Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Semantical Investigations in Heyting's Intuitionistic Logic.Dov M. Gabbay - 1981 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Reidel.
    From the point of view of non-classical logics, Heyting's implication is the smallest implication for which the deduction theorem holds. This book studies properties of logical systems having some of the classical connectives and implication in the neighbourhood of Heyt ing's implication. I have not included anything on entailment, al though it belongs to this neighbourhood, mainly because of the appearance of the Anderson-Belnap book on entailment. In the later chapters of this book, I have included material that might be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • An introduction to modal logic.G. E. Hughes - 1968 - London,: Methuen. Edited by M. J. Cresswell.
    Modal propositional logic; Modal predicate logic; A survey of modal logic.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   201 citations  
  • Theory of Logical Calculi: Basic Theory of Consequence Operations.Ryszard Wójcicki - 1988 - Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    The general aim of this book is to provide an elementary exposition of some basic concepts in terms of which both classical and non-dassicallogirs may be studied and appraised. Although quantificational logic is dealt with briefly in the last chapter, the discussion is chiefly concemed with propo gjtional cakuli. Still, the subject, as it stands today, cannot br covered in one book of reasonable length. Rather than to try to include in the volume as much as possible, I have put (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • On structural completeness of implicational logics.Piotr Wojtylak - 1991 - Studia Logica 50 (2):275 - 297.
    We consider the notion of structural completeness with respect to arbitrary (finitary and/or infinitary) inferential rules. Our main task is to characterize structurally complete intermediate logics. We prove that the structurally complete extension of any pure implicational in termediate logic C can be given as an extension of C with a certain family of schematically denned infinitary rules; the same rules are used for each C. The cardinality of the family is continuum and, in the case of (the pure implicational (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The problem of reconstructability of propositional calculi.Marek Tokarz & Ryszard Wójcicki - 1971 - Studia Logica 28 (1):119 - 129.
  • Continuum Many Maximal Consistent Normal Bimodal Logics with Inverses.Timothy Williamson - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (1):128-134.
  • A simple decision procedure for one-variable implicational/negation formulae in intuitionist logic.Storrs McCall - 1962 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 3 (2):120-122.
  • Relative necessity.Timothy Smiley - 1963 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 28 (2):113-134.
  • Relative Necessity.Timothy Smiley & T. J. Smiley - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3):401-401.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Classical propositional operators: an exercise in the foundations of logic.Krister Segerberg - 1982 - New York: Oxford University Press.
  • On systems containing Aristotle's thesis.R. Routley & H. Montgomery - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):82-96.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Applications of weak Kripke semantics to intermediate consequences.Wolfgang Rautenberg - 1986 - Studia Logica 45 (1):119 - 134.
    Section 1 contains a Kripke-style completeness theorem for arbitrary intermediate consequences. In Section 2 we apply weak Kripke semantics to splittings in order to obtain generalized axiomatization criteria of the Jankov-type. Section 3 presents new and short proofs of recent results on implicationless intermediate consequences. In Section 4 we prove that these consequences admit no deduction theorem. In Section 5 all maximal logics in the 3 rd counterslice are determined. On these results we reported at the 1980 meeting on Mathematical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Philosophy of logic.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1970 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Edited by Simon Blackburn & Keith Simmons.
  • The deducibilities of S.Jean Porte - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (4):409 - 422.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Strong Boethius' thesis and consequential implication.Claudio Pizzi & Timothy Williamson - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (5):569-588.
    The paper studies the relation between systems of modal logic and systems of consequential implication, a non-material form of implication satisfying "Aristotle's Thesis" (p does not imply not p) and "Weak Boethius' Thesis" (if p implies q, then p does not imply not q). Definitions are given of consequential implication in terms of modal operators and of modal operators in terms of consequential implication. The modal equivalent of "Strong Boethius' Thesis" (that p implies q implies that p does not imply (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • On formulas of one variable in intuitionistic propositional calculus.Iwao Nishimura - 1960 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 25 (4):327-331.
  • Aristotle's thesis in consistent and inconsistent logics.Chris Mortensen - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (1-2):107 - 116.
    A typical theorem of conaexive logics is Aristotle''s Thesis(A), (AA).A cannot be added to classical logic without producing a trivial (Post-inconsistent) logic, so connexive logics typically give up one or more of the classical properties of conjunction, e.g.(A & B)A, and are thereby able to achieve not only nontriviality, but also (negation) consistency. To date, semantical modellings forA have been unintuitive. One task of this paper is to give a more intuitive modelling forA in consistent logics. In addition, while inconsistent (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Verisimilitude redeflated.David Miller - 1976 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (4):363-381.
  • Connexive implication.Storrs Mccall - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3):415-433.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • A. Białynicki-Birula and H. Rasiowa. On constructible falsity in the constructive logic with strong negation. Colloquium mathematicum, vol. 6 (1958), pp. 287–310. [REVIEW]V. A. Jankov, Sue Walker & Elliott Mendelson - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):138-138.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Choice of primitives: A note on axiomatizing intuitionistic logic.I. L. Humberstone - 1998 - History and Philosophy of Logic 19 (1):31-40.
    A purported axiomatization, by P. Gärdenfors, of intuitionistic propositional logic is shown to be incomplete, and that the mistaken claim to completeness is seen to result from carelessness in the choice of primitive logical vocabulary. This leads to a consideration of various ways of conceiving the distinction between primitive and defined vocabularies, along with the bearing of these differences on such matters as are discussed in connection with Gärdenfors.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Two types of circularity.I. L. Humberstone - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (2):249-280.
