Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Mortal Questions.[author unknown] - 1979 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 43 (3):578-578.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   519 citations  
  • Kant's Empirical Realism.[author unknown] - 2005 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 195 (2):250-250.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Nonconceptual content and the "space of reasons".Richard G. Heck - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):483-523.
    In Mind and World, John McDowell argues against the view that perceptual representation is non-conceptual. The central worry is that this view cannot offer any reasonable account of how perception bears rationally upon belief. I argue that this worry, though sensible, can be met, if we are clear that perceptual representation is, though non-conceptual, still in some sense 'assertoric': Perception, like belief, represents things as being thus and so.
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   248 citations  
  • Analog Representation Beyond Mental Imagery.James Blachowicz - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (2):55-84.
  • Critical Notice.Michael Tye - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (1):245-247.
    In 1995, in my book, Ten Problems of Consciousness, I proposed a version of the theory of phenomenal consciousness now known as representationalism. The present book, in part, consists of a further development of that theory along with replies to common objections. It is also concerned with two prominent challenges for any reductive theory of consciousness: the explanatory gap and the knowledge argument. In addition, it connects representationalism with two more general issues: the nature of color and the location of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   397 citations  
  • The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. [REVIEW]Adam Morton - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3):727-730.
    I discuss Bermudez' minimalist approach to self-consciousness approvingly, connecting it with other positions in philosophy and trying to separate it from ideas about non-conceptual content.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes.Leslie Stevenson - 1970 - Philosophical Quarterly 20 (78):86.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • McDowell’s Hegelianism.Sally Sedgwick - 1997 - European Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):21–38.
  • Must conceptually informed perceptual experience involve nonconceptual content?Sonia Sedivy - 1996 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):413-31.
    The idea of nonconceptual contents proposes that there are mental contents at the level of the experiencing person that are individuated independently of ‘anything to do with the mind.’ Such contents are posited to meet a variety of theoretical and explanatory needs concerning concepts and conceptual mental contents which are individuated in terms having to do with the mind. So to examine the idea of nonconceptual content we need to examine whether we really need to posit such content and whether (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Nonconceptual content defended. [REVIEW]Christopher Peacocke - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):381-388.
  • Kant's Transcendental Psychology.Ralf Meerbote & Patricia Kitcher - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):862.
  • Perception, concepts, and memory.Michael G. F. Martin - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):745-63.
  • Defining 'intrinsic'.Rae Langton & David Lewis - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):333-345.
    Something could be round even if it were the only thing in the universe, unaccompanied by anything distinct from itself. Jaegwon Kim once suggested that we define an intrinsic property as one that can belong to something unaccompanied. Wrong: unaccompaniment itself is not intrinsic, yet it can belong to something unaccompanied. But there is a better Kim-style definition. Say that P is independent of accompaniment iff four different cases are possible: something accompanied may have P or lack P, something unaccompanied (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   204 citations  
  • The non-conceptual content of perceptual experience: Situation dependence and fineness of grain.Sean D. Kelly - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3):601-608.
    I begin by examining a recent debate between John McDowell and Christopher Peacocke over whether the content of perceptual experience is non-conceptual. Although I am sympathetic to Peacocke’s claim that perceptual content is non-conceptual, I suggest a number of ways in which his arguments fail to make that case. This failure stems from an over-emphasis on the "fine-grainedness" of perceptual content - a feature that is relatively unimportant to its non-conceptual structure. I go on to describe two other features of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Mind and World.Huw Price & John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical Books 38 (3):169-181.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1015 citations  
  • The inner and the outer: Kant's 'refutation' reconstructed.Robert Hanna - 2000 - Ratio 13 (2):146–174.
    In Skeptical idealism says that possibly nothing exists outside my own conscious mental states. Purported refutations of skeptical idealism – whether Descartes's, Locke's, Reid's, Kant's, Moore's, Putnam's, or Burge's – are philosophically scandalous: they have convinced no one. I argue (1) that what is wrong with the failed refutations is that they have attempted to prove the wrong thing – i.e., that necessarily I have veridical perceptions of distal material objects in space, and (2) that a charitable reconstruction of Kant's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Mathematics for humans: Kant's philosophy of arithmetic revisited.Robert Hanna - 2002 - European Journal of Philosophy 10 (3):328–352.
