Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Coordinatisation and canonical bases in simple theories.Bradd Hart, Byunghan Kim & Anand Pillay - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (1):293-309.
    In this paper we discuss several generalization of theorems from stability theory to simple theories. Cherlin and Hrushovski, in [2] develop a substitute for canonical bases in finite rank, ω-categorical supersimple theories. Motivated by methods there, we prove the existence of canonical bases (in a suitable sense) for types in any simple theory. This is done in Section 2. In general these canonical bases will (as far as we know) exist only as “hyperimaginaries”, namely objects of the forma/Ewhereais a possibly (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Simple Theories.Frank O. Wagner - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (4):522-524.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Toward classifying unstable theories.Saharon Shelah - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 80 (3):229-255.
  • Classification Theory and the Number of Nonisomorphic Models.S. Shelah - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (3):694-696.
  • A rank for the class of elementary submodels of a superstable homogeneous model.Tapani Hyttinen & Olivier Lessmann - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (4):1469-1482.
    We study the class of elementary submodels of a large superstable homogeneous model. We introduce a rank which is bounded in the superstable case, and use it to define a dependence relation which shares many (but not all) of the properties of forking in the first order case. The main difference is that we do not have extension over all sets. We also present an example of Shelah showing that extension over all sets may not hold for any dependence relation (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A geometric introduction to forking and thorn-forking.Hans Adler - 2009 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 9 (1):1-20.
    A ternary relation [Formula: see text] between subsets of the big model of a complete first-order theory T is called an independence relation if it satisfies a certain set of axioms. The primary example is forking in a simple theory, but o-minimal theories are also known to have an interesting independence relation. Our approach in this paper is to treat independence relations as mathematical objects worth studying. The main application is a better understanding of thorn-forking, which turns out to be (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Thorn-forking in continuous logic.Clifton Ealy & Isaac Goldbring - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (1):63-93.
    We study thorn forking and rosiness in the context of continuous logic. We prove that the Urysohn sphere is rosy (with respect to finitary imaginaries), providing the first example of an essentially continuous unstable theory with a nice notion of independence. In the process, we show that a real rosy theory which has weak elimination of finitary imaginaries is rosy with respect to finitary imaginaries, a fact which is new even for discrete first-order real rosy theories.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Model theoretic properties of the Urysohn sphere.Gabriel Conant & Caroline Terry - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (1):49-72.
  • Distance structures for generalized metric spaces.Gabriel Conant - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (3):622-650.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A remark on strict independence relations.Gabriel Conant - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (3-4):535-544.
    We prove that if T is a complete theory with weak elimination of imaginaries, then there is an explicit bijection between strict independence relations for T and strict independence relations for Teq\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${T^{\rm eq}}$$\end{document}. We use this observation to show that if T is the theory of the Fraïssé limit of finite metric spaces with integer distances, then Teq\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${T^{\rm eq}}$$\end{document} has more than one (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Theories without the tree property of the second kind.Artem Chernikov - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (2):695-723.
    We initiate a systematic study of the class of theories without the tree property of the second kind — NTP2. Most importantly, we show: the burden is “sub-multiplicative” in arbitrary theories ; NTP2 is equivalent to the generalized Kimʼs lemma and to the boundedness of ist-weight; the dp-rank of a type in an arbitrary theory is witnessed by mutually indiscernible sequences of realizations of the type, after adding some parameters — so the dp-rank of a 1-type in any theory is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Fundamentals of Stability Theory.Anand Pillay - 1990 - Studia Logica 49 (4):608-609.