Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Fundamental principles of the metaphysic of ethics.Immanuel Kant & Thomas Kingsmill Abbott - 1934 - New York [etc.]: Longmans, Green and co.. Edited by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott.
    What is morally permissible, and what is morally obligatory? These questions form the core of a vast amount of philosophical reasoning. In this landmark work, Kant proposes the concept of a maxim, which functions as a guide to appropriate action under a given set of circumstances. By universalizing the maxim, morally permissible and obligatory behavior becomes clear. The German philosopher's test, known as the Categorical Imperative, is a logical proof of the Golden Rule and the centerpiece of this work. It (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Complicity and torture.Henry Shue - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (4):264-265.
    One of the great merits ofOn Complicity and Compromiseis that it wades into specific swamps where ordinary theorists fear to slog. It is persuasive that in general it can be right sometimes to be complicit in wrongdoing by others through causally contributing to the wrongdoing, but not sharing its purpose, if by being involved one can reasonably expect to lessen the extent of the wrong that would otherwise be suffered by the victims. I focus on whether the book's general thesis (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The responsibility to prevent, the duty to educate.Zohar Lederman, Alexandra Cernat, Eleonora Gregori Ferri, Franco Galbo, Guiomar Micol Andrea Levi-Setti, Mayli Mertens, Bryanna Moore, Olga Riklikiene, Jamie Vescio & Sheena Eagan Chamberlin - 2016 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 37 (3):233-236.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The ethics of medical involvement in torture: commentary.R. M. Hare - 1993 - Journal of Medical Ethics 19 (3):138-141.
    Torture does need to be defined if we are to know exactly what we are seeking to ban; but no single definition will do, because there are many possible ones, and we may want to treat different practices that might be called torture differently. Compare the case of homicide; we do not want to punish manslaughter as severely as murder, and may not want to punish killing in self-defence at all. There are degrees of torture as of murder. Unclarities simply (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Medicine and Human Rights A Proposal for International Action.Michael A. Grodin, George J. Annas & Leonard H. Glantz - 1993 - Hastings Center Report 23 (4):8.
    An international medical tribunal should be established with power to impose criminal sanctions against physicians who are guilty of crimes against humanity.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Doctors in the decent society: Torture, ill-treatment and civic duty.Michael L. Gross - 2004 - Bioethics 18 (2):181–203.
    ABSTRACT How should physicians act when faced with corporal punishment, such as amputation, or torture? In most cases, the answer is clear: international law, UN resolutions and universal codes of medical ethics absolutely forbid physicians from countenancing torture and corporal punishment in any form. An acute problem arises, however, in decent societies, but not necessarily liberal states, that are, nonetheless, welcome in the world community. The decent society is often governed, in whole or in part, by religious laws, and while (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Guantanamo and Other Cases of Enforced Medical Treatment-A Biopolitical Analysis.Mirko D. Garasic - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (1):22-23.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Force-feeding, hunger strikes, Guantanamo and autonomy: replies to George Annas, Charles Foster and Michael Gross.Mirko D. Garasic - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (1):28-29.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The implications of starvation induced psychological changes for the ethical treatment of hunger strikers.D. M. T. Fessler - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (4):243-247.
    Objective: To evaluate existing ethical guidelines for the treatment of hunger strikers in light of findings on psychological changes that accompany the cessation of food intake.Design: Electronic databases were searched for editorials and ethical proclamations on hunger strikers and their treatment; studies of voluntary and involuntary starvation, and legal cases pertaining to hunger striking. Additional studies were gathered in a snowball fashion from the published material cited in these databases. Material was included if it provided ethical or legal guidelines; shed (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Food refusal in prisoners: a communication or a method of self-killing? The role of the psychiatrist and resulting ethical challenges.B. Brockman - 1999 - Journal of Medical Ethics 25 (6):451-456.
    Food refusal occurs for a variety of reasons. It may be used as a political tool, as a method of exercising control over others, at either the individual, family or societal level, or as a method of self-harm, and occasionally it indicates possible mental illness. This article examines the motivation behind hunger strikes in prisoners. It describes the psychiatrist's role in assessment and management of prisoners by referring to case examples. The paper discusses the assessment of an individual's competence to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Detention without Trial, Hunger Strikes and Medical Ethics.S. R. Benatar - 1990 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 18 (1-2):140-145.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Bioethics and Armed Conflict: Moral Dilemmas of Medicine and War. [REVIEW]Michael Gross - 2008 - Journal of Military Ethics 6 (1):83-84.
  • A Defense of Torture.Fritz Allhoff - 2005 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 19 (2):243-264.
    In this paper, I argue for the permissibility of torture in idealized cases by application of separation of cases: if torture is permissible given any of the dominant moral theories (and if one of those is correct), then torture is permissible simpliciter and I can discharge the tricky business of trying to adjudicate among conflicting moral views. To be sure, torture is not permissible on all the dominant moral theories as at least Kantianism will prove especially recalcitrant to granting moral (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Autonomy and Long-Term Care.George J. Agich - 1993 - Oxford University Press.
    The realities and myths of long-term care and the challenges it poses for the ethics of autonomy are analyzed in this perceptive work. The book defends the concept of autonomy, but argues that the standard view of autonomy as non-interference and independence has only a limited applicability for long term care. The treatment of actual autonomy stresses the developmental and social nature of human persons and the priority of identification over autonomous choice. The work balances analysis of the ethical concepts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The morality of freedom.J. Raz - 1988 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 178 (1):108-109.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   627 citations  
  • Torture.Henry Shue - 1978 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 7 (2):124-143.