Switch to: Citations

References in:

Science as Social Existence: Heidegger and the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge

Cambridge, UK: Open Book Publishers (2017)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Heidegger on Science.Trish Glazebrook (ed.) - 2012 - State University of New York Press.
    The first collection of essays devoted to Heidegger’s contribution to understanding modern science.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Possibility.[author unknown] - 1937 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 124 (11):274-275.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Der Wissenschaftsbegriff Martin Heideggers im Zusammenhang seiner Philosophie.[author unknown] - 1988 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 50 (2):372-373.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Sciences of Subjectivity.Steven Shapin - 2017 - In Babette Babich (ed.), Hermeneutic Philosophies of Social Science: Introduction. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 123-142.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Sciences of Subjectivity.Steven Shapin - 2017 - In Babette E. Babich (ed.), Hermeneutic Philosophies of Social Science. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 123-142.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • How We Know About Electrons.John D. Norton - 1982 - In John Norton (ed.).
  • Rethinking Logic: Logic in Relation to Mathematics, Evolution, and Method.Carlo Cellucci - 2013 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This volume examines the limitations of mathematical logic and proposes a new approach to logic intended to overcome them. To this end, the book compares mathematical logic with earlier views of logic, both in the ancient and in the modern age, including those of Plato, Aristotle, Bacon, Descartes, Leibniz, and Kant. From the comparison it is apparent that a basic limitation of mathematical logic is that it narrows down the scope of logic confining it to the study of deduction, without (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals' Abuse of Science.Alan Sokal & Jean Bricmont - 2014 - Picador.
    In 1996 physicist Alan Sokal published an essay in Social Text--an influential academic journal of cultural studies--touting the deep similarities between quantum gravitational theory and postmodern philosophy. Soon thereafter, the essay was revealed as a brilliant parody, a catalog of nonsense written in the cutting-edge but impenetrable lingo of postmodern theorists. The event sparked a furious debate in academic circles and made the headlines of newspapers in the U.S. and abroad. Now in Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals' Abuse of Science, Sokal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy.Michael Polanyi - 1958 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Mary Jo Nye.
    In this work the distinguished physical chemist and philosopher, Michael Polanyi, demonstrates that the scientist's personal participation in his knowledge, in both its discovery and its validation, is an indispensable part of science itself. Even in the exact sciences, "knowing" is an art, of which the skill of the knower, guided by his personal commitment and his passionate sense of increasing contact with reality, is a logically necessary part. In the biological and social sciences this becomes even more evident. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   362 citations  
  • Critique of Pure Reason.Immanuel Kant - 1998 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Edited by J. M. D. Meiklejohn. Translated by Paul Guyer & Allen W. Wood.
    This entirely new translation of Critique of Pure Reason by Paul Guyer and Allan Wood is the most accurate and informative English translation ever produced of this epochal philosophical text. Though its simple, direct style will make it suitable for all new readers of Kant, the translation displays a philosophical and textual sophistication that will enlighten Kant scholars as well. This translation recreates as far as possible a text with the same interpretative nuances and richness as the original.
  • The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology.Edmund Husserl - 1970 - Evanston,: Northwestern University Press.
    In this book, which remained unfinished at his death, Husserl attempts to forge a union between phenomenology and existentialism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   710 citations  
  • Kant and the problem of metaphysics.Martin Heidegger - 1962 - Bloomington,: Indiana University Press.
    The work is significant not only for its illuminating assessment of Kant's thought but also for its elaboration of themes first broached in Being and Time, ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • The passions.Robert C. Solomon (ed.) - 1976 - Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.
    INTRODUCTION: REASON AND THE PASSIONS i. Philosophy? This same philosophy is a good horse in the stable, but an arrant jade on a journey. ...
  • Articulating the World: Conceptual Understanding and the Scientific Image.Joseph Rouse - 2015 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    Naturalism as a guiding philosophy for modern science both disavows any appeal to the supernatural or anything else transcendent to nature, and repudiates any philosophical or religious authority over the workings and conclusions of the sciences. A longstanding paradox within naturalism, however, has been the status of scientific knowledge itself, which seems, at first glance, to be something that transcends and is therefore impossible to conceptualize within scientific naturalism itself. In Articulating the World, Joseph Rouse argues that the most pressing (...)
  • The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza.Richard Henry Popkin - 2023 - Univ of California Press.
    "I had read the book before in the shorter Harper Torchbook edition but read it again right through--and found it as interesting and exciting as before. I regard it as one of the seminal books in the history of ideas. Based on a prodigious amount of original research, it demonstrated conclusively and in fascinating details how the transmission of ancient skepticism was a bital factor in the formation of modern thought. The story is rich in implications for th history of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Der Wahrheitsbegriff bei Husserl und Heidegger.Ernst Tugendhat - 1967 - Berlin,: De Gruyter.
  • Heidegger.William J. Richardson - 1967 - The Hague,: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic.Dallas Willard, Martin Heidegger & Michael Heim - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (4):628.
  • Science, truth and history, part II. metaphysical Bolt-holds for the sociology of scientific knowlege?Nick Tosh - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (1):185-209.
    Historians of science have frequently sought to exclude modern scientific knowledge from their narratives. Part I of this paper, published in the previous issue, cautioned against seeing more than a literary preference at work here. In particular, it was argued—contra advocates of the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge —that a commitment to epistemological relativism should not be seen as having straightforward historiographical consequences. Part II considers further SSK-inspired attempts to entangle the currently fashionable historiography with particular positions in the philosophy of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Science, truth and history, part II. Metaphysical bolt-holes for the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge?Nick Tosh - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (1):185-209.
  • How to Collaborate: Procedural Knowledge in the Cooperative Development of Science.Paul Thagard - 2006 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (S1):177-196.
    A philosopher once asked me: “Paul, how do you collaborate?” He was puzzled about how I came to have more than two dozen co-authors over the past 20 years. His puzzlement was natural for a philosopher, because co-authored articles and books are still rare in philosophy and the humanities, in contrast to science where most current research is collaborative. Unlike most philosophers, scientists know how to collaborate; this paper is about the nature of such procedural knowledge. I begin by discussing (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • How to Collaborate: Procedural Knowledge in the Cooperative Development of Science.Paul Thagard - 2006 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (S1):177-196.
    This paper argues that collaboration in scientific and other fields requires a substantial amount of procedural knowledge about how to collaborate. It discusses how scientists collaborate, how they learn to collaborate, and why they collaborate. Knowledge how does not always reduce to knowledge that, and collaboration has many purposes besides the pursuit of power and resources. The relative scarcity of philosophical collaborations can be overcome by more naturalistic approaches to philosophy and by philosophers learning how to collaborate.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Heidegger on Realism and Idealism.Mark Basil Tanzer - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Research 23:95-111.
    This paper concerns the relation of Heidegger’s thought to the traditionally opposed positions of realism and idealism: a dilemma that Heidegger explicitly addresses in Section 43 of Being and Time. Heidegger’s attempt to forge a position ‘between’ realism and idealism has recently been interpreted in a number of ways, depending on whether Heidegger’s affinity with realism or his affinity with idealism is prioritized. My contention is that Heidegger’s realist and idealist dimensions are equally essential to his thought in view of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger on Realism and Idealism.Mark Basil Tanzer - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Research 23:95-111.
    This paper concerns the relation of Heidegger’s thought to the traditionally opposed positions of realism and idealism: a dilemma that Heidegger explicitly addresses in Section 43 of Being and Time. Heidegger’s attempt to forge a position ‘between’ realism and idealism has recently been interpreted in a number of ways, depending on whether Heidegger’s affinity with realism or his affinity with idealism is prioritized. My contention is that Heidegger’s realist and idealist dimensions are equally essential to his thought in view of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger: Between Idealism and Realism.Lambert V. Stepanich - 1991 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 1 (1):20-28.
  • Heidegger: Between Idealism and Realism.Lambert V. Stepanich - 1991 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 1 (1):20-28.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The logic of emotion.Robert C. Solomon - 1977 - Noûs 11 (1):41-49.
  • Paduan epistemology and the doctrine of the one mind.Harold Skulsky - 1968 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 6 (4):341-361.
  • Robert Boyle and Mathematics: Reality, Representation, and Experimental Practice.Steven Shapin - 1988 - Science in Context 2 (1):23-58.
    The ArgumentThis paper is a study of the role of language in scientific activity. It recommends that language be viewed as a community's means of patterning its affairs. Language represents where the boundaries of the community are and who is entitled to speak within it, and it displays the structures of authority in the community. Moreover, language precipitates the community's view of what the world is like, such that linguistic usages can be taken as referring to that world. Thus, language (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life. [REVIEW]Richard S. Westfall - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (1):128-130.
  • Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life.Steven Shapin & Simon Schaffer - 1985 - Princeton University Press.
    In a new introduction, the authors describe how science and its social context were understood when this book was first published, and how the study of the history of science has changed since then.
  • The Passions.David Sachs - 1978 - Philosophical Review 87 (3):472.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • Knowledge and power: toward a political philosophy of science.Joseph Rouse - 1987 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    This lucidly written book examines the social and political significance of the natural sciences through a detailed and original account of science as an interpretive social practice.
  • Husserlian phenomenology and scientific realism.Joseph Rouse - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (2):222-232.
    Husserl's (1970) discussion of "Galilean science" is often dismissed as naïvely instrumentalist and hostile to science. He has been explicitly criticized for misunderstanding idealization in science, for treating the lifeworld as a privileged conceptual framework, and for denying that science can in principle completely describe the world (because ordinary prescientific concepts are irreplaceable). I clarify Husserl's position concerning realism, and use this to show that the first two criticisms depend upon misinterpretations. The third criticism is well taken. Nevertheless, this is (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Heidegger, Science, and the Mathematical Age.Michael Roubach - 1997 - Science in Context 10 (1):199-206.
    The ArgumentThe purpose of this article is to read Heidegger's critique of modern science —especially in What Is a Thing? —as evolving from ontological issues that preoccupied Heidegger in the period after the publication of Being and Time. The main issues at stake are formal ontology and its connection with mathematics and modern mathematical physics, and the distinction between formal and regional ontology. The connection between these issues constitutes Heidegger's understanding of mathematics. An exposition of Heidegger's notion of the “mathematical” (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Engaging science: how to understand its practices philosophically.Joseph Rouse - 1996 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    Summarizing this century's major debates over realism and the rationality of scientific knowledge, Joseph Rouse believes that these disputes oversimplify the ...
  • On Historicizing Epistemology: An Essay.Hans-Jörg Rheinberger - 2010 - Stanford University Press.
    Epistemology, as generally understood by philosophers of science, is rather remote from the history of science and from historical concerns in general. Rheinberger shows that, from the late nineteenth through the late twentieth century, a parallel, alternative discourse sought to come to terms with the rather fundamental experience of the thoroughgoing scientific changes brought on by the revolution in physics. Philosophers of science and historians of science alike contributed their share to what this essay describes as an ongoing quest to (...)
  • An epistemology of the concrete: twentieth-century histories of life.Hans-Jörg Rheinberger - 2010 - Durham [NC]: Duke University Press.
    Ludwik Fleck, Edmund Husserl : on the historicity of scientific knowledge -- Gaston Bachelard : the concept of "phenomenotechnique" -- Georges Canguilhem : epistemological history -- Pisum : Carl Correns's experiments on Xenia, 1896-99 -- Eudorina : Max Hartmann's experiments on biological regulation in protozoa, 1914-21 -- Ephestia : Alfred Kähn's experimental design for a developmental physiological -- Genetics, 1924-45 -- Tobacco mosaic virus : virus research at the Kaiser Wilhelm Institutes for Biochemistry and Biology, 1937-45 -- The concept of (...)
  • Critical Notice.Stathis Psillos - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (2):495-497.
  • What is a thing?Martin Heidegger - 1967 - Lanham [Md.]: University Press of America. Edited by Eugene T. Gendlin.
  • Gender and Boyle's Law of Gases. By Elizabeth Potter. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. 2001.Laura Ruetsche - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (1):297-302.
  • Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy.Edward C. Moore - 1959 - Philosophy of Science 26 (3):270-272.
  • Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy.Richard Robin - 1959 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 20 (3):429-429.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Heidegger on logic.Jitendranath Mohanty - 1988 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (1):107-135.
  • Recent work on aesthetics of science.James W. McAllister - 2002 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16 (1):7 – 11.
    This introduction to the special issue on "Aesthetics of Science" reviews recent philosophical research on aesthetic aspects of science. Topics represented in this research include the aesthetic properties of scientific images, theories, and experiments; the relation of science and art; the role of aesthetic criteria in scientific practice and their effect on the development of science; aesthetic aspects of mathematics; the contrast between a classic and a Romantic aesthetic; and the relation between emotion, cognition, and rationality.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Methodological dilemmas and emotion in science.James W. McAllister - 2014 - Synthese 191 (13):3143-3158.
    Inconsistencies in science take several forms. Some occur at the level of substantive claims about the world. Others occur at the level of methodology, and take the form of dilemmas, or cases of conflicting epistemic or cognitive values. In this article, I discuss how methodological dilemmas arise. I then consider how scientists resolve them. There are strong grounds for thinking that emotional judgement plays an important role in resolving methodological dilemmas. Lastly, I discuss whether and under what conditions this reliance (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Realism and the strong program.Tim Lewens - 2005 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (3):559-577.
    The four tenets of the Strong Program are compatible with a scientific realism founded on an externalist epistemology. Such an epistemology allows that appropriate norms of rationality may differ from time to time, and from community to community, and thereby enables the realist to embrace strong forms of the ‘symmetry principle’. It also suggests a fruitful collaborative research program in externalist social epistemology. Some of what the Edinburgh School says about truth can also be accepted. But the realist should reject (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Science Wars: A Dialogue.Bruno Latour & Ashraf Noor - 2002 - Common Knowledge 8 (1):71-79.
  • Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves.Rae Langton - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198):105-108.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Kantian humility: our ignorance of things in themselves.Rae Langton - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Rae Langton offers a new interpretation and defense of Kant's doctrine of things in themselves. Kant distinguishes things in themselves from phenomena, and in so doing he makes a metaphysical distinction between intrinsic and relational properties of substances. Langton argues that his claim that we have no knowledge of things in themselves is not idealism, but epistemic humility: we have no knowledge of the intrinsic properties of substances. This interpretation vindicates Kant's scientific realism, and shows his primary/secondary quality distinction to (...)