Switch to: Citations

References in:

Living Words: Meaning Underdetermination and the Dynamic Lexicon

Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press (2014)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use.Noam Chomsky - 1986 - Prager. Edited by Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel.
    Attempts to indentify the fundamental concepts of language, argues that the study of language reveals hidden facts about the mind, and looks at the impact of propaganda.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   695 citations  
  • Truth and meaning.Donald Davidson - 1967 - Synthese 17 (1):304-323.
  • Truth and meaning.Donald Davidson - 1967 - Synthese 17 (1):304-323.
  • Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1956 - Oxford: Macmillan. Edited by G. E. M. Anscombe, Rush Rhees & G. H. von Wright.
    Wittgenstein's work remains, undeniably, now, that off one of those few philosophers who will be read by all future generations.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • I do not exist.Peter K. Unger - 1979 - In Graham Macdonald (ed.), Perception and Identity. Cornell University Press.
  • Can there be vague objects?Gareth Evans - 2004 - In Tim Crane & Katalin Farkas (eds.), Metaphysics: A Guide and Anthology. Oxford University Press UK.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   152 citations  
  • Words without Meaning.Christopher Gauker - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2):480-483.
  • Material Beings.Peter Van Inwagen - 1990 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    According to Peter van Inwagen, visible inanimate objects do not, strictly speaking, exist. In defending this controversial thesis, he offers fresh insights on such topics as personal identity, commonsense belief, existence over time, the phenomenon of vagueness, and the relation between metaphysics and ordinary language.
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. Quine - 1951 - [Longmans, Green].
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1206 citations  
  • Fuzzy Sets.Lofti A. Zadeh - 1965 - Information and Control 8 (1):338--53.
  • On What Is Strictly Speaking True.Charles Travis - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (2):187 - 229.
    Let us begin with a piece of intellectual history. The story begins in a period encapsulating the second world war – say the ‘40’s, give and take a bit. Around then, it began to be argued with force that an expression – e.g., an English one – while it well might mean something, does not say anything, and notably no one thing in particular. The principal behind the argument was surely J.L. Austin, though, I would claim, the same point was (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Modeling Truth.Paul Teller - 2017 - Philosophia 45 (1):143-161.
    Many in philosophy understand truth in terms of precise semantic values, true propositions. Following Braun and Sider, I say that in this sense almost nothing we say is, literally, true. I take the stand that this account of truth nonetheless constitutes a vitally useful idealization in understanding many features of the structure of language. The Fregean problem discussed by Braun and Sider concerns issues about application of language to the world. In understanding these issues I propose an alternative modeling tool (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Skepticism, relevant alternatives, and deductive closure.G. C. Stine - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 29 (4):249--261.
  • On Quantifier Domain Restriction.Jason Stanley & Zoltán Gendler Szabó - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (2-3):219--61.
    In this paper, we provide a comprehensive survey of the space of possible analyses of the phenomenon of quantifier domain restriction, together with a set of considerations which militate against all but our own proposal. Among the many accounts we consider and reject are the ‘explicit’ approach to quantifier domain restric‐tion discussed, for example, by Stephen Neale, and the pragmatic approach to quantifier domain restriction proposed by Kent Bach. Our hope is that the exhaustive discussion of this special case of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   385 citations  
  • Context and logical form.Jason Stanley - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (4):391--434.
    In this paper, I defend the thesis that alleffects of extra-linguistic context on thetruth-conditions of an assertion are traceable toelements in the actual syntactic structure of thesentence uttered. In the first section, I develop thethesis in detail, and discuss its implications for therelation between semantics and pragmatics. The nexttwo sections are devoted to apparent counterexamples.In the second section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of true non-sentential assertions.In the third section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of what (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   349 citations  
  • The calculus of terms.Fred Sommers - 1970 - Mind 79 (313):1-39.
  • Scott Soames: Understanding Truth.Matthew Mcgrath - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):410-417.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Précis of Understanding Truth.Scott Soames - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):397-401.
    Part one attempts to diffuse five different forms of truth skepticism, broadly conceived: the view that truth is indefinable, that it is unknowable, that it is inextricably metaphysical, that there is no such thing as truth, and the view that truth is inherently paradoxical, and so must either be abandoned, or revised. An intriguing formulation of the last of these views is due to Alfred Tarski, who argued that the Liar paradox shows natural languages to be inconsistent because they contain (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   145 citations  
  • Direct Reference.Francois Recanati - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4):953-956.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • A Plea for Semantic Localism.Agustín Rayo - 2011 - Noûs 47 (4):647-679.
    The purpose of this paper is to defend a conception of language that does not rely on linguistic meanings, and use it to address the Sorites and Liar paradoxes.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Vagueness and context-relativity.Diana Raffman - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 81 (2-3):175 - 192.
    This paper develops the treatment of vague predicates begun in my "Vagueness Without Paradox" (Philosophical Review 103, 1 [1994]). In particular, I show how my account of vague words dissolves an "eternal" version of the sorites paradox, i.e., a version in which the paradox is generated independently of any particular run of judgments of the items in a sorites series. In so doing I refine the notion of an internal contest, introduced in the earlier paper, and draw a distinction within (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. V. O. Quine - 1951 - In Robert B. Talisse & Scott F. Aikin (eds.), The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce Through the Present. Princeton University Press. pp. 202-220.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   917 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
    Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1334 citations  
  • Frege on demonstratives.John Perry - 1977 - Philosophical Review 86 (4):474-497.
    Demonstratives seem to have posed a severe difficulty for Frege’s philosophy of language, to which his doctrine of incommunicable senses was a reaction. In “The Thought,” Frege briefly discusses sentences containing such demonstratives as “today,” “here,” and “yesterday,” and then turns to certain questions that he says are raised by the occurrence of “I” in sentences (T, 24-26). He is led to say that, when one thinks about oneself, one grasps thoughts that others cannot grasp, that cannot be communicated. However, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   411 citations  
  • How cheap can you get?Ram Neta - 2008 - Philosophical Issues 18 (1):130-142.
    According to a contextualist account of knowledge ascriptions, it’s possible for both Skeptic’s assertion of “Moore doesn’t know (at a particular time t0) that he has hands” and Normal’s simultaneous assertion of “Moore does know (at t0) that he has hands” to be true, so long as these assertions are issued in different contexts. That’s because the truth-conditions of such knowledge ascriptions (or denials) are fixed partly by features of the context in which those ascriptions (or denials) are issued.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Paul Grice and the philosophy of language.Stephen Neale - 1992 - Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (5):509 - 559.
    The work of the late Paul Grice (1913–1988) exerts a powerful influence on the way philosophers, linguists, and cognitive scientists think about meaning and communication. With respect to a particular sentence φ and an “utterer” U, Grice stressed the philosophical importance of separating (i) what φ means, (ii) what U said on a given occasion by uttering φ, and (iii) what U meant by uttering φ on that occasion. Second, he provided systematic attempts to say precisely what meaning is by (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Future contingents and relative truth.John MacFarlane - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (212):321–336.
    If it is not now determined whether there will be a sea battle tomorrow, can an assertion that there will be one be true? The problem has persisted because there are compelling arguments on both sides. If there are objectively possible futures which would make the prediction true and others which would make it false, symmetry considerations seem to forbid counting it either true or false. Yet if we think about how we would assess the prediction tomorrow, when a sea (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   291 citations  
  • The logical form of determiners.Peter Ludlow - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (1):47 - 69.
  • Convention: A Philosophical Study.David Kellogg Lewis - 1969 - Cambridge, MA, USA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    _ Convention_ was immediately recognized as a major contribution to the subject and its significance has remained undiminished since its first publication in 1969. Lewis analyzes social conventions as regularities in the resolution of recurring coordination problems-situations characterized by interdependent decision processes in which common interests are at stake. Conventions are contrasted with other kinds of regularity, and conventions governing systems of communication are given special attention.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   908 citations  
  • What model theoretic semantics cannot do?Ernest Lepore - 1983 - Synthese 54 (2):167 - 187.
  • Pragmatic halos.Peter Lasersohn - 1999 - Language 75 (3):522-551.