    In this essay I revisit Kant's much-criticized views on arithmetic. In so doing I make a case for the claim that his theory of arithmetic is not in fact subject to the most familiar and forceful objection against it, namely that his doctrine of the dependence of arithmetic on time is plainly false, or even worse, simply unintelligible; on the contrary, Kant's doctrine about time and arithmetic is highly original, fully intelligible, and with qualifications due to the inherent limitations of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • How do we know necessary truths? Kant's answer.Robert Hanna - 1998 - European Journal of Philosophy 6 (2):115–145.
    It is traditionally held that our knowledge of necessity is a priori; but the familiar theories of a priori knowledge – platonism and conventionalism – have now been discredited, and replaced by either modal skepticism or a posteriori essentialism. The main thesis of this paper is that Kant's theory of a priori knowledge, when detached from his transcendental idealism, offers a genuine alternative to these unpalatable options. According to Kant's doctrine, all epistemic necessity is grounded directly or indirectly on our (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Direct reference, direct perception, and the cognitive theory of demonstratives.Robert Hanna - 1993 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74 (2):96-117.
  • Seeing and Knowing.L. C. Holborow - 1971 - Philosophical Quarterly 21 (82):82-83.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • Knowledge and the flow of information.F. Dretske - 1989 - Trans/Form/Ação 12:133-139.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1374 citations  
  • Conscious experience.Fred Dretske - 1993 - Mind 102 (406):263-283.
  • The Modularity of Mind.Robert Cummins & Jerry Fodor - 1983 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):101.
  • Consciousness in Action.Jennifer Church & S. L. Hurley - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (3):465.
    Hurley’s is a difficult book to work through—partly because of its length and the complexity of its arguments, but also because each of the ten essays of which it is composed has a rather different starting point and focus, and because few of her arguments achieve real closure. Essay 2 discusses competing interpretations of Kant, essay 4 articulates nonconceptual forms of self-consciousness, essay 5 offers fresh interpretations of commissurotomy patients’ behavior, essay 6 develops an objection to Wittgenstein on rule following, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Idealism.Jill Vance Buroker - 1986 - Noûs 20 (4):577.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • Kant and the Mind.Pascal Engel - 1998 - Synthese 115 (3):375-393.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Varieties of Reference.Louise M. Antony - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (2):275.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1136 citations  
  • Lecture I.John McDowell - 1998 - Journal of Philosophy 95 (9):431-450.
  • Does perception have a nonconceptual content?Christopher Peacocke - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (5):239-264.
  • Nonconceptual mental content.Jose Luis Bermudez - 2003 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Concepts and Cognitive Science.Stephen Laurence & Eric Margolis - 1999 - In Eric Margolis & Stephen Laurence (eds.), Concepts: Core Readings. MIT Press. pp. 3-81.
    Given the fundamental role that concepts play in theories of cognition, philosophers and cognitive scientists have a common interest in concepts. Nonetheless, there is a great deal of controversy regarding what kinds of things concepts are, how they are structured, and how they are acquired. This chapter offers a detailed high-level overview and critical evaluation of the main theories of concepts and their motivations. Taking into account the various challenges that each theory faces, the chapter also presents a novel approach (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   241 citations  
  • Mortal Questions.Thomas Nagel - 1983 - Religious Studies 19 (1):96-99.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   450 citations  
  • Kant in the Twentieth Century.Robert Hanna - 2008 - In Routledge Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophy. pp. 150-203.
    Alfred North Whitehead (1861–1947) quotably wrote in 1929 that “the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.”1 The same could be said, perhaps with even greater accuracy, of the twentieth-century Euro-American philosophical tradition and Immanuel Kant (1724–1804).2 In this sense the twentieth century was the post-Kantian century. Twentieth-century philosophy in Europe and the USA was dominated by two distinctive and (after 1945) officially opposed traditions: the analytic tradition and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Imagination and perception.P. F. Strawson - 1982 - In Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker (ed.), Kant on Pure Reason. Oxford University Press.
  • Transcendental Arguments and Scepticism.Robert Stern - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (206):119-123.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • 1991.Wilfrid Sellars - 1963 - In Robert Colodny (ed.), Science, Perception, and Reality. Humanities Press/Ridgeview.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Emotion and force.York H. Gunther - 2003 - In Essays on Nonconceptual Content. MIT Press. pp. 279--88.
    Any satisfactory model of the emotions must at once recognize their place within intentional psychology and acknowledge their uniqueness as mental causes. In the first half of the century, the James-Lange model had considerable influence on reinforcing the idea that emotions are non-intentional (see Lange 1885 and James 1890). The uniqueness of emotions was therefore acknowledged at the price of denying them a place within intentional psychology proper. More recently, cognitive reductionists (including identity theorists) like Robert Solomon and Joel Marks (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations