Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Language of Thought.Jerry A. Fodor - 1975 - Harvard University Press.
    INTRODUCTION: TWO KINDS OF RLDUCTIONISM The man who laughs is the one who has not yet heard the terrible news. BERTHOLD BRECHT I propose, in this book, ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1648 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. Quine - 1951 - [Longmans, Green].
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1206 citations  
  • The Cognizer's Innards: A Psychological and Philosophical Perspective on the Development of Thought.Andy Clark & Annette Karmiloff-Smith - 1991 - School of Cognitive and Computing Sciences, University of Sussex.
    We show that a popular class of connectionist models (which we label 'first order connectionism') looks unlikely to provide the kind of resources required by the hypothesis. We examine some alternative hybrid models that seem more promising. Finally, we raise a more purely philosophical issue concerning the conditions under which a being can count as a genuine believer or cognizer.".
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Incidentally, things in general are particularly determined: An episodic-processing account of implicit learning.Bruce W. Whittlesea & Michael D. Dorken - 1993 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 122 (2):227.
  • Individuals.P. F. Strawson - 1959 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 14 (2):246-246.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   880 citations  
  • Memory and the hippocampus: A synthesis from findings with rats, monkeys, and humans.Larry R. Squire - 1992 - Psychological Review 99 (2):195-231.
  • "Memory and the hippocampus: A synthesis from findings with rats, monkeys, and humans": Correction.Larry R. Squire - 1992 - Psychological Review 99 (3):582-582.
  • Intuitive and reflective beliefs.Dan Sperber - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):67-83.
    Humans have two kinds of beliefs, intuitive beliefs and reflective beliefs. Intuitive beliefs are a most fundamental category of cognition, defined in the architecture of the mind. They are formulated in an intuitive mental lexicon. Humans are also capable of entertaining an indefinite variety of higher-order or "reflective" propositional attitudes, many of which are of a credal sort. Reasons to hold "reflective beliefs" are provided by other beliefs that describe the source of the reflective belief as reliable, or that provide (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • Intuitive and Reflective Beliefs.Dan Sperber - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):67-83.
    Humans have two kinds of beliefs, intuitive beliefs and reflective beliefs. Intuitive beliefs are a fundamental category of cognition, defined in the architecture of the mind. They are formulated in an intuitive mental lexicon. Humans are also capable of entertaining an indefinite variety of higher‐order or‘reflective’propositional attitudes, many of which are of a credat sort. Reasons to hold reflective beliefs are provided by other beliefs that describe the source of the reflective belief as reliable, or that provide an explicit argument (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Explaining Culture: A Naturalistic Approach.Dan Sperber - 1996 - Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
  • Explaining Culture: A Naturalistic Approach.K. Sterelny - 1996 - Mind 110 (439):845-854.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   258 citations  
  • The empirical case for two systems of reasoning.Steven A. Sloman - 1996 - Psychological Bulletin 119 (1):3-22.
    Distinctions have been proposed between systems of reasoning for centuries. This article distills properties shared by many of these distinctions and characterizes the resulting systems in light of recent findings and theoretical developments. One system is associative because its computations reflect similarity structure and relations of temporal contiguity. The other is "rule based" because it operates on symbolic structures that have logical content and variables and because its computations have the properties that are normally assigned to rules. The systems serve (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   458 citations  
  • Characteristics of dissociable human learning systems.David R. Shanks & Mark F. St John - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):367-447.
    A number of ways of taxonomizing human learning have been proposed. We examine the evidence for one such proposal, namely, that there exist independent explicit and implicit learning systems. This combines two further distinctions, (1) between learning that takes place with versus without concurrent awareness, and (2) between learning that involves the encoding of instances (or fragments) versus the induction of abstract rules or hypotheses. Implicit learning is assumed to involve unconscious rule learning. We examine the evidence for implicit learning (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  • Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World.Wesley C. Salmon - 1984 - Princeton University Press.
    The philosophical theory of scientific explanation proposed here involves a radically new treatment of causality that accords with the pervasively statistical character of contemporary science. Wesley C. Salmon describes three fundamental conceptions of scientific explanation--the epistemic, modal, and ontic. He argues that the prevailing view is untenable and that the modal conception is scientifically out-dated. Significantly revising aspects of his earlier work, he defends a causal/mechanical theory that is a version of the ontic conception. Professor Salmon's theory furnishes a robust (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1037 citations  
  • Two concepts of consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 49 (May):329-59.
