities of individuals. Capabilities refer to the functionings, or valuable doings and beings, individuals are able to achieve given available personal, material, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Determining public policy and resource allocation priorities for mitigating natural hazards: A capabilities-based approach.Colleen Murphy & Paolo Gardoni - 2007 - Science and Engineering Ethics 13 (4):489-504.
    This paper proposes a Capabilities -based Approach to guide hazard mitigation efforts. First, a discussion is provided of the criteria that should be met by an adequate framework for formulating public policy and allocating resources. This paper shows why a common decision-aiding tool, Cost-benefit Analysis, fails to fulfill such criteria. A Capabilities -based Approach to hazard mitigation is then presented, drawing on the framework originally developed in the context of development economics and policy. The focus of a Capabilities -based Approach (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Justice and the assignment of the intergenerational costs of climate change.Darrel Moellendorf - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (2):204-224.
  • Rights and Risk.Dennis McKerlie - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (2):239 - 251.
    Robert Nozick has suggested that risky actions are a problem for a moral view based on rights. We ordinarily think that some actions are too dangerous to be permissible, taking into account both the harm risked and the degree of the risk. Other actions, although they run some risk of serious harm, are thought permissible. The problem is to draw this distinction in a principled way by looking to rights.I think that Nozick's argument about risk can be answered but a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Preference, Rationality, and Risk Taking.Eric Magnuvons - 1984 - Ethics 94 (4):637-.
  • The precautionary principle: Scientific uncertainty and type I and type II errors. [REVIEW]John Lemons, Kristin Shrader-Frechette & Carl Cranor - 1997 - Foundations of Science 2 (2):207-236.
    We provide examples of the extent and nature of environmental and human health problems and show why in the United States prevailing scientific and legal burden of proof requirements usually cannot be met because of the pervasiveness of scientific uncertainty. We also provide examples of how may assumptions, judgments, evaluations, and inferences in scientific methods are value-laden and that when this is not recognized results of studies will appear to be more factual and value-neutral than warranted. Further, we show that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Fairness, Responsibility, and Climate Change.Paul G. Harris - 2003 - Ethics and International Affairs 17 (1):149-156.
    Most literature on the ethics of global warming focuses on the obligations of industrialized states to reduce their emissions of greenhouse gases and to help poor countries do likewise. These books are no exception, arguing that the issue is a matter of international justice and equity.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Philosophical Perspectives on Risk.Sven Ove Hansson - 2004 - Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 8 (1):10-35.
    In non-technical contexts, the word “risk” refers, often rather vaguely, to situations in which it is possible but not certain that some undesirable event will occur. In technical contexts, the word has many uses and specialized meanings. The most common ones are the following.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Ethics and global climate change.Stephen M. Gardiner - 2004 - Ethics 114 (3):555-600.
    Very few moral philosophers have written on climate change.1 This is puzzling, for several reasons. First, many politicians and policy makers claim that climate change is not only the most serious environmental problem currently facing the world, but also one of the most important international problems per se.2 Second, many of those working in other disciplines describe climate change as fundamentally an ethical issue.3.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Some moral issues in risk assessment.Carl F. Cranor - 1990 - Ethics 101 (1):123-143.
  • Scientific and legal standards of statistical evidence in toxic tort and discrimination suits.Carl Cranor & Kurt Nutting - 1990 - Law and Philosophy 9 (2):115 - 156.
    Many legal disputes turn on scientific, especially statistical, evidence. Traditionally scientists have accepted only that statistical evidence which satisfies a 95 percent (or 99 percent) rule — that is, only evidence which has less than five percent (or one percent) probability of resulting from chance.The rationale for this rule is the reluctance of scientists to accept anything less than the best-supported new knowledge. The rule reflects the internal needs of scientific practice. However, when uncritically adopted as a rule for admitting (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Climate change and the future: Discounting for time, wealth, and risk.Simon Caney - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (2):163-186.
    This paper examines explore the issues of intergenerational equity raised by climate change. A number of different reasons have been suggested as to why current generations may legitimately favor devoting resources to contemporaries rather than to future generations. These - either individually or jointly - challenge the case for combating climate change. In this paper, I distinguish between three different kinds of reason for favoring contemporaries. I argue that none of these arguments is persuasive. My answer in each case appeals (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Against Beck: In defence of risk analysis.Scott Campbell & Greg Currie - 2006 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (2):149-172.
    For more than 10 years, Ulrich Beck has dominated discussion of risk issues in the social sciences. We argue that Beck's criticisms of the theory and practise of risk analysis are groundless. His understanding of what risk is is badly flawed. His attempt to identify risk and risk perception fails. He misunderstands and distorts the use of probability in risk analysis. His comments about the insurance industry show that he does not understand some of the basics of that industry. And (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things.Jane Bennett - 2010 - Durham: Duke University Press.
    In _Vibrant Matter_ the political theorist Jane Bennett, renowned for her work on nature, ethics, and affect, shifts her focus from the human experience of things to things themselves. Bennett argues that political theory needs to do a better job of recognizing the active participation of nonhuman forces in events. Toward that end, she theorizes a “vital materiality” that runs through and across bodies, both human and nonhuman. Bennett explores how political analyses of public events might change were we to (...)
  • Philosophy of technology.Maarten Franssen - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Risk.Sven Ove Hansson - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Theories of tort law.Jules L. Coleman - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Irreconcilable differences? The troubled marriage of science and law.Susan Haack - 2009 - Law and Contemporary Problems 72 (1).
    Because its business is to resolve disputed issues, the law very often calls on those fields of science where the pressure of commercial interests is most severe. Because the legal system aspires to handle disputes promptly, the scientific questions to which it seeks answers will often be those for which all the evidence is not yet in. Because of its case-specificity, the legal system often demands answers of a kind science is not well-equipped to supply; and, for related reasons, constitutes (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Philosophy of Tort Law.Arthur Ripstein - 2002 - In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophy of Tort Law.Arthur Ripstein - 2002 - In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence & Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations