Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation.Seana Valentine Shiffrin - 2000 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (3):205-250.
    The unconscionability doctrine in contract law enables a court to decline to enforce a contract whose terms are seriously one-sided, exploitative, or otherwise manifestly unfair. It is often criticized for being paternalist. The essay argues that the characterization of unconscionability doctrine as paternalist reflects common but misleading thought about paternalism and obscures more important issues about autonomy and social connection. The defense responds to another criticism: that unconscionability doctrine is an inappropriate, because economically inefficient, egalitarian tool. The final part discusses (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   162 citations  
  • In defense of hard paternalism.Danny Scoccia - 2008 - Law and Philosophy 27 (4):351 - 381.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The Problem of Paternal Motives.Chris Mills - 2013 - Utilitas 25 (4):446-462.
    In this article I assess the ability of motivational accounts of paternalism to respond to a particular challenge: can its proponents adequately explain the source of the distinctive form of disrespect that animates this view? In particular I examine the recent argument put forward by Jonathan Quong that we can explain the presumptive wrong of paternalism by relying on a Rawlsian account of moral status. I challenge the plausibility of Quong's argument, claiming that although this approach can provide a clear (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Avoiding Paternalism.Peter De Marneffe - 2005 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (1):68 - 94.
  • Why Value Autonomy?Thomas Hurka - 1987 - Social Theory and Practice 13 (3):361-382.
  • Legal Paternalism.Joel Feinberg - 1971 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):105 - 124.
    The principle of legal paternalism justifies state coercion to protect individuals from self-inflicted harm, or in its extreme version, to guide them, whether they like it or not, toward their own good. Parents can be expected to justify their interference in the lives of their children on the ground that “daddy knows best.” legal paternalism seems to imply that since the state often can know the interests of individual citizens better than the citizens know them themselves, it stands as a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Hypothetical Consent and the Value (s) of Autonomy.David Enoch - 2017 - Ethics 128 (1):6-36.
    Hypothetical consent is puzzling. On the one hand, it seems to make a moral difference across a wide range of cases. On the other hand, there seem to be principled reasons to think that it cannot. In this article I put forward reasonably precise formulations of these general suspicions regarding hypothetical consent; I draw several distinctions regarding the ways in which hypothetical consent may make a moral difference; I distinguish between two autonomy-related concerns, nonalienation and sovereignty; and, utilizing these distinctions, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • The Concept of Autonomy.Gerald Dworkin - 1981 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 12 (1):203-213.
    In both theoretical and applied contexts the concept of autonomy has assumed increasing importance in recent normative philosophical discussion. Given various problems to be clarified or resolved the author characterizes the concept by first setting out conditions of adequacy. The author then links the notion of autonomy to the identification and critical reflection of an agent upon his first-order motivations. It is only when a person identifies with the influences that motivate him, assimilates them to himself, that he is autonomous. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The Concept of Autonomy.Gerald Dworkin - 1981 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 12 (1):203-213.
    In both theoretical and applied contexts the concept of autonomy has assumed increasing importance in recent normative philosophical discussion. Given various problems to be clarified or resolved the author characterizes the concept by first setting out conditions of adequacy. The author then links the notion of autonomy to the identification and critical reflection of an agent upon his first-order motivations. It is only when a person identifies with the influences that motivate him, assimilates them to himself, that he is autonomous. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Avoiding Paternalism.Peter de Marneffe - 2005 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (1):68-94.
  • Paternalism.Jessica Begon - 2016 - Analysis 76 (3):355-373.
  • Voluntary Obligation and Contract.Aditi Bagchi - 2019 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 20 (2):433-455.
    Absent mistake or misrepresentation, most scholars assume that parties who agree to contract do so voluntarily. Scholars tend further to regard that choice as an important exercise in moral agency. Hanoch Dagan and Michael Heller are right to question the quality of our choices. Where the fundamental contours of the transaction are legally determined, parties have little opportunity to exercise autonomous choice over the terms on which they deal with others. To the extent that our choices in contract do not (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Autonomy in moral and political philosophy.John Christman - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • A Third Theory of Paternalism.Nicolas Cornell - 2015 - Michigan Law Review 113:1295-1336.