Switch to: Citations

References in:

Paternalism and Rights

In Kalle Grill & Jason Hanna (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Paternalism. Routledge (2018)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.[author unknown] - 1925 - Mind 34 (135):365-369.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • On Liberty.John Stuart Mill - 1956 - Cambridge University Press.
    British philosopher and economist John Stuart Mill is the author of several essays, including Utilitarianism - a defence of Jeremy Bentham's principle applied to the field of ethics - and The Subjection of Women, which advocates legal equality between the sexes. This work, arguably his most famous contribution to political philosophy and theory, was first published in 1859, and remains a major influence upon contemporary liberal political thought. In it, Mill argues for a limitation of the power of government and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • The Bite of Rights in Paternalism.Norbert Paulo - 2015 - In Thomas Schramme (ed.), New Perspectives on Paternalism and Health Care. Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This paper scrutinizes the tension between individuals’ rights and paternalism. I will argue that no normative account that includes rights of individuals can justify hard paternalism since the infringement of a right can only be justified with the right or interest of another person, which is never the case in hard paternalism. Justifications of hard paternalistic actions generally include a deviation from the very idea of having rights. The paper first introduces Tom Beauchamp as the most famous contemporary hard paternalist (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Liberalism and paternalism.Russ Shafer-Landau - 2005 - Legal Theory 11 (3):169-191.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. [REVIEW]Walter B. Pitkin - 1912 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 9 (16):440-444.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Avoiding Paternalism.Peter De Marneffe - 2005 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (1):68 - 94.
  • Forced to be free? Increasing patient autonomy by constraining it.Neil Levy - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (5):293-300.
    It is universally accepted in bioethics that doctors and other medical professionals have an obligation to procure the informed consent of their patients. Informed consent is required because patients have the moral right to autonomy in furthering the pursuit of their most important goals. In the present work, it is argued that evidence from psychology shows that human beings are subject to a number of biases and limitations as reasoners, which can be expected to lower the quality of their decisions (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Paternalism, Respect and the Will.Daniel Groll - 2012 - Ethics 122 (4):692-720.
    In general, we think that when it comes to the good of another, we respect that person’s will by acting in accordance with what he wills because he wills it. I argue that this is not necessarily true. When it comes to the good of another person, it is possible to disrespect that person’s will while acting in accordance with what he wills because he wills it. Seeing how this is so, I argue, enables us to clarify the distinct roles (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Medical Paternalism - Part 1.Daniel Groll - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (3):194-203.
    Medical clinicians – doctors, nurses, nurse practitioners etc. – are charged to act for the good of their patients. But not all ways of acting for a patient's good are on par: some are paternalistic; others are not. What does it mean to act paternalistically, both in general and specifically in a medical context? And when, if ever, is it permissible for a clinician to act paternalistically? -/- This paper deals with the first question, with a special focus on paternalism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The normative core of paternalism.Kalle Grill - 2007 - Res Publica 13 (4):441-458.
    The philosophical debate on paternalism is conducted as if the property of being paternalistic should be attributed to actions. Actions are typically deemed to be paternalistic if they amount to some kind of interference with a person and if the rationale for the action is the good of the person interfered with. This focus on actions obscures the normative issues involved. In particular, it makes it hard to provide an analysis of the traditional liberal resistance to paternalism. Given the fact (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Paternalism.Gerald Dworkin - 1972 - The Monist 56 (1):64-84.
    I take as my starting point the “one very simple principle” proclaimed by Mill in On Liberty … “That principle is, that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • Avoiding Paternalism.Peter de Marneffe - 2005 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (1):68-94.
  • Paternalism.Jessica Begon - 2016 - Analysis 76 (3):355-373.
  • The Concept of Paternalism in Biomedical Ethics.Tom L. Beauchamp - 2009 - Jahrbuch für Wissenschaft Und Ethik 14 (1):77-92.
  • Joel Feinberg and the justification of hard paternalism.Richard J. Arneson - 2005 - Legal Theory 11 (3):259-284.
    Joel Feinberg was a brilliant philosopher whose work in social and moral philosophy is a legacy of excellent, even stunning achievement. Perhaps his most memorable achievement is his four-volume treatise on The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, and perhaps the most striking jewel in this crowning achievement is his passionate and deeply insightful treatment of paternalism.1 Feinberg opposes Legal Paternalism, the doctrine that “it is always a good reason in support of a [criminal law] prohibition that it is necessary (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • On Liberty.John Stuart Mill - 1859 - Broadview Press.
    Mill predicted that "[t]he Liberty is likely to survive longer than anything else that I have written...because the conjunction of [Harriet Taylor’s] mind with mine has rendered it a kind of philosophic text-book of a single truth, which the changes progressively taking place in modern society tend to bring out in ever greater relief." Indeed, On Liberty is one of the most influential books ever written, and remains a foundational document for the understanding of vital political, philosophical and social issues. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  • Paternalistic behavior.Bernard Gert & Charles M. Culver - 1976 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1):45-57.
  • Paternalism.Gerald Dworkin - 1972 - The Monist.
  • Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.É Duprat - 1922 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 93:156-157.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations