Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive: Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence, and the Methods of Scientific Investigation.John Stuart Mill - 1851 - London, England: Cambridge University Press.
    A foundational text in modern empiricist method, published in 1843 by Victorian England's foremost philosopher of political and social life.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  • A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive: Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence, and the Methods of Scientific Investigation.John Stuart Mill (ed.) - 1843 - London, England: Cambridge University Press.
    This two-volume work, first published in 1843, was John Stuart Mill's first major book. It reinvented the modern study of logic and laid the foundations for his later work in the areas of political economy, women's rights and representative government. In clear, systematic prose, Mill disentangles syllogistic logic from its origins in Aristotle and scholasticism and grounds it instead in processes of inductive reasoning. An important attempt at integrating empiricism within a more general theory of human knowledge, the work constitutes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • The guide for the perplexed.Moses Maimonides & Salomon Pines - 1904 - New York,: E. P. Dutton & co.. Edited by M. Friedländer.
    This superb abridgement and annotated translation of Maimonides' monumental work includes discussions of divine language, the scope and limits of human knowledge, cosmological doctrines concerning the creation or eternity of the world, prophecy and providence, the nature and purpose of divine law, and moral and political philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment.Alexander R. Pruss - 2006 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The Principle of Sufficient Reason says that all contingent facts must have explanation. In this 2006 volume, which was the first on the topic in the English language in nearly half a century, Alexander Pruss examines the substantive philosophical issues raised by the Principle Reason. Discussing various forms of the PSR and selected historical episodes, from Parmenides, Leibnez, and Hume, Pruss defends the claim that every true contingent proposition must have an explanation against major objections, including Hume's imaginability argument and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Simplicity or Priority?Gregory Fowler - 2013 - In L. Kvanvig Jonathan (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion. Oxford University Press. pp. 114-138.
    This chapter is a work in applied metaphysics. Recent discussions of monism and metaphysical dependence are deployed to develop a view—the doctrine of divine priority (DDP)—that is a viable alternative to the doctrine of divine simplicity (DDS). DDS and the traditional motivation for it are discussed, then DDP is introduced by way of an analogy involving Jonathan Schaffer’s distinction between two forms of monism. It is argued that DDP is an alternative to DDS by showing that it is consistent with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment.Alexander Pruss - 2007 - Religious Studies 43 (4):500-503.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Doing and Being: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta.Jonathan Beere - 2009 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Doing and Being confronts the problem of how to understand two central concepts of Aristotle's philosophy: energeia and dunamis. While these terms seem ambiguous between actuality/potentiality and activity/capacity, Aristotle did not intend them to be so. Through a careful and detailed reading of Metaphysics Theta, Beere argues that we can solve the problem by rejecting both "actuality" and "activity" as translations of energeia, and by working out an analogical conception of energeia. This approach enables Beere to discern a hitherto unnoticed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Anselmian Explorations: Essays in Philosophical Theology.David E. White - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (1):109.
  • The Nature of a Simple God.Eleonore Stump - 2013 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 87:33-42.
  • The least discerning and most promiscuous truthmaker.Jonathan Schaffer - 2010 - Philosophical Quarterly 60 (239):307 - 324.
    I argue that the one and only truthmaker is the world. This view can be seen as arisingfrom (i) the view that truthmaking is a relation of grounding holding between true propositions and fundamental entities, together with (ii) the view that the world is the one and only fundamental entity. I argue that this view provides an elegant and economical account of the truthmakers, while solving the problem of negative existentials, in a way that proves ontologically revealing.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   155 citations  
  • Monism: The Priority of the Whole.Jonathan Schaffer - 2010 - Philosophical Review 119 (1):31-76.
    Consider a circle and a pair of its semicircles. Which is prior, the whole or its parts? Are the semicircles dependent abstractions from their whole, or is the circle a derivative construction from its parts? Now in place of the circle consider the entire cosmos (the ultimate concrete whole), and in place of the pair of semicircles consider the myriad particles (the ultimate concrete parts). Which if either is ultimately prior, the one ultimate whole or its many ultimate parts?
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   643 citations  
  • Does God Have a Nature?William L. Rowe - 1983 - Philosophical Review 92 (2):305.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Perfect Being Theology.Rogers Katherin A. Rogers - 2019 - Edinburgh University Press.
    That being than which a greater cannot be conceived.' This was the way in which the living God of biblical tradition was described by the great Medieval philosophers such as Augustine, Anselm and Aquinas.Contemporary philosophers find much to question, criticise and reject in the traditional analysis of that description. Some hold that the attributes traditionally ascribed to God - simplicity, necessity, immutability, eternity, omniscience, omnipotence, creativity and goodness - are inherently incoherent individually, or mutually inconsistent. Others argue that the divinity (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Does God Have a Nature?William E. Mann - 1982 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 42 (4):625-630.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Does God Have a Nature?Alvin Plantinga - 1980 - Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.
    Sets of contingent objects, perhaps, are as contingent as their members; but properties, propositions, numbers and states of affairs, it seems, are objects whose non-existence is quite impossible. If so, however, how are they related to God? Suppose God has a nature: a property he has essentially that includes each property essential to him. Does God have a nature? And if he does, is there a conflict between God's sovereignty and his having a nature? How is God related to such (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Aristotle on Ontological Dependence.Phil Corkum - 2008 - Phronesis 53 (1):65 - 92.
    Aristotle holds that individual substances are ontologically independent from nonsubstances and universal substances but that non-substances and universal substances are ontologically dependent on substances. There is then an asymmetry between individual substances and other kinds of beings with respect to ontological dependence. Under what could plausibly be called the standard interpretation, the ontological independence ascribed to individual substances and denied of non-substances and universal substances is a capacity for independent existence. There is, however, a tension between this interpretation and the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Perfection, near-perfection, maximality, and Anselmian Theism.Graham Oppy - 2011 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 69 (2):119-138.
    Anselmian theists claim (a) that there is a being than which none greater can be conceived; and (b) that it is knowable on purely—solely, entirely—a priori grounds that there is a being than which none greater can be conceived. In this paper, I argue that Anselmian Theism gains traction by conflating different interpretations of the key description ‘being than which no greater can be conceived’. In particular, I insist that it is very important to distinguish between ideal excellence and maximal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Models of Anselmian Theism.Yujin Nagasawa - 2013 - Faith and Philosophy 30 (1):3-25.
    The so-called Anselmian thesis says that God is that than which no greater can be thought. This thesis has been widely accepted among traditional theists and it has for several hundred years been a central notion whenever philosophers debate the existence and nature of God. Proponents of the thesis are often silent, however, about exactly what it means to say that God is that than which no greater can be thought. The aim of this paper is to offer an answer (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A new defence of Anselmian theism.Yujin Nagasawa - 2008 - Philosophical Quarterly 58 (233):577-596.
    Anselmian theists, for whom God is the being than which no greater can be thought, usually infer that he is an omniscient, omnipotent and omnibenevolent being. Critics have attacked these claims by numerous distinct arguments, such as the paradox of the stone, the argument from God's inability to sin, and the argument from evil. Anselmian theists have responded to these arguments by constructing an independent response to each. This way of defending Anselmian theism is uneconomical. I seek to establish a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Anselmian Explorations: Essays in Philosophical Theology.Thomas V. Morris - 1987 - University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Anselmian Explorations: Essays in Philosophical Theology.Barry Miller - 1991 - Noûs 25 (2):238-241.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why perfect being theology?Brian Leftow - 2011 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 69 (2):103-118.
    I display the historical roots of perfect being theology in Greco-Roman philosophy, and the distinctive reasons for Christians to take up a version of this project. I also rebut a recent argument that perfect-being reasoning should lead one to atheism.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A Return to the Theory of the Verb be and the Concept of Being.Charles H. Kahn - 2004 - Ancient Philosophy 24 (2):381-405.
  • Ghazali and the Poetics of Imagination. [REVIEW]Muhammad Hozien - 2006 - Journal of Islamic Philosophy 2 (1):201-202.
  • Aristoteles Metaphysik Ζ.Michael Frede & Günther Patzig - 1988 - C. H. Beck.
  • A Map of Metaphysics Zeta.Myles Burnyeat - 2001 - Mathesis.
  • Plotinus. [REVIEW]John Bussanich - 1996 - The Classical Review 46 (2):275-277.
  • A Map of Metaphysics Zeta.Frank A. Lewis - 2004 - Mind 113 (449):158-164.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A Map of Metaphysics Zeta.Mary Louise Gill - 2005 - Philosophical Quarterly 55 (218):114-121.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Making Sense of Divine Simplicity.Jeffrey E. Brower - 2008 - Faith and Philosophy 25 (1):3-30.
    According to the doctrine of divine simplicity, God is an absolutely simple being lacking any distinct metaphysical parts, properties, or constituents. Although this doctrine was once an essential part of traditional philosophical theology, it is now widely rejected as incoherent. In this paper, I develop an interpretation of the doctrine designed to resolve contemporary concerns about its coherence, as well as to show precisely what is required to make sense of divine simplicity.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus.Lloyd P. Gerson (ed.) - 1996 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Each volume of this series of companions to major philosophers contains specially commissioned essays by an international team of scholars, together with a substantial bibliography, and will serve as a reference work for students and non-specialists. One aim of the series is to dispel the intimidation such readers often feel when faced with the work of a difficult and challenging thinker. Plotinus was the greatest philosopher in the 700-year period between Aristotle and Augustine. He thought of himself as a disciple (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Arabic Plotinus: a philosophical study of the theology of Aristotle.Peter Adamson - 2002 - London: Duckworth.
    The so-called "Theology of Aristotle" is a translation of the Enneads of Plotinus, the most important representative of late ancient Platonism. It was produced in the 9th century CE within the circle of al-Kindī, one of the most important groups for the early reception of Greek thought in Arabic. In part because the "Theology" was erroneously transmitted under Aristotle's authorship, it became the single most important conduit by which Neoplatonism reached the Islamic world. It is referred to by such thinkers (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Doing and being: an interpretation of Aristotle's Metaphysics theta.Jonathan B. Beere - 2009 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Doing and Being confronts the problem of how to understand two central concepts of Aristotle's philosophy: energeia and dunamis.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive.John Stuart Mill - 1843 - New York and London,: University of Toronto Press. Edited by J. Robson.
    Ethics and jurisprudence are liable to the remark in common with logic. Almost every writer having taken a different view of some of the particulars which ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   344 citations  
  • Plotinus. [REVIEW]John Bussanich - 1994 - Review of Metaphysics 47 (4):837-839.
  • Foundational Grounding and the Argument from Contingency.Kenneth L. Pearce - 2017 - Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 8.
    The argument from contingency for the existence of God is best understood as a request for an explanation of the total sequence of causes and effects in the universe (‘History’ for short). Many puzzles about how there could be such an explanation arise from the assumption that God is being introduced as one more cause prepended to the sequence of causes that (allegedly) needed explaining. In response to this difficulty, this chapter defends three theses. First, it argues that, if the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Ineffable, Inconceivable, and Incomprehensible God: Fundamentality and Apophatic Theology.Jonathan D. Jacobs - 2015 - Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 6:158-176.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus.Lloyd P. Gerson - 1996 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 61 (1):159-160.
    Each volume of this series of companions to major philosophers contains specially commissioned essays by an international team of scholars, together with a substantial bibliography, and will serve as a reference work for students and non-specialists. One aim of the series is to dispel the intimidation such readers often feel when faced with the work of a difficult and challenging thinker. Plotinus was the greatest philosopher in the 700-year period between Aristotle and Augustine. He thought of himself as a disciple (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A Map of Metaphysics Zeta.Myles Burnyeat - 2001 - In . Mathesis Publications.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • The Guide of the Perplexed.Moses Maimonides, S. Pines & L. Strauss - 1956 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 20 (3):366-367.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Anselmian Explorations. Essays in Philosophical Theology.Thomas V. Morris - 1989 - Religious Studies 25 (1):137-138.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The verb "to be" in greek philosophy.Lesley Brown - 1994 - In Stephen Everson (ed.), Language. Cambridge University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Anselm's perfect being theology.Brian Leftow - 2004 - In The Cambridge Companion to Anselm. Cambridge University Press. pp. 132--156.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations