Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Prospects for a sound stage 3 of cosmological arguments.Jerome Gellman - 2000 - Religious Studies 36 (2):195-201.
    Recently, "Religious Studies" published an article by Richard Gale and Alexander Pruss, arguing that there exists a necessary being who is a creator of the world. Building on their argument, I argue that, assuming that there is exactly one creator, that creator is essentially omnipotent.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Leibnizian Cosmological Argument.Alexander R. Pruss - 2009 - In William Lane Craig & J. P. Moreland (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 24–100.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction The PSR Nonlocal CPs Toward a First Cause The Gap Problem Conclusions and Further Research References.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The Existence of God.Richard Swinburne - 1979 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Substantially re-written and updated, this edition of 'The Existence of God' presents arguments such as the existence of the laws of nature, 'fine-tuning' of the universe, moral awareness and evidence of miracles, to prove the case that there is a God.
    No categories
  • A new critique of theological interpretations of physical cosmology.A. Grünbaum - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (1):1-43.
    This paper is a sequel to my 'Theological Misinterpretations of Current Physical Cosmology' (Foundations of Physics [1996], 26 (4); revised in Philo [1998], 1 (1)). There I argued that the Big Bang models of (classical) general relativity theory, as well as the original 1948 versions of the steady state cosmology, are each logically incompatible with the time-honored theological doctrine that perpetual divine creation ('creatio continuans') is required in each of these two theorized worlds. Furthermore, I challenged the perennial theological doctrine (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Some Reflections on Richard Swinburne's Argument from Design.Mark Wynn - 1993 - Religious Studies 29 (3):325 - 335.
    In his book The Existence of God , Professor Swinburne develops a cumulative case for theism. As part of this case, he presents two forms of the argument from design, one form taking as its premise the fact of spatial order, the other proceeding from the fact of temporal order. In this paper, I shall concern myself with the second of these arguments; that is, in Swinburne's terms, I shall concern myself with the argument from regularities of succession.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • God As the Simplest Explanation of the Universe.Richard Swinburne - 2010 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 2 (1):1 - 24.
    Inanimate explanation is to be analysed in terms of substances having powers and liabilities to exercise their powers under certain conditions; while personal explanation is to be analysed in terms of persons, their beliefs, powers, and purposes. A crucial criterion for an explanation being probably true is that it is (among explanations leading us to expect the data) the simplest one. Simplicity is a matter of few substances, few kinds of substances, few properties (including powers and liabilities), few kinds of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Swinburne's explanation of the universe. [REVIEW]Quentin Smith - 1998 - Religious Studies 34 (1):91-102.
    Swinburne's Is There A God? presents a brief, updated version of his book, The Existence of God, in which Swinburne argued that criteria used in scientific reasoning could be used to argue that God probably exists. This new book is designed for a wider audience than professional philosophers. Nonetheless, there is much that is new and of interest to philosophers in Is There a God? For example, there is a discussion of Stephen Hawking's cosmology, some new ideas in the philosophy (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Review: Swinburne's Explanation of the Universe. [REVIEW]Quentin Smith - 1998 - Religious Studies 34 (1):91 - 102.
    Richard Swinburne, IsThereaGod? Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996, pp. vii+144.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Argument from Silence.Timothy McGrew - 2014 - Acta Analytica 29 (2):215-228.
    The argument from silence is a pattern of reasoning in which the failure of a known source to mention a particular fact or event is used as the ground of an inference, usually to the conclusion that the supposed fact is untrue or the supposed event did not actually happen. Such arguments are widely used in historical work, but they are also widely contested. This paper surveys some inadequate attempts to model this sort of argument, offers a new analysis using (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The evil-god challenge.Stephen Law - 2010 - Religious Studies 46 (3):353 - 373.
    This paper develops a challenge to theism. The challenge is to explain why the hypothesis that there exists an omnipotent, omniscient and all-good god should be considered significantly more reasonable than the hypothesis that there exists an omnipotent, omniscient and all-evil god. Theists typically dismiss the evil-god hypothesis out of hand because of the problem of good–there is surely too much good in the world for it to be the creation of such a being. But then why doesn't the problem (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Richard Swinburne's argument to the simplicity of God via the infinite.Jeremy Gwiazda - 2009 - Religious Studies 45 (4):487-493.
    In ’The Coherence of Theism’ Richard Swinburne writes that a person cannot be omniscient and perfectly free. In ’The Existence of God’ Swinburne writes that God is a person who is omniscient and perfectly free. There is a straightforward reason why the two passages are not in tension, but recognition of this reason raises a problem for Swinburne’s argument in ’The Existence of God’ (the conclusion of which is that God likely exists). In this paper I present the problem for (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Richard Swinburne, the existence of God, and principle P.Jeremy Gwiazda - 2009 - Sophia 48 (4):393-398.
    Swinburne relies on principle P in The Existence of God to argue that God is simple and thus likely to exist. In this paper, I argue that Swinburne does not support P. In particular, his arguments from mathematical simplicity and scientists’ preferences both fail. Given the central role P plays in Swinburne’s overall argument in The Existence of God , I conclude that Swinburne should further support P if his argument that God likely exists is to be persuasive.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Simplicity and Theology.Don Fawkes & Tom Smythe - 1996 - Religious Studies 32 (2):259 - 270.
    Richard Swinburne has given a defense of arguments for the existence of God (and in particular of teleological arguments) in his book "The Existence of God" (1979/1991). This paper argues that such theistic arguments fail, and poses some general problems for theistic arguments. Swinburne's use of a principle of simplicity is not given adequate justification and, if justified, works against theism. There are adequate rebuttals to Swinburne's arguments that depend upon there being few particles of basic physics, universal laws of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A finite God reconsidered.Frank B. Dilley - 2000 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 47 (1):29-41.
  • Antitheism: A reflection.Christopher New - 1993 - Ratio 6 (1):36-43.
    Why is there no sustained tradition of argument concerning the existence of a supreme (omniscient and omnipotent) being who is perfectly evil, as there is about one who is perfectly good? Arguments which are reflections of the ontological, cosmological and teleological arguments, and arguments based on personal experience or the occurrence of antimiracles (harmful events not explicable by science) could have provided at least as good grounds for belief in such a being (ie for antitheism) as their originals in fact (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Cacodaemony.Steven M. Cahn - 1982 - In Steven M. Cahn & David Shatz (eds.), Analysis. Oxford University Press. pp. 69 - 73.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hume's chief objection to natural theology.M. C. Bradley - 2007 - Religious Studies 43 (3):249-270.
    In the Dialogues Hume attaches great importance to an objection to the design argument which states, negatively, that from phenomena which embody evil as well as good there can be no analogical inference to the morally perfect deity of traditional theism and, positively, that the proper conclusion as regards moral character is an indifferent designer. The first section of this paper sets out Hume's points, and the next three offer an updating of Hume's objection which will apply to Swinburne's Bayesian (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • God, the Demon, and the Status of Theodicies.Edward Stein - 1990 - American Philosophical Quarterly 27 (2):163 - 167.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations