Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Besires and the Motivation Debate.Nick Zangwill - 2008 - Theoria 74 (1):50-59.
    Abstract: This article addresses a number of difficulties and complications in the standard formulations of motivational internalism, and considers what besires might be in the light of those difficulties and complications. Two notions of besire are then distinguished, before considering how different kinds of motivational internalism and different conceptions of besire fare against the significant argument that we may be indifferent to the demands of morality without irrationality.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Emotion and moral judgment.Linda Zagzebski - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (1):104–124.
    This paper argues that an emotion is a state of affectively perceiving its intentional object as falling under a "thick affective concept" A, a concept that combines cognitive and affective aspects in a way that cannot be pulled apart. For example, in a state of pity an object is seen as pitiful, where to see something as pitiful is to be in a state that is both cognitive and affective. One way of expressing an emotion is to assert that the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs.David Wiggins - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:61 - 85.
    David Wiggins; IV*—Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, P.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • IV*—Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs.David Wiggins - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1):61-86.
    David Wiggins; IV*—Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, P.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Humean and anti-Humean internalism about moral judgements.Mark Van Roojen - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1):26-49.
    Motivational internalism about moral judgments is the plausible view that accepting a moral judgment is necessarily connected to motivation motivation. However, it conflicts with the Humean theory that motives must be constituted by desires. Simple versions of internalism run into problems with people who do not desire to do what they believe right. This has long been urged by David Brink. Hence, many internalists have adopted more subtle defeasible views, on which only rational agents will have a desire to act. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Metaethical Internalism: Another Neglected Distinction.Jon Tresan - 2009 - The Journal of Ethics 13 (1):51-72.
    ‘Internalism’ is used in metaethics for a cluster of claims which bear a family resemblance. They tend to link, in some distinctive way—typically modal, mereological, or causal—different parts of the normative realm, or the normative and the psychological. The thesis of this paper is that much metaethical mischief has resulted from philosophers’ neglect of the distinction between two different features of such claims. The first is the modality of the entire claim. The second is the relation between the items specified (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Against direction of fit accounts of belief and desire.David Sobel & Copp - 2001 - Analysis 61 (1):44-53.
    The authors argue against direction of fit accounts of the distinction between belief and desire.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • The Humean theory of motivation.Michael Smith - 1987 - Mind 96 (381):36-61.
  • On Humeans, anti-Humeans, and motivation: A reply to Pettit.Michael Smith - 1988 - Mind 97 (388):589-595.
  • Pro-attitudes and direction of fit.G. F. Schueler - 1991 - Mind 100 (400):277-81.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Sensibility theory and conservative complancency.Peter W. Ross & Dale Turner - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (4):544–555.
    In Ruling Passions, Simon Blackburn contends that we should reject sensibility theory because it serves to support a conservative complacency. Blackburn's strategy is attractive in that it seeks to win this metaethical dispute – which ultimately stems from a deep disagreement over antireductionism – on the basis of an uncontroversial normative consideration. Therefore, Blackburn seems to offer an easy solution to an apparently intractable debate. We will show, however, that Blackburn's argument against sensibility theory does not succeed; it is no (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Explaining motivated desires.Peter W. Ross - 2002 - Topoi 21 (1-2):199-207.
    I examine a dispute about the nature of practical reason, and in particular moral reason, generated by Thomas Nagel's proposal of an internalist rationalism which claims we can explain motivation in terms of reason and belief alone. In opposition, Humeans contend that such explanations must also appeal to further desires. Arguments on either side of this debate typically assume that a rationalist or Humean conclusion can be reached independently of a claim about the nature of moral judgment. I'll maintain, to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Humean motivation and Humean rationality.Mark van Roojen - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 79 (1):37-57.
    Michael Smith's recent defence of the theory shows promise, in that it captures the most common reasons for accepting a Humean view. But, as I will argue, it falls short of vindicating the view. Smith's argument fails, because it ignores the role of rationality conditions on the ascription of motivating reason explanations. Because of these conditions, we must have a theory of rationality before we choose a theory of motivation. Thus, we cannot use Humean restrictions on motivation to argue for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Defending desire-as-belief.Huw Price - 1989 - Mind 98 (January):119-27.
  • Humeans, anti-Humeans, and motivation.Philip Pettit - 1987 - Mind 96 (384):530-533.
    In 'The Humean Theory of Motivation' Michael Smith attempts two tasks: he offers an account of the debate about motivation between Humeans and anti-Humeans and he provides arguments that are designed to show that the Humeans win. While the paper is of great virtue in clarifying the debate, I believe that it falls short of both its goals. It does not highlight the really central issue between Humeans and anti-Humeans and it does not provide arguments which would settle that issue (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Bare functional desire.Philip Pettit & Huw Price - 1989 - Analysis 49 (4):162-69.
    The purpose of this paper is to sound two notes of caution about a beguiling argument for the negative answer: for the Humean view that desires cannot be beliefs, or cognitive states more generally.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Pushmi-pullyu representations.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1995 - Philosophical Perspectives 9:185-200.
    A list of groceries, Professor Anscombe once suggested, might be used as a shopping list, telling what to buy, or it might be used as an inventory list, telling what has been bought (Anscombe 1957). If used as a shopping list, the world is supposed to conform to the representation: if the list does not match what is in the grocery bag, it is what is in the bag that is at fault. But if used as an inventory list, the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  • Motivation in agents.Christian Miller - 2008 - Noûs 42 (2):222–266.
