Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Understanding Peace: A Comprehensive Introduction.Michael Allen Fox - 2013 - New York: Routledge.
  • A defense of abortion.Judith Jarvis Thomson - 1971 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1):47-66.
  • Creation and Abortion: A Study in Moral and Legal Philosophy.Mary Anne Warren & F. M. Kamm - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (4):729.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Living High and Letting Die.Peter Unger - 1999 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 59 (1):195-201.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Living High and Letting Die.Peter Unger - 1999 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 59 (1):173-175.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Critical notice--Defending life: a moral and legal case against abortion choice by Francis J Beckwith.D. Stretton - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (11):793-797.
    Francis Beckwith’s Defending life: a moral and legal case against abortion choice defends the pro-life position on moral, legal and political grounds. In this critical notice I consider three key issues and argue that Beckwith’s treatment of each of them is unpersuasive. The issues are: (1) whether abortion is politically justified by the principle that we should err on the side of liberty in the face of reasonable disagreement over the moral status of the fetus; (2) whether the fetus’s natural (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On the Success Condition for Legitimate Self‐Defense.Daniel Statman - 2008 - Ethics 118 (4):659-686.
    The paper discusses a neglected condition for justified self-defense, namely, 'The Success Condition [SC].' According to SC, otherwise immoral acts can be justified under the right to self-defense only if they actually achieve the intended defense from the perceived threat. If they don't, they are almost always excused, but not morally justified. I show that SC leads to a troubling puzzle because victims who estimate they cannot prevent the attack against them would be morally required to surrender. I try to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Self-defense, pacifism, and the possibility of killing.Cheyney C. Ryan - 1982 - Ethics 93 (3):508-524.
  • Making pacifism plausible.Soran Reader - 2000 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 17 (2):169–180.
  • Aquinas, Double-Effect Reasoning, and the Pauline Principle.Bernard G. Prusak - 2015 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 89 (3):505-520.
    This paper reconsiders whether Aquinas is rightly read as a double-effect thinker and whether it is right to understand him as concurring with Paul’s dictum that evil is not to be done that good may come. I focus on what to make of Aquinas’s position that, though the private citizen may not intend to kill a man in self-defense, those holding public authority, like soldiers, may rightly do so. On my interpretation, we cannot attribute to Aquinas the position that aiming (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Self-defense and the problem of the innocent attacker.Jeff McMahan - 1994 - Ethics 104 (2):252-290.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Killing, letting die, and withdrawing aid.Jeff McMahan - 1993 - Ethics 103 (2):250-279.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Infanticide.Jeff Mcmahan - 2007 - Utilitas 19 (2):131-159.
    It is sometimes suggested that if a moral theory implies that infanticide can sometimes be permissible, that is sufficient to discredit the theory. I argue in this article that the common-sense belief that infanticide is wrong, and perhaps even worse than the killing of an adult, is challenged not so much by theoretical considerations as by common-sense beliefs about abortion, the killing of non-human animals, and so on. Because there are no intrinsic differences between premature infants and viable fetuses, it (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Life's Dominion.Melissa Lane & Ronald Dworkin - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (176):413.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   200 citations  
  • Creation and abortion: a study in moral and legal philosophy.Frances Myrna Kamm - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Based on a non-consequentialist ethical theory, this book critically examines the prevalent view that if a fetus has the moral standing of a person, it has a right to life and abortion is impermissible. Most discussion of abortion has assumed that this view is correct, and so has focused on the question of the personhood of the fetus. Kamm begins by considering in detail the permissibility of killing in non-abortion cases which are similar to abortion cases. She goes on to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Trouble with Secunda Secundae 64, 7.Steven Jensen - 2006 - Modern Schoolman 83 (2):143-162.
  • Abortions and Distortions: An Analysis of Morally Irrelevant Factors in Thomson’s Violinist Thought Experiment.David B. Hershenov - 2001 - Social Theory and Practice 27 (1):129-148.
  • Pacifism.Stanley Hauerwas - 1985 - Faith and Philosophy 2 (2):99-104.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pacifism.Stanley Hauerwas - 1985 - Faith and Philosophy 2 (2):99-104.
  • War-Pacifism.David Carroll Cochran - 1996 - Social Theory and Practice 22 (2):161-180.
  • Justified Killing: The Paradox of Self-Defense.Whitley R. P. Kaufman - 2009 - Lexington Books.
    In Justified Killing, Whitley R. P. Kaufman argues that none of the leading theories adequately explains why it is permissible even to kill an innocent attacker in self-defense, given the basic moral prohibition against killing the innocent. Kaufman suggests that such an explanation can be found in the traditional Doctrine of Double Effect, according to which self-defense is justified because the intention of the defender is to protect himself rather than harm the attacker.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Success Condition for Legitimate Self-Defense.Daniel Statman - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 3 (4):89-94.
    The paper discusses a neglected condition for justified self-defense, namely, 'The Success Condition [SC].' According to SC, otherwise immoral acts can be justified under the right to self-defense only if they actually achieve the intended defense from the perceived threat. If they don't, they are almost always excused, but not morally justified. I show that SC leads to a troubling puzzle because victims who estimate they cannot prevent the attack against them would be morally required to surrender. I try to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Action, Intention and ‘Double Effect’.Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe - 2005 - In M. Geach & L. Gormally (eds.), Human Life, Action and Ethics. Exeter: Imprint Academic.
    Introduction: It is customary in the dominant English and related schools of philosophy to restrict the terms “action” or “agency.” That is, when the topic is ‘philosophy of action’. This is often done by an appeal to intuition about a few examples. If I fall over, you wouldn’t usually call that an action on my part; it’s not something that I do, it is rather something that happens to me. Donald Davidson has made a more serious attempt than this at (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Creation and Abortion: A Study in Moral and Legal Philosophy.F. M. Kamm - 1993 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (4):331-348.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Self-defense, justification and excuse.Larry Alexander - 1993 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (1):53-66.
  • Political Liberalism.J. Rawls - 1995 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 57 (3):596-598.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2155 citations  
  • Aquinas on defensive killing: A case of double effect?Gregory M. Reichberg - 2005 - The Thomist 69 (3):341-370.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations