Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Critique of Pure Reason.Günter Zöller - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (1):113.
    This new translation of the first Critique forms part of a fifteen-volume English-language edition of the works of Immanuel Kant under the general editorship of this volume’s editor-translators, Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. The edition, which is almost complete by now, comprises all of Kant’s published works along with extensive selections from his literary remains, his correspondence, and student transcripts of his lecture courses in metaphysics, ethics, logic, and anthropology. The Cambridge edition aims at a consistent English rendition of Kant’s (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • Recent work on Kant's transcendental deduction.Justin B. Shaddock - 2017 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 25 (2):401-410.
  • Transcendental Synthesis and Developmental Psychology.Onora O’Neill - 1984 - Kant Studien 75 (1-4):149-167.
  • Kant's Transcendental Psychology.Ralf Meerbote & Patricia Kitcher - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):862.
  • Kant’s Theory of Mind in the Critique of Pure Reason’s Subjective Deduction.Matt McCormick - 2005 - Journal of Value Inquiry 39 (3):353–381.
  • Psychology and the Transcendental Deduction.Paul Guyer - 1989 - In Eckart Förster (ed.), Kant’s Transcendental Deductions: The Three ‘Critiques’ and the ‘Opus Postumum’. Stanford University Press. pp. 47-68.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Spontaneity before the Critical Turn: Crusius, Tetens, and the Pre-Critical Kant on the Spontaneity of the Mind.Corey W. Dyck - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (4):625-648.
    Kant’s introduction in the Kritik der reinen Vernunft (KrV) of a spontaneity proper to the understanding is often thought to be one of the central innovations of his Critical philosophy. As I show in this paper, however, a number of thinkers within the 18th century German tradition in the time before the KrV (including the pre-Critical Kant himself) had already developed a robust conception of the spontaneity of the mind, a conception which, in many respects lays the groundwork for Kant’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The subjective deduction and the search for a fundamental force.Corey W. Dyck - 2008 - Kant Studien 99 (2):152-179.
    In this paper, I claim that Kant’s subjective deduction in the first edition of the KrV is to be understood in terms of an investigation of the fundamental force(s) (Grundkraft) of the soul, an investigation essential to Wolffian psychology and much debated throughout Germany in the second half of the 1700’s. I argue that the subjective deduction is indeed presented by means of the exposition of the three-fold syntheses but only insofar as these syntheses are employed as pointers towards each (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Kant’s Transcendental Deduction.W. H. Bossart - 1977 - Kant Studien 68 (1-4):383-403.
  • Kant's Subjective Deduction.Nathan Bauer - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (3):433-460.
    In the transcendental deduction, the central argument of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant seeks to secure the objective validity of our basic categories of thought. He distinguishes objective and subjective sides of this argument. The latter side, the subjective deduction, is normally understood as an investigation of our cognitive faculties. It is identified with Kant’s account of a threefold synthesis involved in our cognition of objects of experience, and it is said to precede and ground Kant’s proof of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Kant, non-conceptual content and the representation of space.Lucy Allais - 2009 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (3):pp. 383-413.
    :Space is not an empirical concept that has been drawn from outer experiences. For in order for certain sensations to be related to something outside me , thus in order for me to represent them as outside and next to one another, thus not merely different but as in different places, the representation of space must already be their ground. Thus the representation of space cannot be obtained from the relations of outer appearance through experience, but this outer experience is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Kant's Theory of Imagination: Bridging Gaps in Judgment and Experience.Sarah L. Gibbons - 1994 - New York: Oxford.
    This book departs from much of the scholarship on Kant by demonstrating the centrality of imagination to Kant's philosophy as a whole. In Kant's works, human experience is simultaneously passive and active, thought and sensed, free and unfree: these dualisms are often thought of as unfortunate byproducts of his system. Gibbons, however, shows that imagination performs a vital function in "bridging gaps" between the different elements of cognition and experience. Thus, the role imagination plays in Kant's works expresses his fundamental (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Possible Experience. [REVIEW]Michelle Grier - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (1):135-137.
    The central thesis of this book is clear. According to Collins, Kant is not an idealist of any sort. Kant is not an idealist, on Collins’s view, because he neither denies the existence of a non-mental reality nor claims that we cannot be sure that there is any non-mental reality. Because Kant explicitly criticizes both dogmatic and problematic forms of idealism, Collins concludes that the appellation “idealist” is altogether improperly ascribed to Kant. One might ask straightaway whether there might not (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutic Import of the Critique of Judgment.Rudolph A. MAKKREEL - 1990
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Kant's Theory of Mental Activity: A Commentary on the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason.R. W. WOLFF - 1963
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • A Commentary to Kant's `Critique of Pure Reason'.Norman Kemp Smith - 1919 - Mind 28 (110):217-229.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Kant's Theory or Imagination.Sarah Gibbons - 2002 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 192 (4):482-482.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant's Metaphysic of Experience.H. J. Paton - 1937 - Philosophy 12 (45):99-104.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Critique of Pure Reason.I. Kant - 1787/1998 - Philosophy 59 (230):555-557.
  • The development of kantian thought. The History of a Doctrine.Herman J. de Wleeschauwer & A. R. C. Duncan - 1962 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 69 (1):121-122.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Some remarks on Ludwig Heinrich Jakob's Examination of Mendelssohn's morning hours (1786).Immanuel Kant - 2007 - In Anthropology, History, and Education. Cambridge University Press.
  • Essay on the maladies of the head (1764).Immanuel Kant - 2007 - In Anthropology, History, and Education. Cambridge University Press.