    The Humean theory of motivation remains the default position in much of the contemporary literature in meta-ethics, moral psychology, and action theory. Yet despite its widespread support, the theory is implausible as a view about what motivates agents to act. More specifically, my reasons for dissatisfaction with the Humean theory stem from its incompatibility with what I take to be a compelling model of the role of motivating reasons in first-person practical deliberation and third-person action explanations. So after first introducing (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • In a Fitter Direction: Moving Beyond the Direction of Fit Picture of Belief and Desire.John Milliken - 2008 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (5):563-571.
    Those working within the tradition of Humean psychology tend to mark a clear distinction between beliefs and desires. One prominent way of elucidating this distinction is to describe them as having different “directions of fit” with respect to the world. After first giving a brief overview of the various attempts to carry out this strategy along with their flaws, I argue that the direction of fit metaphor is misleading and ought to be abandoned. It fails to take into account the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Virtue and Reason.John Mcdowell - 1979 - The Monist 62 (3):331-350.
    1. Presumably the point of, say, inculcating a moral outlook lies in a concern with how people live. It may seem that the very idea of a moral outlook makes room for, and requires, the existence of moral theory, conceived as a discipline which seeks to formulate acceptable principles of conduct. It is then natural to think of ethics as a branch of philosophy related to moral theory, so conceived, rather as the philosophy of science is related to science. On (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   566 citations  
  • Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?John McDowell & I. G. McFetridge - 1978 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 52 (1):13-42.
  • Virtue as knowledge: Objections from the philosophy of mind.Margaret Olivia Little - 1997 - Noûs 31 (1):59-79.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Desire as belief.David Lewis - 1988 - Mind 97 (418):323-32.
    Argues for the humean theory of motivation on the grounds that rejecting it requires rejecting decision theory.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Desire as belief II.David K. Lewis - 1996 - Mind 105 (418):303-13.
  • Direction of fit.I. Lloyd Humberstone - 1992 - Mind 101 (401):59-83.
  • Weakness of will and divisions of the mind.Edmund Henden - 2004 - European Journal of Philosophy 12 (2):199–213.
    Some authors have argued that, in order to give an account of weakness of the will, we must assume that the mind is divisible into parts. This claim is often referred to as the partitioning claim. There appear to be two main arguments for this claim. While the first is conceptual and claims that the notion of divisibility is entailed by the notion of non-rational mental causation (which is held to be a necessary condition of weakness of the will), the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Pro-Attitudes and Direction of Fit.G. F. Schueler - 1991 - Mind 100 (2):277 - 281.
  • Ethical Internalism and Cognitive Theories of Motivation.Allen Coates - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 129 (2):295-315.
    Cognitive internalism is the view that moral judgments are both cognitive and motivating. Philosophers have found cognitive internalism to be attractive in part because it seems to offer support for the idea that moral reasons are categorical, that is, independent of agents’ desires. In this paper, I argue that it offers no such support.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Belief attribution and the falsification of motive internalism.Michael Cholbi - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (5):607 – 616.
    The metatethical position known as motive internalism (MI) holds that moral beliefs are necessarily motivating. Adina Roskies (in Philosophical Psychology, 16) has recently argued against MI by citing patients with injuries to the ventromedial (VM) cortex as counterexamples to MI. Roskies claims that not only do these patients not act in accordance with their professed moral beliefs, they exhibit no physiological or affective evidence of being motivated by these beliefs. I argue that Roskies' attempt to falsify MI is unpersuasive because (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Moral motivation.David O. Brink - 1997 - Ethics 108 (1):4-32.
  • Moral judgment purposivism: saving internalism from amoralism.M. S. Bedke - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 144 (2):189-209.
    Consider orthodox motivational judgment internalism: necessarily, A’s sincere moral judgment that he or she ought to φ motivates A to φ. Such principles fail because they cannot accommodate the amoralist, or one who renders moral judgments without any corresponding motivation. The orthodox alternative, externalism, posits only contingent relations between moral judgment and motivation. In response I first revive conceptual internalism by offering some modifications on the amoralist case to show that certain community-wide motivational failures are not conceptually possible. Second, I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Moral Cognitivism and Motivation.Sigrun Svavarsdóttir - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (2):161-219.
    The impact moral judgments have on our deliberations and actions seems to vary a great deal. Moral judgments play a large part in the lives of some people, who are apt not only to make them, but also to be guided by them in the sense that they tend to pursue what they judge to be of moral value, and shun what they judge to be of moral disvalue. But it seems unrealistic to claim that moral judgments play a pervasive (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • External reasons.Philip Pettit & Michael Smith - 2006 - In Cynthia Macdonald & Graham Macdonald (eds.), Mcdowell and His Critics. Blackwell. pp. 6--142.
  • Desire as Belief.David K. Lewis - 1988 - Mind 97 (387):323-332.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Desire-as-Belief Revisited.Richard Bradley & Christian List - manuscript
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Desire-as-Belief Revisited.Richard Bradley & Christian List - manuscript
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Legacy of Emotivism.J. E. J. Altham - 1986 - In Graham Frank Macdonald & Crispin Wright (eds.), Fact, science and morality: essays on A.J. Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. pp. 275-288.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Belief, Desire, and Revision.John Collins - 1988 - Mind 97 (387):333 - 342.
  • Belief, Desire and Motivation: An Essay in Quasi-Hydraulics.James Lenman - 1996 - American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (3):291-301.
    My concern here is with the Humean claim that no purely cognitive state could, in combination with appropriate other beliefs, but with nothing else, originate a process of rational motivation. The starting point of such motivation must always include some other element: a desire. Let's call this claim, following David McNaughton the belief-desire theory, or BDT for short. The theory is widely believed but intensely controversial. I argue here that it is true.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations