Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Poincaré's Conventionalism of Applied Geometry.F. P. O'Gorman - 1977 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 8 (4):303.
  • Poincarés philosophy of geometry, or does geometric conventionalism deserve its name?E. G. Zahar - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28 (2):183-218.
  • Poincarés philosophy of geometry, or does geometric conventionalism deserve its name?E. G. Zahar - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28 (2):183-218.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Poincaré's thesis of the translatability of euclidean and non-euclidean geometries.David Stump - 1991 - Noûs 25 (5):639-657.
    Poincaré's claim that Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries are translatable has generally been thought to be based on his introduction of a model to prove the consistency of Lobachevskian geometry and to be equivalent to a claim that Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries are logically isomorphic axiomatic systems. In contrast to the standard view, I argue that Poincaré's translation thesis has a mathematical, rather than a meta-mathematical basis. The mathematical basis of Poincaré's translation thesis is that the underlying manifolds of Euclidean and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Henri Poincaré's philosophy of science.David Stump - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (3):335-363.
    Poincare’s arguments for his thesis of the conventionality of metric depend on a relationalist program for dynamics, not on any general philosophical interpretation of science. I will sketch Poincare’s development of the relationalist program and show that his arguments for the conventionality of metric do not depend on any global strategies such as a general empiricism or Duhemian underdetermination arguments. Poincare’s theory of space, while empirically false, is more philosophically sophisticated than his critics have claimed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Husserl's Phenomenology and Weyl's Predictivism.Jairo José Da Silva - 1997 - Synthese 110 (2):277 - 296.
    In this paper I discuss the version of predicative analysis put forward by Hermann Weyl in "Das Kontinuum". I try to establish how much of the underlying motivation for Weyl's position may be due to his acceptance of a phenomenological philosophical perspective. More specifically, I analyze Weyl's philosophical ideas in connexion with the work of Husserl, in particular "Logische Untersuchungen" and "Ideen I". I believe that this interpretation of Weyl can clarify the views on mathematical existence and mathematical intuition which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the Foundations of Geometry.Henri Poincaré - 1898 - The Monist 9 (1):1-43.
  • Poincaré: Mathematics & logic & intuition.Colin Mclarty - 1997 - Philosophia Mathematica 5 (2):97-115.
    often insisted existence in mathematics means logical consistency, and formal logic is the sole guarantor of rigor. The paper joins this to his view of intuition and his own mathematics. It looks at predicativity and the infinite, Poincaré's early endorsement of the axiom of choice, and Cantor's set theory versus Zermelo's axioms. Poincaré discussed constructivism sympathetically only once, a few months before his death, and conspicuously avoided committing himself. We end with Poincaré on Couturat, Russell, and Hilbert.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The problem of the invariance of dimension in the growth of modern topology, part II.Dale M. Johnson - 1981 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 25 (2-3):85-266.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Poincaré against the logicians.Michael Detlefsen - 1992 - Synthese 90 (3):349 - 378.
    Poincaré was a persistent critic of logicism. Unlike most critics of logicism, however, he did not focus his attention on the basic laws of the logicists or the question of their genuinely logical status. Instead, he directed his remarks against the place accorded to logical inference in the logicist's conception of mathematical proof. Following Leibniz, traditional logicist dogma (and this is explicit in Frege) has held that reasoning or inference is everywhere the same — that there are no principles of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Husserl's Phenomenology and Weyl's Predictivism.Jairo José Da Silva - 1997 - Synthese 110 (2):277-296.
    In this paper I discuss the version of predicative analysis put forward by Hermann Weyl in Das Kontinuum. I try to establish how much of the underlying motivation for Weyl's position may be due to his acceptance of a phenomenological philosophical perspective. More specifically, I analyze Weyl's philosophical ideas in connexion with the work of Husserl, in particular Logische Untersuchungen} and Ideen.I believe that this interpretation of Weyl can clarify the views on mathematical existence and mathematical intuition which are implicit (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Conventionalism in geometry and the interpretation of necessary statements.Max Black - 1942 - Philosophy of Science 9 (4):335-349.
    The statements traditionally labelled “necessary,” among them the valid theorems of mathematics and logic, are identified as “those whose truth is independent of experience.” The “truth” of a necessary statement has to be independent of the truth or falsity of experiential statements; a necessary statement can be neither confirmed nor refuted by empirical tests.The admission of genuinely necessary statements presents the empiricist with a troublesome problem. For an empiricist may be defined, in terms of the current idiom, as one who (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Space and Geometry.Henri Poincaré - forthcoming - Foundations of Science.