    For the claim that the satisfaction of certain conditions is sufficient for the application of some concept to serve as part of the (`reductive') analysis of that concept, we require the conditions to be specified without employing that very concept. An account of the application conditions of a concept not meeting this requirement, we call analytically circular. For such a claim to be usable in determining the extension of the concept, however, such circularity may not matter, since if the concept (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Two Types of Circularity.I. L. Humberstone - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (2):249-280.
    For the claim that the satisfaction of certain conditions is sufficient for the application of some concept to serve as part of the (‘reductive’) analysis of that concept, we require the conditions to be specified without employing that very concept. An account of the application conditions of a concept not meeting this requirement, we call analytically circular. For such a claim to be usable in determining the extension of the concept, however, such circularity may not matter, since if the concept (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Singulary extensional connectives: A closer look. [REVIEW]I. L. Humberstone - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (3):341-356.
    The totality of extensional 1-ary connectives distinguishable in a logical framework allowing sequents with multiple or empty (alongside singleton) succedents form a lattice under a natural partial ordering relating one connective to another if all the inferential properties of the former are possessed by the latter. Here we give a complete description of that lattice; its Hasse diagram appears as Figure 1 in §2. Simple syntactic descriptions of the lattice elements are provided in §3; §§4 and 5 give some additional (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Negation by iteration.I. L. Humberstone - 1995 - Theoria 61 (1):1-24.
  • Inverses for normal modal operators.Lloyd Humberstone & Timothy Williamson - 1997 - Studia Logica 59 (1):33-64.
    Given a 1-ary sentence operator , we describe L - another 1-ary operator - as as a left inverse of in a given logic if in that logic every formula is provably equivalent to L. Similarly R is a right inverse of if is always provably equivalent to R. We investigate the behaviour of left and right inverses for taken as the operator of various normal modal logics, paying particular attention to the conditions under which these logics are conservatively extended (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Extensionality in sentence position.Lloyd Humberstone - 1986 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 15 (1):27 - 54.
  • Extendible sentential calculus.H. Hiz - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 24 (3):193-202.
  • Deviant logic: some philosophical issues.Susan Haack - 1974 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    PART ONE I 'Alternative' in 'Alternative logic There are many systems of logic — many-valued systems and modal systems for instance - which are non-standard ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Intuitionistic logic with strong negation.Yuri Gurevich - 1977 - Studia Logica 36 (1-2):49 - 59.
    This paper is a reaction to the following remark by grzegorczyk: "the compound sentences are not a product of experiment. they arise from reasoning. this concerns also negations; we see that the lemon is yellow, we do not see that it is not blue." generally, in science the truth is ascertained as indirectly as falsehood. an example: a litmus-paper is used to verify the sentence "the solution is acid." this approach gives rise to a (very intuitionistic indeed) conservative extension of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Semantical Investigations in Heyting's Intuitionistic Logic.Dov M. Gabbay - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):824-824.
  • A note on Halldén-incompleteness.E. J. Lemmon - 1966 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 7 (4):296-300.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Some embedding theorems for modal logic.David Makinson - 1971 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 12 (2):252-254.
    Some results on the upper end of the lattice of all modal propositional logics.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • A Propositional Logic with Subjunctive Conditionals.R. B. Angell - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):464-465.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • A propositional logic with subjunctive conditionals.R. B. Angell - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (3):327-343.
    In this paper a formalized logic of propositions, PA1, is presented. It is proven consistent and its relationships to traditional logic, to PM ([15]), to subjunctive (including contrary-to-fact) implication and to the “paradoxes” of material and strict implication are developed. Apart from any intrinsic merit it possesses, its chief significance lies in demonstrating the feasibility of a general logic containing theprinciple of subjunctive contrariety, i.e., the principle that ‘Ifpwere true thenqwould be true’ and ‘Ifpwere true thenqwould be false’ are incompatible.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Constructivism in mathematics: an introduction.A. S. Troelstra - 1988 - New York, N.Y.: Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada, Elsevier Science Pub. Co.. Edited by D. van Dalen.
    Provability, Computability and Reflection.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • .E. J. Lemmon - 1966
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Relevant Logics and Their Rivals.Richard Routley, Val Plumwood, Robert K. Meyer & Ross T. Brady - 1982 - Ridgeview. Edited by Richard Sylvan & Ross Brady.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   204 citations  
  • A New Introduction to Modal Logic.M. J. Cresswell & G. E. Hughes - 1996 - New York: Routledge. Edited by M. J. Cresswell.
    This long-awaited book replaces Hughes and Cresswell's two classic studies of modal logic: _An Introduction to Modal Logic_ and _A Companion to Modal Logic_. _A New Introduction to Modal Logic_ is an entirely new work, completely re-written by the authors. They have incorporated all the new developments that have taken place since 1968 in both modal propositional logic and modal predicate logic, without sacrificing tha clarity of exposition and approachability that were essential features of their earlier works. The book takes (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   242 citations  
  • Modal logic.Alexander Chagrov - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Michael Zakharyaschev.
    For a novice this book is a mathematically-oriented introduction to modal logic, the discipline within mathematical logic studying mathematical models of reasoning which involve various kinds of modal operators. It starts with very fundamental concepts and gradually proceeds to the front line of current research, introducing in full details the modern semantic and algebraic apparatus and covering practically all classical results in the field. It contains both numerous exercises and open problems, and presupposes only minimal knowledge in mathematics. A specialist (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • A survey of some connections between classical, intuitionistic and minimal logic.D. Prawitz & P.-E. Malmnäs - 1968 - In H. Arnold Schmidt, K. Schütte & H. J. Thiele (eds.), Contributions to Mathematical Logic, Proceedings of the Logic Colloquium, Hannover 1966. North-Holland Publishing Company. pp. 215–229.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations