Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Consent, Context, and Obligations: A Response to Ciomaga.Steven Weimer - 2014 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 41 (2):233-245.
    In his ‘Rules and Obligations,’ Bogdan Ciomaga defends a pluralist account of moral obligations to follow sport rules by arguing that no single explanation of such obligations will plausibly apply in multiple contexts. I dispute this claim by showing that consent generates rule-following obligations in a very wide variety of the contexts in which sports are played, including each of those Ciomaga cites in support of his pluralist account. The contractualist or consent-based theory of rule normativity therefore offers a substantially (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Consent and Right Action in Sport.Steven Weimer - 2012 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39 (1):11-31.
    This paper argues that recent treatments of ethics in sport have accorded too much importance to the promotion and portrayal of a sport’s excellences, and too little to the consent of participants First, I consider and reject a fundamental challenge to the idea that consent should play a central role in determining the morality of action in sport – namely, Sean McAleer’s argument to the effect that consent is incapable of rendering normally impermissible actions permissible in sport. I then offer (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Freedom to box.N. Warburton - 1998 - Journal of Medical Ethics 24 (1):56-60.
    The british Medical Association wants to criminalise all boxing. This article examines the logic of the arguments it uses and finds them wanting. The move from medical evidence about the risk of brain damage to the conclusion that boxing should be banned is not warranted. The BMA's arguments are a combination of inconsistent paternalism and legal moralism. Consistent application of the principles implicit in the BMA's arguments would lead to absurd consequences and to severe limitations being put on individual freedom.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What Counts As Part of a Game? A Look at Skills.Cesar R. Torres - 2000 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 27 (1):81-92.
  • What’s Wrong With J.S. Mill’s “Harm-to-Others”-Principle?Claudio Tamburrini - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 38 (1):1-26.
  • Paternalism and partial autonomy.O. O'Neill - 1984 - Journal of Medical Ethics 10 (4):173-178.
    A contrast is often drawn between standard adult capacities for autonomy, which allow informed consent to be given or withheld, and patients' reduced capacities, which demand paternalistic treatment. But patients may not be radically different from the rest of us, in that all human capacities for autonomous action are limited. An adequate account of paternalism and the role that consent and respect for persons can play in medical and other practice has to be developed within an ethical theory that does (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Paternalism and partial autonomy.Onora O' Neill - 1984 - Journal of Medical Ethics 10 (4):173.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Facing up to paternalism in research ethics.Franklin G. Miller & Alan Wertheimer - 2007 - Hastings Center Report 37 (3):24-34.
    : Bioethicists have failed to understand the pervasively paternalistic character of research ethics. Not only is the overall structure of research review and regulation paternalistic in some sense; even the way informed consent is sought may imply paternalism. Paternalism has limits, however. Getting clear on the paternalism of research ethics may mean some kinds of prohibited research should be reassessed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Forced to be free? Increasing patient autonomy by constraining it.Neil Levy - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (5):293-300.
    It is universally accepted in bioethics that doctors and other medical professionals have an obligation to procure the informed consent of their patients. Informed consent is required because patients have the moral right to autonomy in furthering the pursuit of their most important goals. In the present work, it is argued that evidence from psychology shows that human beings are subject to a number of biases and limitations as reasoners, which can be expected to lower the quality of their decisions (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The Moral Controversy Over Boxing Reform.C. D. Herrera - 2002 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 29 (2):163-173.
  • The Moral Controversy Over Boxing Reform.C. D. Herrera - 2002 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 29 (2):163-173.
  • Concussions, Professional Sports, and Conflicts of Interest: Why the National Football League’s Current Policies are Bad for Its Health. [REVIEW]Daniel S. Goldberg - 2008 - HEC Forum 20 (4):337-355.
  • Intentional Rules Violations—One More Time.Warren P. Fraleigh - 2003 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 30 (2):166-176.
  • Fair Play in Sport: A Moral Norm System By Sigmund Loland. Published by Routledge, London and New York. [REVIEW]Warren Fraleigh - 2003 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 30 (1):93-96.
  • Review of Allen E. Buchanan and Dan W. Brock: Deciding for Others: The Ethics of Surrogate Decision Making[REVIEW]Jonathan D. Moreno - 1992 - Ethics 103 (1):172-175.
  • Rules and Obligations.Bogdan Ciomaga - 2013 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 40 (1):19-40.
    The existence of the obligation to follow rules in sport is widely accepted, but there are only a few studies that provide accounts that justify it. Building upon Wolff's challenge to traditional political theories, this study proposes a theory that limits the level of normativity to which participants in sport contests are bound in an effort to maximize their autonomy. Instead of constructing a unitary theory of obligations to follow sport rules, a pluralistic account is offered, one that allows for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy.Robert Audi (ed.) - 1995 - New York City: Cambridge University Press.
    This is the leading, full-scale comprehensive dictionary of philosophical terms and thinkers to appear in English in more than half a century. Written by a team of more than 550 experts and now widely translated, it contains approximately 5,000 entries ranging from short definitions to longer articles. It is designed to facilitate the understanding of philosophy at all levels and in all fields. Key features of this third edition include: • 500 new entries covering Eastern as well as Western philosophy, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Deciding for Others: The Ethics of Surrogate Decision Making.Allen E. Buchanan & Dan W. Brock - 1989 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Dan W. Brock.
    This book is the most comprehensive treatment available of one of the most urgent - and yet in some respects most neglected - problems in bioethics: decision-making for incompetents. Part I develops a general theory for making treatment and care decisions for patients who are not competent to decide for themselves. It provides an in-depth analysis of competence, articulates and defends a coherent set of principles to specify suitable surrogate decisionmakers and to guide their choices, examines the value of advance (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   251 citations  
  • Concussion and youth hockey: It’s time to break the cycle.L. Syd M. Johnson - 2011 - Canadian Medical Association Journal 183:921-924.
    Concussion is a common, serious injury in youth ice hockey, affecting up to 25% of players per season by one estimate. • Bodychecking is a major cause of injury and concussion in hockey, yet some Canadian provinces allow players as young as nine years to engage in bodychecking. • Reducing rates of concussion requires eliminating bodychecking for all except elite hockey players aged 16 years and older, as per the recommendations of the Canadian Academy of Sports and Exercise Medicine.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Paternalism and autonomy.Douglas N. Husak - 1981 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (1):27-46.