    No mental phenomenon is more central than consciousness to an adequate understanding of the mind. Nor does any mental phenomenon seem more stubbornly to resist theoretical treatment. Consciousness is so basic to the way we think about the mind that it can be tempting to suppose that no mental states exist that are not conscious states. Indeed, it may even seem mysterious what sort of thing a mental state might be if it is not a conscious state. On this way (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   517 citations  
  • Implicit short-lived motor representations of space in brain damaged and healthy subjects.Yves Rossetti - 1998 - Consciousness and Cognition 7 (3):520-558.
    This article reviews experimental evidence for a specific sensorimotor function which can be dissociated from higher level representations of space. It attempts to delineate this function on the basis of results obtained by psychophysical experiments performed with brain damaged and healthy subjects. Eye and hand movement control exhibit automatic features, such that they are incompatible with conscious control. In addition, they rely on a reference frame different from the one used by conscious perception. Neuropsychological cases provide a strong support for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • On the inter-relatedness of theory and measurement in the study of unconscious processes.Eyal M. Reingold & Philip M. Merikle - 1990 - Mind and Language 5 (1):9-28.
  • Implicit learning and tacit knowledge.Arthur S. Reber - 1989 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 118 (3):219-235.
    I examine the phenomenon of implicit learning, the process by which knowledge about the rule-governed complexities of the stimulus environment is acquired independently of conscious attempts to do so. Our research with the two seemingly disparate experimental paradigms of synthetic grammar learning and probability learning, is reviewed and integrated with other approaches to the general problem of unconscious cognition. The conclusions reached are as follows: Implicit learning produces a tacit knowledge base that is abstract and representative of the structure of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   321 citations  
  • Connectionism and the Mind: an Introduction to Parallel Processing in Networks.David Pickles, William Bechtel & Adele Abrahamson - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (166):101.
  • Thought without Representation.John Perry & Simon Blackburn - 1986 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 60 (1):137-166.
  • A connectionist theory of phenomenal experience.Jonathan Opie & Gerard O'Brien - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (1):127-148.
    When cognitive scientists apply computational theory to the problem of phenomenal consciousness, as many of them have been doing recently, there are two fundamentally distinct approaches available. Either consciousness is to be explained in terms of the nature of the representational vehicles the brain deploys; or it is to be explained in terms of the computational processes defined over these vehicles. We call versions of these two approaches _vehicle_ and _process_ theories of consciousness, respectively. However, while there may be space (...)
    Direct download (16 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The Perception of the Visual World.Norman Malcolm - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (4):594.
  • The Nature of Mind and Other Essays.William G. Lycan - 1983 - Philosophical Review 92 (3):471.
  • Pretending and believing: issues in the theory of ToMM.Alan M. Leslie - 1994 - Cognition 50 (1-3):211-238.
  • Pretense and representation: The origins of "theory of mind.".Alan M. Leslie - 1987 - Psychological Review 94 (4):412-426.
  • Attention, awareness, and the triangular circuit.David LaBerge - 1997 - Consciousness and Cognition 9 (2-3):149-81.
    It is proposed that attention to an object requires the simultaneous activity of three brain regions that are interconnected by a triangular circuit. The regions are the cortical site of attentional expression, the thalamic enhancement structure, and the prefrontal area of control. It is also proposed that awareness of an object requires the additional component of attention directed to a representation of the self. The expression of attention to a self-representation may involve activations of cortical sites corresponding to the body (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Some Varieties of Thinking.Wolfgang Künne - 1995 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 50 (1):365-395.
    The first half of the paper reflects on a couple of folk-psychological notions. "Belief and "judgement" are selected for special attention. They cover two varieties of thinking, a mental state and a mental act. Both lay claim to truth, and thereby stand in marked contrast to their nowadays sadly neglected non-committal counterparts. Meinong, of course, did not neglect them, and his notions of "Annehmen (merely entertaining a thought)" and "Denken (entertaining a thought)" play a decisive role in the paper. - (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Some Varieties of Thinking.Wolfgang Künne - 1995 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 50 (1):365-395.
    The first half of the paper reflects on a couple of folk-psychological notions. "Belief and "judgement" are selected for special attention. They cover two varieties of thinking, a mental state and a mental act. Both lay claim to truth, and thereby stand in marked contrast to their nowadays sadly neglected non-committal counterparts. Meinong, of course, did not neglect them, and his notions of "Annehmen (merely entertaining a thought)" and "Denken (entertaining a thought)" play a decisive role in the paper. - (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Consciousness and Concepts.Robert Kirk & Peter Carruthers - 1992 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 66 (1):23-60.
  • From meta-processes to conscious access: Evidence from children's metalinguistic and repair data.Annette Karmiloff-Smith - 1986 - Cognition 23 (2):95-147.
  • Nonconceptual Content: From Perceptual Experience to Subpersonal Computational States.José Luis Bermúdez - 1995 - Mind and Language 10 (4):333-369.
    Philosophers have often argued that ascriptions of content are appropriate only to the personal level states of folk psychology. Against this, this paper defends the view that the familiar propositional attitudes and states defined over them are part of a larger set of cognitive proceses that do not make constitutive reference to concept possession. It does this by showing that states with nonconceptual content exist both in perceptual experience and in subpersonal information-processing systems. What makes these states content-involving is their (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Semantic activation without conscious identification in dichotic listening, parafoveal vision, and visual masking: A survey and appraisal.Daniel Holender - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):1-23.
    When the stored representation of the meaning of a stimulus is accessed through the processing of a sensory input it is maintained in an activated state for a certain amount of time that allows for further processing. This semantic activation is generally accompanied by conscious identification, which can be demonstrated by the ability of a person to perform discriminations on the basis of the meaning of the stimulus. The idea that a sensory input can give rise to semantic activation without (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   447 citations  
  • Confirmation, disconfirmation, and invention: The case of Alexander Graham bell and the telephone.Michael E. Gorman - 1995 - Thinking and Reasoning 1 (1):31 – 53.
  • How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):1-14.
  • Transitions in concept acquisition: Using the hand to read the mind.Susan Goldin-Meadow, Martha Wagner Alibali & R. Breckinridge Church - 1993 - Psychological Review 100 (2):279-297.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • The Perception Of The Visual World.James J. Gibson - 1950 - Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
  • The modularity of mind. [REVIEW]Robert Cummins - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):101-108.
  • The Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology.Jerry A. Fodor - 1983 - MIT Press.
    One of the most notable aspects of Fodor's work is that it articulates features not only of speculative cognitive architectures but also of current research in ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   463 citations  
  • Propositional attitudes.Jerry Fodor - 1978 - The Monist 61 (October):501-23.
    Some philosophers hold that philosophy is what you do to a problem until it’s clear enough to solve it by doing science. Others hold that if a philosophical problem succumbs to empirical methods, that shows it wasn’t really philosophical to begin with. Either way, the facts seem clear enough: questions first mooted by philosophers are sometimes coopted by people who do experiments. This seems to be happening now to the question: “what are propositional attitudes?” and cognitive psychology is the science (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Propositional Attitudes.J. A. Fodor - 1978 - The Monist 61 (4):501-523.
    Some philosophers hold that philosophy is what you do to a problem until it’s clear enough to solve it by doing science. Others hold that if a philosophical problem succumbs to empirical methods, that shows it wasn’t really philosophical to begin with. Either way, the facts seem clear enough: questions first mooted by philosophers are sometimes coopted by people who do experiments. This seems to be happening now to the question: “what are propositional attitudes?” and cognitive psychology is the science (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • A situated grandmother? Some remarks on proposals by Barwise and Perry.Jerry A. Fodor - 1987 - Mind and Language 2 (1):64-81.
  • A Situated Grandmother? Some Remarks on Proposals by Barwise and Perry.J. A. Fodor - 1987 - Mind and Language 2 (1):64-81.
  • Mental representation.Hartry Field - 1978 - Erkenntnis 13 (July):9-61.
  • Identity and predication.Gareth Evans - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (13):343-363.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Discrimination and learning without awareness: A metholodological survey and evaluation.Charles W. Eriksen - 1960 - Psychological Review 67 (5):279-300.
  • Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes.Fred Dretske - 1988 - MIT Press.
    In this lucid portrayal of human behavior, Fred Dretske provides an original account of the way reasons function in the causal explanation of behavior.
  • Explaining Behaviour: Reasons in a World of Causes.Andy Clark - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (158):95-102.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   535 citations  
  • Connectionist and Memory‐Array Models of Artificial Grammar Learning.Zoltan Dienes - 1992 - Cognitive Science 16 (1):41-79.
    Subjects exposed to strings of letters generated by a finite state grammar can later classify grammatical and nongrammatical test strings, even though they cannot adequately say what the rules of the grammar are (e.g., Reber, 1989). The MINERVA 2 (Hintzman, 1986) and Medin and Schaffer (1978) memory‐array models and a number of connectionist outoassociator models are tested against experimental data by deriving mainly parameter‐free predictions from the models of the rank order of classification difficulty of test strings. The importance of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Brainstorms.Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - MIT Press.
    This collection of 17 essays by the author offers a comprehensive theory of mind, encompassing traditional issues of consciousness and free will.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1093 citations  
  • Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
    What is the relation between a reason and an action when the reason explains the action by giving the agent's reason for doing what he did? We may call such explanations rationalizations, and say that the reason rationalizes the action. In this paper I want to defend the ancient - and common-sense - position that rationalization is a species of ordinary causal explanation. The defense no doubt requires some redeployment, but not more or less complete abandonment of the position, as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1248 citations