    It is a truism that people speak ‘loosely’——that is, that they often say things that we can recognize not to be true, but which come close enough to the truth for practical purposes. Certain expressions. such as those including ‘exactly’, ‘all’ and ‘perfectly’, appear to serve as signals of the intended degree of approximation to the truth. This article presents a novel formalism for representing the notion of approximation to the truth, and analyzes the meanings of these expressions in terms (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Interpreted Logical Forms.Richard K. Larson & Peter Ludlow - 1993 - Synthese 95 (3):305 - 355.
  • Mathematical rigor--who needs it?Philip Kitcher - 1981 - Noûs 15 (4):469-493.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Meaning, Reference and Cognitive Significance.Kenneth A. Taylor - 1995 - Mind and Language 10 (1-2):129-180.
    I argue that a certain initially appealing Fregean conception of our shared semantic competence in our shared language cannot be made good. In particular, I show that we must reject two fundamental Fregean principles‐what I call Frege's Adequacy Condition and what I call Frege's Cognitive Constraint on Reference Determination. Frege's adequacy condition says that in an adequate semantic theory, sentence meanings must have the same fineness of grain as attitude contents. The Cognitive Constraint on Reference Determination says that in an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Metaphor in Context. [REVIEW]David Hills - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):473-478.
    The unit of metaphor isn’t always a complete sentence; often it is a single word or phrase. In such a case, the word or phrase in question makes a nonstandard, metaphorically determined contribution to the propositional content of the sentence in which it appears, a content whose other ingredients are determined in routine ways by routine recursive procedures of truth-conditional semantics. In this respect, metaphor belongs to semantics. In other respects, it doesn’t belong to semantics at all. To identify what (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Aptness and Truth in Verbal Metaphor.David Hills - 1997 - Philosophical Topics 25 (1):117-153.
  • Knowledge and Lotteries.John Hawthorne - 2005 - Philosophical Quarterly 55 (219):353-356.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   926 citations  
  • Knowledge and Lotteries. [REVIEW]David Jehle - 2006 - Studia Logica 84 (1):161-165.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   216 citations  
  • Words without Meaning.Christopher Gauker - 2003 - MIT Press.
  • Realism and Truth.Philip Gasper - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (3):446.
  • The thought: A logical inquiry.Gottlob Frege - 1956 - Mind 65 (259):289-311.
  • Substitutivity and the Coherence of Quantifying In.Graeme Forbes - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (3):337-372.
    This paper is about the cluster of issues that orbit a well-known thesis of Quine’s, as it applies to attitude ascriptions.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Skeptical problems, contextualist solutions.Richard Feldman - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 103 (1):61 - 85.
  • Can there be vague objects?Gareth Evans - 1978 - Analysis 38 (4):208.
  • Realism and truth.Michael Devitt - 1984 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
  • Contextualism and knowledge attributions.Keith DeRose - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (4):913-929.
  • Verbal Disputes.David J. Chalmers - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (4):515-566.
    The philosophical interest of verbal disputes is twofold. First, they play a key role in philosophical method. Many philosophical disagreements are at least partly verbal, and almost every philosophical dispute has been diagnosed as verbal at some point. Here we can see the diagnosis of verbal disputes as a tool for philosophical progress. Second, they are interesting as a subject matter for first-order philosophy. Reflection on the existence and nature of verbal disputes can reveal something about the nature of concepts, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   220 citations  
  • Insensitive Semantics.Herman Cappelen & Ernie Lepore - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2):443-450.
    We give a precis of our book Insensitive Semantics.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   207 citations  
  • Reference and proper names.Tyler Burge - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (14):425-439.
  • Sea Battle Semantics.Berit Brogaard - 2008 - Philosophical Quarterly 58 (231):326–335.
    The assumption that the future is open makes well known problems for traditional semantics. According to a commonly held intuition, today's occurrence of the sentence 'There will be a sea battle tomorrow', while truth-valueless today, will have a determinate truth-value by tomorrow night. Yet given traditional semantics, sentences that are truth-valueless now cannot later 'become' true. Relativistic semantics has been claimed to do a better job of accommodating intuitions about future contingents than non-relativistic semantics does. However, intuitions about future contingents (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations